đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș noam-chomsky-notes-on-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:58:23. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Notes on Anarchism Author: Noam Chomsky Date: 1970 Language: en Topics: philosophy Source: Retrieved on July 29, 2009 from http://www.zmag.org/znet/viewArticle/19611 Notes: This essay is a revised version of the introduction to Daniel GuĂ©rinâs Anarchism: From Theory to Practice. In a slightly different version, it appeared in the New York Review of Books, May 21, 1970. Transcribed by Bill Lear.
A French writer, sympathetic to anarchism, wrote in the 1890s that
âanarchism has a broad back, like paper it endures anythingâ â
including, he noted those whose acts are such that âa mortal enemy of
anarchism could not have done better.â[1] There have been many styles of
thought and action that have been referred to as âanarchist.â It would
be hopeless to try to encompass all of these conflicting tendencies in
some general theory or ideology. And even if we proceed to extract from
the history of libertarian thought a living, evolving tradition, as
Daniel Guérin does in Anarchism, it remains difficult to formulate its
doctrines as a specific and determinate theory of society and social
change. The anarchist historian Rudolph Rocker, who presents a
systematic conception of the development of anarchist thought towards
anarchosyndicalism, along lines that bear comparison to Guérins work,
puts the matter well when he writes that anarchism is not
a fixed, self-enclosed social system but rather a definite trend in the
historic development of mankind, which, in contrast with the
intellectual guardianship of all clerical and governmental institutions,
strives for the free unhindered unfolding of all the individual and
social forces in life. Even freedom is only a relative, not an absolute
concept, since it tends constantly to become broader and to affect wider
circles in more manifold ways. For the anarchist, freedom is not an
abstract philosophical concept, but the vital concrete possibility for
every human being to bring to full development all the powers,
capacities, and talents with which nature has endowed him, and turn them
to social account. The less this natural development of man is
influenced by ecclesiastical or political guardianship, the more
efficient and harmonious will human personality become, the more will it
become the measure of the intellectual culture of the society in which
it has grown.[2]
One might ask what value there is in studying a âdefinite trend in the
historic development of mankindâ that does not articulate a specific and
detailed social theory. Indeed, many commentators dismiss anarchism as
utopian, formless, primitive, or otherwise incompatible with the
realities of a complex society. One might, however, argue rather
differently: that at every stage of history our concern must be to
dismantle those forms of authority and oppression that survive from an
era when they might have been justified in terms of the need for
security or survival or economic development, but that now contribute to
â rather than alleviate â material and cultural deficit. If so, there
will be no doctrine of social change fixed for the present and future,
nor even, necessarily, a specific and unchanging concept of the goals
towards which social change should tend. Surely our understanding of the
nature of man or of the range of viable social forms is so rudimentary
that any far-reaching doctrine must be treated with great skepticism,
just as skepticism is in order when we hear that âhuman natureâ or âthe
demands of efficiencyâ or âthe complexity of modern lifeâ requires this
or that form of oppression and autocratic rule.
Nevertheless, at a particular time there is every reason to develop,
insofar as our understanding permits, a specific realization of this
definite trend in the historic development of mankind, appropriate to
the tasks of the moment. For Rocker, âthe problem that is set for our
time is that of freeing man from the curse of economic exploitation and
political and social enslavementâ; and the method is not the conquest
and exercise of state power, nor stultifying parliamentarianism, but
rather âto reconstruct the economic life of the peoples from the ground
up and build it up in the spirit of Socialism.â
But only the producers themselves are fitted for this task, since they
are the only value-creating element in society out of which a new future
can arise. Theirs must be the task of freeing labor from all the fetters
which economic exploitation has fastened on it, of freeing society from
all the institutions and procedure of political power, and of opening
the way to an alliance of free groups of men and women based on
co-operative labor and a planned administration of things in the
interest of the community. To prepare the toiling masses in the city and
country for this great goal and to bind them together as a militant
force is the objective of modern Anarcho-syndicalism, and in this its
whole purpose is exhausted. [P. 108]
As a socialist, Rocker would take for granted âthat the serious, final,
complete liberation of the workers is possible only upon one condition:
that of the appropriation of capital, that is, of raw material and all
the tools of labor, including land, by the whole body of the
workers.â[3] As an anarchosyndicalist, he insists, further, that the
workersâ organizations create ânot only the ideas, but also the facts of
the future itselfâ in the prerevolutionary period, that they embody in
themselves the structure of the future society â and he looks forward to
a social revolution that will dismantle the state apparatus as well as
expropriate the expropriators. âWhat we put in place of the government
is industrial organization.â
Anarcho-syndicalists are convinced that a Socialist economic order
cannot be created by the decrees and statutes of a government, but only
by the solidaric collaboration of the workers with hand and brain in
each special branch of production; that is, through the taking over of
the management of all plants by the producers themselves under such form
that the separate groups, plants, and branches of industry are
independent members of the general economic organism and systematically
carry on production and the distribution of the products in the interest
of the community on the basis of free mutual agreements. [p. 94]
Rocker was writing at a moment when such ideas had been put into
practice in a dramatic way in the Spanish Revolution. Just prior to the
outbreak of the revolution, the anarchosyndicalist economist Diego Abad
de Santillan had written:
...in facing the problem of social transformation, the Revolution cannot
consider the state as a medium, but must depend on the organization of
producers.
We have followed this norm and we find no need for the hypothesis of a
superior power to organized labor, in order to establish a new order of
things. We would thank anyone to point out to us what function, if any,
the State can have in an economic organization, where private property
has been abolished and in which parasitism and special privilege have no
place. The suppression of the State cannot be a languid affair; it must
be the task of the Revolution to finish with the State. Either the
Revolution gives social wealth to the producers in which case the
producers organize themselves for due collective distribution and the
State has nothing to do; or the Revolution does not give social wealth
to the producers, in which case the Revolution has been a lie and the
State would continue.
Our federal council of economy is not a political power but an economic
and administrative regulating power. It receives its orientation from
below and operates in accordance with the resolutions of the regional
and national assemblies. It is a liaison corps and nothing else.[4]
Engels, in a letter of 1883, expressed his disagreement with this
conception as follows:
The anarchists put the thing upside down. They declare that the
proletarian revolution must begin by doing away with the political
organization of the state....But to destroy it at such a moment would be
to destroy the only organism by means of which the victorious
proletariat can assert its newly-conquered power, hold down its
capitalist adversaries, and carry out that economic revolution of
society without which the whole victory must end in a new defeat and a
mass slaughter of the workers similar to those after the Paris
commune.[5]
In contrast, the anarchists â most eloquently Bakunin â warned of the
dangers of the âred bureaucracy,â which would prove to be âthe most vile
and terrible lie that our century has created.â[6] The
anarchosyndicalist Fernand Pelloutier asked: âMust even the transitory
state to which we have to submit necessarily and fatally be a
collectivist jail? Canât it consist in a free organization limited
exclusively by the needs of production and consumption, all political
institutions having disappeared?â[7]
I do not pretend to know the answers to this question. But it seems
clear that unless there is, in some form, a positive answer, the chances
for a truly democratic revolution that will achieve the humanistic
ideals of the left are not great. Martin Buber put the problem
succinctly when he wrote: âOne cannot in the nature of things expect a
little tree that has been turned into a club to put forth leaves.â[8]
The question of conquest or destruction of state power is what Bakunin
regarded as the primary issue dividing him from Marx.[9] In one form or
another, the problem has arisen repeatedly in the century since,
dividing âlibertarianâ from âauthoritarianâ socialists.
Despite Bakuninâs warnings about the red bureaucracy, and their
fulfillment under Stalinâs dictatorship, it would obviously be a gross
error in interpreting the debates of a century ago to rely on the claims
of contemporary social movements as to their historical origins. In
particular, it is perverse to regard Bolshevism as âMarxism in
practice.â Rather, the left-wing critique of Bolshevism, taking account
of the historical circumstances surrounding the Russian Revolution, is
far more to the point.[10]
The anti-Bolshevik, left-wing labor movement opposed the Leninists
because they did not go far enough in exploiting the Russian upheavals
for strictly proletarian ends. They became prisoners of their
environment and used the international radical movement to satisfy
specifically Russian needs, which soon became synonymous with the needs
of the Bolshevik Party-State. The âbourgeoisâ aspects of the Russian
Revolution were now discovered in Bolshevism itself: Leninism was
adjudged a part of international social-democracy, differing from the
latter only on tactical issues.[11]
If one were to seek a single leading idea within the anarchist
tradition, it should, I believe, be that expressed by Bakunin when, in
writing on the Paris Commune, he identified himself as follows:
I am a fanatic lover of liberty, considering it as the unique condition
under which intelligence, dignity and human happiness can develop and
grow; not the purely formal liberty conceded, measured out and regulated
by the State, an eternal lie which in reality represents nothing more
than the privilege of some founded on the slavery of the rest; not the
individualistic, egoistic, shabby, and fictitious liberty extolled by
the School of J.-J. Rousseau and other schools of bourgeois liberalism,
which considers the would-be rights of all men, represented by the State
which limits the rights of each â an idea that leads inevitably to the
reduction of the rights of each to zero. No, I mean the only kind of
liberty that is worthy of the name, liberty that consists in the full
development of all the material, intellectual and moral powers that are
latent in each person; liberty that recognizes no restrictions other
than those determined by the laws of our own individual nature, which
cannot properly be regarded as restrictions since these laws are not
imposed by any outside legislator beside or above us, but are immanent
and inherent, forming the very basis of our material, intellectual and
moral being â they do not limit us but are the real and immediate
conditions of our freedom.[12]
These ideas grew out of the Enlightenment; their roots are in Rousseauâs
Discourse on Inequality, Humboldtâs Limits of State Action, Kantâs
insistence, in his defense of the French Revolution, that freedom is the
precondition for acquiring the maturity for freedom, not a gift to be
granted when such maturity is achieved. With the development of
industrial capitalism, a new and unanticipated system of injustice, it
is libertarian socialism that has preserved and extended the radical
humanist message of the Enlightenment and the classical liberal ideals
that were perverted into an ideology to sustain the emerging social
order. In fact, on the very same assumptions that led classical
liberalism to oppose the intervention of the state in social life,
capitalist social relations are also intolerable. This is clear, for
example, from the classic work of Humboldt, The Limits of State Action,
which anticipated and perhaps inspired Mill. This classic of liberal
thought, completed in 1792, is in its essence profoundly, though
prematurely, anticapitalist. Its ideas must be attenuated beyond
recognition to be transmuted into an ideology of industrial capitalism.
Humboldtâs vision of a society in which social fetters are replaced by
social bonds and labor is freely undertaken suggests the early Marx.,
with his discussion of the âalienation of labor when work is external to
the worker...not part of his nature...[so that] he does not fulfill
himself in his work but denies himself...[and is] physically exhausted
and mentally debased,â alienated labor that âcasts some of the workers
back into a barbarous kind of work and turns others into machines,â thus
depriving man of his âspecies characterâ of âfree conscious activityâ
and âproductive life.â Similarly, Marx conceives of âa new type of human
being who needs his fellow men....[The workersâ association becomes] the
real constructive effort to create the social texture of future human
relations.â[13] It is true that classical libertarian thought is opposed
to state intervention in social life, as a consequence of deeper
assumptions about the human need for liberty, diversity, and free
association. On the same assumptions, capitalist relations of
production, wage labor, competitiveness, the ideology of âpossessive
individualismâ â all must be regarded as fundamentally antihuman.
Libertarian socialism is properly to be regarded as the inheritor of the
liberal ideals of the Enlightenment.
Rudolf Rocker describes modern anarchism as âthe confluence of the two
great currents which during and since the French revolution have found
such characteristic expression in the intellectual life of Europe:
Socialism and Liberalism.â The classical liberal ideals, he argues, were
wrecked on the realities of capitalist economic forms. Anarchism is
necessarily anticapitalist in that it âopposes the exploitation of man
by man.â But anarchism also opposes âthe dominion of man over man.â It
insists that âsocialism will be free or it will not be at all. In its
recognition of this lies the genuine and profound justification for the
existence of anarchism.â[14] From this point of view, anarchism may be
regarded as the libertarian wing of socialism. It is in this spirit that
Daniel Guérin has approached the study of anarchism in Anarchism and
other works.[15] GuĂ©rin quotes Adolph Fischer, who said that âevery
anarchist is a socialist but not every socialist is necessarily an
anarchist.â Similarly Bakunin, in his âanarchist manifestoâ of 1865, the
program of his projected international revolutionary fraternity, laid
down the principle that each member must be, to begin with, a socialist.
A consistent anarchist must oppose private ownership of the means of
production and the wage slavery which is a component of this system, as
incompatible with the principle that labor must be freely undertaken and
under the control of the producer. As Marx put it, socialists look
forward to a society in which labor will âbecome not only a means of
life, but also the highest want in life,â[16] an impossibility when the
worker is driven by external authority or need rather than inner
impulse: âno form of wage-labor, even though one may be less obnoxious
that another, can do away with the misery of wage-labor itself.â[17] A
consistent anarchist must oppose not only alienated labor but also the
stupefying specialization of labor that takes place when the means for
developing production
mutilate the worker into a fragment of a human being, degrade him to
become a mere appurtenance of the machine, make his work such a torment
that its essential meaning is destroyed; estrange from him the
intellectual potentialities of the labor process in very proportion to
the extent to which science is incorporated into it as an independent
power...[18]
Marx saw this not as an inevitable concomitant of industrialization, but
rather as a feature of capitalist relations of production. The society
of the future must be concerned to âreplace the detail-worker of
today...reduced to a mere fragment of a man, by the fully developed
individual, fit for a variety of labours...to whom the different social
functions...are but so many modes of giving free scope to his own
natural powers.â[19] The prerequisite is the abolition of capital and
wage labor as social categories (not to speak of the industrial armies
of the âlabor stateâ or the various modern forms of totalitarianism
since capitalism). The reduction of man to an appurtenance of the
machine, a specialized tool of production, might in principle be
overcome, rather than enhanced, with the proper development and use of
technology, but not under the conditions of autocratic control of
production by those who make man an instrument to serve their ends,
overlooking his individual purposes, in Humboldtâs phrase.
Anarchosyndicalists sought, even under capitalism, to create âfree
associations of free producersâ that would engage in militant struggle
and prepare to take over the organization of production on a democratic
basis. These associations would serve as âa practical school of
anarchism.â[20] If private ownership of the means of production is, in
Proudhonâs often quoted phrase, merely a form of âtheftâ â âthe
exploitation of the weak by the strongâ[21] â control of production by a
state bureaucracy, no matter how benevolent its intentions, also does
not create the conditions under which labor, manual and intellectual,
can become the highest want in life. Both, then, must be overcome.
In his attack on the right of private or bureaucratic control over the
means of production,, the anarchist takes his stand with those who
struggle to bring about âthe third and last emancipatory phase of
history,â the first having made serfs out of slaves, the second having
made wage earners out of serfs, and the third which abolishes the
proletariat in a final act of liberation that places control over the
economy in the hands of free and voluntary associations of producers
(Fourier, 1848).[22] The imminent danger to âcivilizationâ was noted by
de Tocqueville, also in 1848:
As long as the right of property was the origin and groundwork of many
other rights, it was easily defended â or rather it was not attacked; it
was then the citadel of society while all the other rights were its
outworks; it did not bear the brunt of attack and, indeed, there was no
serious attempt to assail it. but today, when the right of property is
regarded as the last undestroyed remnant of the aristocratic world, when
it alone is left standing, the sole privilege in an equalized society,
it is a different matter. Consider what is happening in the hearts of
the working-classes, although I admit they are quiet as yet. It is true
that they are less inflamed than formerly by political passions properly
speaking; but do you not see that their passions, far from being
political, have become social? Do you not see that, little by little,
ideas and opinions are spreading amongst them which aim not merely at
removing such and such laws, such a ministry or such a government, but
at breaking up the very foundations of society itself?[23]
The workers of Paris, in 1871, broke the silence, and proceeded
to abolish property, the basis of all civilization! Yes, gentlemen, the
Commune intended to abolish that class property which makes the labor of
the many the wealth of the few. It aimed at the expropriation of the
expropriators. It wanted to make individual property a truth by
transforming the means of production, land and capital, now chiefly the
means of enslaving and exploiting labor, into mere instruments of free
and associated labor.[24]
The Commune, of course, was drowned in blood. The nature of the
âcivilizationâ that the workers of Paris sought to overcome in their
attack on âthe very foundations of society itselfâ was revealed, once
again, when the troops of the Versailles government reconquered Paris
from its population. As Marx wrote, bitterly but accurately:
The civilization and justice of bourgeois order comes out in its lurid
light whenever the slaves and drudges of that order rise against their
masters. Then this civilization and justice stand forth as undisguised
savagery and lawless revenge...the infernal deeds of the soldiery
reflect the innate spirit of that civilization of which they are the
mercenary vindicators....The bourgeoisie of the whole world, which looks
complacently upon the wholesale massacre after the battle, is convulsed
by horror at the destruction of brick and mortar. [Ibid., pp. 74, 77]
Despite the violent destruction of the Commune, Bakunin wrote that Paris
opens a new era, âthat of the definitive and complete emancipation of
the popular masses and their future true solidarity, across and despite
state boundaries...the next revolution of man, international in
solidarity, will be the resurrection of Parisâ â a revolution that the
world still awaits.
The consistent anarchist, then, should be a socialist, but a socialist
of a particular sort. He will not only oppose alienated and specialized
labor and look forward to the appropriation of capital by the whole body
of workers, but he will also insist that this appropriation be direct,
not exercised by some elite force acting in the name of the proletariat.
He will, in short, oppose
the organization of production by the Government. It means
State-socialism, the command of the State officials over production and
the command of managers, scientists, shop-officials in the shop....The
goal of the working class is liberation from exploitation. This goal is
not reached and cannot be reached by a new directing and governing class
substituting itself for the bourgeoisie. It is only realized by the
workers themselves being master over production.
These remarks are taken from âFive Theses on the Class Struggleâ by the
left-wing Marxist Anton Pannekoek, one of the outstanding left theorists
of the council communist movement. And in fact, radical Marxism merges
with anarchist currents.
As a further illustration, consider the following characterization of
ârevolutionary Socialismâ:
The revolutionary Socialist denies that State ownership can end in
anything other than a bureaucratic despotism. We have seen why the State
cannot democratically control industry. Industry can only be
democratically owned and controlled by the workers electing directly
from their own ranks industrial administrative committees. Socialism
will be fundamentally an industrial system; its constituencies will be
of an industrial character. Thus those carrying on the social activities
and industries of society will be directly represented in the local and
central councils of social administration. In this way the powers of
such delegates will flow upwards from those carrying on the work and
conversant with the needs of the community. When the central
administrative industrial committee meets it will represent every phase
of social activity. Hence the capitalist political or geographical state
will be replaced by the industrial administrative committee of
Socialism. The transition from the one social system to the other will
be the social revolution. The political State throughout history has
meant the government of men by ruling classes; the Republic of Socialism
will be the government of industry administered on behalf of the whole
community. The former meant the economic and political subjection of the
many; the latter will mean the economic freedom of all â it will be,
therefore, a true democracy.
This programmatic statement appears in William Paulâs The State, its
Origins and Functions, written in early 1917 â shortly before Leninâs
State and Revolution, perhaps his most libertarian work (see note 9).
Paul was a member of the Marxist-De Leonist Socialist Labor Party and
later one of the founders of the British Communist Party.[25] His
critique of state socialism resembles the libertarian doctrine of the
anarchists in its principle that since state ownership and management
will lead to bureaucratic despotism, the social revolution must replace
it by the industrial organization of society with direct workersâ
control. Many similar statements can be cited.
What is far more important is that these ideas have been realized in
spontaneous revolutionary action, for example in Germany and Italy after
World War I and in Spain (not only in the agricultural countryside, but
also in industrial Barcelona) in 1936. One might argue that some form of
council communism is the natural form of revolutionary socialism in an
industrial society. It reflects the intuitive understanding that
democracy is severely limited when the industrial system is controlled
by any form of autocratic elite, whether of owners, managers and
technocrats, a âvanguardâ party, or a state bureaucracy. Under these
conditions of authoritarian domination the classical libertarian ideals
developed further by Marx and Bakunin and all true revolutionaries
cannot be realized; man will not be free to develop his own
potentialities to their fullest, and the producer will remain âa
fragment of a human being,â degraded, a tool in the productive process
directed from above.
The phrase âspontaneous revolutionary actionâ can be misleading. The
anarchosyndicalists, at least, took very seriously Bakuninâs remark that
the workersâ organizations must create ânot only the ideas but also the
facts of the future itselfâ in the prerevolutionary period. The
accomplishments of the popular revolution in Spain, in particular, were
based on the patient work of many years of organization and education,
one component of a long tradition of commitment and militancy. The
resolutions of the Madrid Congress of June 1931 and the Saragossa
Congress in May 1936 foreshadowed in many ways the acts of the
revolution, as did the somewhat different ideas sketched by Santillan
(see note 4) in his fairly specific account of the social and economic
organization to be instituted by the revolution. GuĂ©rin writes âThe
Spanish revolution was relatively mature in the minds of libertarian
thinkers, as in the popular consciousness.â And workersâ organizations
existed with the structure, the experience, and the understanding to
undertake the task of social reconstruction when, with the Franco coup,
the turmoil of early 1936 exploded into social revolution. In his
introduction to a collection of documents on collectivization in Spain,
the anarchist Augustin Souchy writes:
For many years, the anarchists and the syndicalists of Spain considered
their supreme task to be the social transformation of the society. In
their assemblies of Syndicates and groups, in their journals, their
brochures and books, the problem of the social revolution was discussed
incessantly and in a systematic fashion.[26]
All of this lies behind the spontaneous achievements, the constructive
work of the Spanish Revolution.
The ideas of libertarian socialism, in the sense described, have been
submerged in the industrial societies of the past half-century. The
dominant ideologies have been those of state socialism or state
capitalism (of increasingly militarized character in the United States,
for reasons that are not obscure).[27] But there has been a rekindling
of interest in the past few years. The theses I quoted by Anton
Pannekoek were taken from a recent pamphlet of a radical French workersâ
group (Informations Correspondance OuvriĂšre). The remarks by William
Paul on revolutionary socialism are cited in a paper by Walter Kendall
given at the National Conference on Workersâ Control in Sheffield,
England, in March 1969. The workersâ control movement has become a
significant force in England in the past few years. It has organized
several conferences and has produced a substantial pamphlet literature,
and counts among its active adherents representatives of some of the
most important trade unions. The Amalgamated Engineering and
Foundryworkersâ Union, for example, has adopted, as official policy, the
program of nationalization of basic industries under âworkersâ control
at all levels.â[28] On the Continent, there are similar developments.
May 1968 of course accelerated the growing interest in council communism
and related ideas in France and Germany, as it did in England.
Given the highly conservative cast of our highly ideological society, it
is not too surprising that the United States has been relatively
untouched by these developments. But that too may change. The erosion of
cold-war mythology at least makes it possible to raise these questions
in fairly broad circles. If the present wave of repression can be beaten
back, if the left can overcome its more suicidal tendencies and build
upon what has been accomplished in the past decade, then the problem of
how to organize industrial society on truly democratic lines, with
democratic control in the workplace and in the community, should become
a dominant intellectual issue for those who are alive to the problems of
contemporary society, and, as a mass movement for libertarian socialism
develops, speculation should proceed to action.
In his manifesto of 1865, Bakunin predicted that one element in the
social revolution will be âthat intelligent and truly noble part of
youth which, though belonging by birth to the privileged classes, in its
generous convictions and ardent aspirations, adopts the cause of the
people.â Perhaps in the rise of the student movement of the 1960s one
sees steps towards a fulfillment of this prophecy.
Daniel GuĂ©rin has undertaken what he has described as a âprocess of
rehabilitationâ of anarchism. He argues, convincingly I believe, that
âthe constructive ideas of anarchism retain their vitality, that they
may, when re-examined and sifted, assist contemporary socialist thought
to undertake a new departure...[and] contribute to enriching
Marxism.â[29] From the âbroad backâ of anarchism he has selected for
more intensive scrutiny those ideas and actions that can be described as
libertarian socialist. This is natural and proper. This framework
accommodates the major anarchist spokesmen as well as the mass actions
that have been animated by anarchist sentiments and ideals. Guérin is
concerned not only with anarchist thought but also with the spontaneous
actions of popular revolutionary struggle. He is concerned with social
as well as intellectual creativity. Furthermore, he attempts to draw
from the constructive achievements of the past lessons that will enrich
the theory of social liberation. For those who wish not only to
understand the world, but also to change it, this is the proper way to
study the history of anarchism.
Guérin describes the anarchism of the nineteenth century as essentially
doctrinal, while the twentieth century, for the anarchists, has been a
time of ârevolutionary practice.â[30] Anarchism reflects that judgment.
His interpretation of anarchism consciously points toward the future.
Arthur Rosenberg once pointed out that popular revolutions
characteristically seek to replace âa feudal or centralized authority
ruling by forceâ with some form of communal system which âimplies the
destruction and disappearance of the old form of State.â Such a system
will be either socialist or an âextreme form of democracy...[which is]
the preliminary condition for Socialism inasmuch as Socialism can only
be realized in a world enjoying the highest possible measure of
individual freedom.â This ideal, he notes, was common to Marx and the
anarchists.[31] This natural struggle for liberation runs counter to the
prevailing tendency towards centralization in economic and political
life.
A century ago Marx wrote that the workers of Paris âfelt there was but
one alternative â the Commune, or the empire â under whatever name it
might reappear.â
The empire had ruined them economically by the havoc it made of public
wealth, by the wholesale financial swindling it fostered, by the props
it lent to the artificially accelerated centralization of capital, and
the concomitant expropriation of their own ranks. It had suppressed them
politically, it had shocked them morally by its orgies, it had insulted
their Voltairianism by handing over the education of their children to
the frĂšres Ignorantins, it had revolted their national feeling as
Frenchmen by precipitating them headlong into a war which left only one
equivalent for the ruins it made â the disappearance of the empire.[32]
The miserable Second Empire âwas the only form of government possible at
a time when the bourgeoisie had already lost, and the working class had
not yet acquired, the faculty of ruling the nation.â
It is not very difficult to rephrase these remarks so that they become
appropriate to the imperial systems of 1970. The problem of âfreeing man
from the curse of economic exploitation and political and social
enslavementâ remains the problem of our time. As long as this is so, the
doctrines and the revolutionary practice of libertarian socialism will
serve as an inspiration and guide.
London: Cambridge University Press, 1968.
Dolgoff. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1972.
1969.
2^(nd) ed. Toulouse: Editions C.N.T., 1965. First edition, Barcelona,
1937.
the Genesis and Transformation of Communist Ideology.â American Slavic
and East European Review, vol. 12, no. 1 (1953).
Marcel RiviĂšre, 1959.
New York: Monthly Review Press, 1970.
Collier Books, 1962.
London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1969.
Nicolson, 1968.
Horizons Series. Boston: Porter Sargent, 1969.
edited by Priscilla Long. Boston: Porter Sargent, 1969.
Publishers, 1941.
Temps nouveaux, 1895. Reprinted in Ni Dieu, ni MaĂźtre, edited by Daniel
Guérin. Lausanne: La Cité Editeur, n.d.
Enlarged ed. London: Freedom Press, 1972.
Yearsâ Plan. Translated by Ian F. Morrow. New York: Russell & Russell,
1965.
Publishers, 1937.
Workersâ Control Pamphlet Series, no. 1, Nottingham, England, 1968.
Norton & Co., 1969.
Â
[1] Octave Mirbeau, quoted in James Joll, The Anarchists, pp. 145â6.
[2] Rudolf Rocker, Anarchosyndicalism, p. 31.
[3] Cited by Rocker, ibid., p. 77. This quotation and that in the next
sentence are from Michael Bakunin, âThe Program of the Alliance,â in Sam
Dolgoff, ed. and trans., Bakunin on Anarchy, p. 255.
[4] Diego Abad de Santillan, After the Revolution, p. 86. In the last
chapter, written several months after the revolution had begun, he
expresses his dissatisfaction with what had so far been achieved along
these lines. On the accomplishments of the social revolution in Spain,
see my American Power and the New Mandarins, chap. 1, and references
cited there; the important study by Broué and Témime has since been
translated into English. Several other important studies have appeared
since, in particular: Frank Mintz, LâAutogestion dans lâEspagne
révolutionaire (Paris: Editions Bélibaste, 1971); César M. Lorenzo, Les
Anarchistes espagnols et le pouvoir, 1868â1969 (Paris: Editions du
Seuil, 1969); Gaston Leval, Espagne libertaire, 1936â1939: LâOeuvre
constructive de la RĂ©volution espagnole (Paris: Editions du Cercle,
1971). See also Vernon Richards, Lessons of the Spanish Revolution,
enlarged 1972 edition.
[5] Cited by Robert C. Tucker, The Marxian Revolutionary Idea, in his
discussion of Marxism and anarchism.
[6] Bakunin, in a letter to Herzen and Ogareff, 1866. Cited by Daniel
Guérin, Jeunesse du socialisme libertaire, p. 119.
[7] Fernand Pelloutier, cited in Joll, Anarchists. The source is
âLâAnarchisme et les syndicats ouvriers,â Les Temps nouveaux, 1895. The
full text appears in Daniel Guérin, ed., Ni Dieu, ni Maßtre, an
excellent historical anthology of anarchism.
[8] Martin Buber, Paths in Utopia, p. 127.
[9] âNo state, however democratic,â Bakunin wrote, ânot even the reddest
republic â can ever give the people what they really want, i.e., the
free self-organization and administration of their own affairs from the
bottom upward, without any interference or violence from above, because
every state, even the pseudo-Peopleâs State concocted by Mr. Marx, is in
essence only a machine ruling the masses from above, from a privileged
minority of conceited intellectuals, who imagine that they know what the
people need and want better than do the people themselves....â âBut the
people will feel no better if the stick with which they are being beaten
is labeled âthe peopleâs stickâ â (Statism and Anarchy [1873], in
Dolgoff, Bakunin on Anarchy, p. 338) â âthe peopleâs stickâ being the
democratic Republic.
Marx, of course, saw the matter differently.
For discussion of the impact of the Paris Commune on this dispute, see
Daniel GuĂ©rinâs comments in Ni Dieu, ni MaĂźtre; these also appear,
slightly extended, in his Pour un marxisme libertaire. See also note 24.
[10] On Leninâs âintellectual deviationâ to the left during 1917, see
Robert Vincent Daniels, âThe State and Revolution: a Case Study in the
Genesis and Transformation of Communist Ideology,â American Slavic and
East European Review, vol. 12, no. 1 (1953).
[11] Paul Mattick, Marx and Keynes, p. 295.
[12] Michael Bakunin, âLa Commune de Paris et la notion de lâĂ©tat,â
reprinted in GuĂ©rin, Ni Dieu, ni MaĂźtre. Bakuninâs final remark on the
laws of individual nature as the condition of freedom can be compared to
the creative thought developed in the rationalist and romantic
traditions. See my Cartesian Linguistics and Language and Mind.
[13] Shlomo Avineri, The Social and Political Thought of Karl Marx, p.
142, referring to comments in The Holy Family. Avineri states that
within the socialist movement only the Israeli kibbutzim âhave perceived
that the modes and forms of present social organization will determine
the structure of future society.â This, however, was a characteristic
position of anarchosyndicalism, as noted earlier.
[14] Rocker, Anarchosyndicalism, p. 28.
[15] See GuĂ©rinâs works cited earlier.
[16] Karl Marx, Critique of the Gotha Programme.
[17] Karl Marx, Grundrisse der Kritik der Politischen Ăkonomie, cited by
Mattick, Marx and Keynes, p. 306. In this connection, see also Mattickâs
essay âWorkersâ Control,â in Priscilla Long, ed., The New Left; and
Avineri, Social and Political Thought of Marx.
[18] Karl Marx, Capital, quoted by Robert Tucker, who rightly emphasizes
that Marx sees the revolutionary more as a âfrustrated producerâ than a
âdissatisfied consumerâ (The Marxian Revolutionary Idea). This more
radical critique of capitalist relations of production is a direct
outgrowth of the libertarian thought of the Enlightenment.
[19] Marx, Capital, cited by Avineri, Social and Political Thought of
Marx, p. 83.
[20] Pelloutier, âLâAnarchisme.â
[21] âQuâest-ce que la propriĂ©tĂ©?â The phrase âproperty is theftâ
displeased Marx, who saw in its use a logical problem, theft
presupposing the legitimate existence of property. See Avineri, Social
and Political Thought of Marx.
[22] Cited in Buberâs Paths in Utopia, p. 19.
[23] Cited in J. Hampden Jackson, Marx, Proudhon and European Socialism,
p. 60.
[24] Karl Marx, The Civil War in France, p. 24. Avineri observes that
this and other comments of Marx about the Commune refer pointedly to
intentions and plans. As Marx made plain elsewhere, his considered
assessment was more critical than in this address.
[25] For some background, see Walter Kendall, The Revolutionary Movement
in Britain.
[26] Collectivisations: LâOeuvre constructive de la RĂ©volution
espagnole, p. 8.
[27] For discussion, see Mattick, Marx and Keynes, and Michael Kidron,
Western Capitalism Since the War. See also discussion and references
cited in my At War With Asia, chap. 1, pp. 23â6.
[28] See Hugh Scanlon, The Way Forward for Workersâ Control. Scanlon is
the president of the AEF, one of Britainâs largest trade unions. The
institute was established as a result of the sixth Conference on
Workersâ Control, March 1968, and serves as a center for disseminating
information and encouraging research.
[29] Guérin, Ni Dieu, ni Maßtre, introduction.
[30] Ibid.
[31] Arthur Rosenberg, A History of Bolshevism, p. 88.
[32] Marx, Civil War in France, pp. 62â3.