đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș max-stirner-stirner-s-critics.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:51:19. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Stirner’s Critics
Author: Max Stirner
Date: 1845
Language: en
Topics: critique, Little Black Cart
Source: Retrieved on June 15, 2011 from https://sites.google.com/site/vagabondtheorist/stirner/stirner-s-critics
Notes: Translated by Wolfi Landstreicher | Published by Little Black Cart https://littleblackcart.com/index.php?dispatch=products.view&product_id=288.

Max Stirner

Stirner’s Critics

Translator’s Preface

Working on this translation has been a pleasurable challenge for me.

Stirner uses straightforward, even fairly simple language, filled with

passion and sarcasm, to express ideas that are difficult, though more in

the fact that very few people would want to accept their implications

than in their complexity. In wrestling with this work, I have had to

make decisions about how best to get Stirner’s thinking across in

English. The purpose of this preface is to explain some of those

decisions.

One of the central terms in Stirner’s thinking is “der Einzige.” I have

chosen to translate this as “the unique.” Some have argued in favor of

leaving this noun in German, and I understand their point, but in this

text Stirner frequently connects the noun Einzige with the adjective

einzige, and this connection would be lost if I left the noun in German.

In addition, I think that leaving Einzige in German would give the text

a more academic feeling, as if Stirner were inventing a specialized

language, which he is not. For Stirner, Einzige is simply a name to use

for something that is beyond definition, something that is unspeakable,

so I decided not to translate it as “the unique one.” Such a translation

would imply that “unique” says something definitive about some one,

rather than merely being a name pointing toward something unsayable. I

think that, in “the unique,” the fact that it is meant to be a mere name

for something beyond language is made clearer. Because Stirner compares

his use of “der Einzige” to the way one uses proper names, such as

“Ludwig,” knowing perfectly well that the word Ludwig tells you nothing

about the person so designated, and yet indicates clearly who you are

talking about if those to whom you speak know Ludwig, I considered

capitalizing “unique” as a proper name is capitalized, but have chosen

not to do so for fear that some would instead read it as presenting the

unique as an ideal, a higher reality, rather than simply as you and I in

the here and now. In light of all this, I choose to translate the title

of Stirner’s book as The Unique and Its Own[1], a more correct

translation than the current English title (The Ego and Its Own).

I decided to keep leave all references to page numbers of citations from

Der Einzige und Sein Eigentum as they were — reflecting the page numbers

in the original edition of the book. I also translated these citations

directly, rather than going to Byington’s translation either in its

original form or in the version edited by David Leopold (Cambridge Texts

in the History of Political Thought). I did this because I wanted to

maintain a consistency in language between what Stirner has written here

and his citations from his earlier book and to guarantee that Stirner’s

references to various philosophical, political and theological ideas of

his time were not lost. I also hope that someone will find the time to

do an improved English translation of Stirner’s major work in the near

future.

Though Stirner does not invent a specialized language, his writings

spring out of the context of the debates of the young Hegelians and

other German philosophical and social radicals of the times. Thus,

Stirner uses certain terms in Hegelian (or anti-Hegelian) ways. I have

chosen to translate these terms as consistently as a good, readable

translation would allow.[2] I want to mention a few of these. In English

translations of Hegelian works, “Begriff” is generally either translated

as “notion” or “concept.” I have chosen the latter translation, because

it allows some of Stirner’s word play to appear more clearly in English.

I have translated “Entfremden” as “alienation” although “estrangement”

is an equally acceptable translation. I felt that my choice has more

meaning to those likely to read this translation, within the context of

present-day radical theoretical endeavors. In Hegelian usage, “Wesen” is

translated as “essence.” In addition, in its frequent usage with

“Mensch,” which itself can be translated as “human being” or merely

“human,” it is clearly a reference to the species “essence” which

Stirner’s critics claim to be inherent in the human being. Stirner turns

this idea on its head in an interesting way by arguing that the real

essence of each individual is, in fact, his or her concrete, actual,

inconceivable, unspeakable, unique being in the immediate moment, the

very opposite of the way Hegel and the other young Hegelians conceived

it. Although the word “Meinung” only appears four times in this text, it

is significant in Hegelian thought. The word is often translated as

“opinion,” though it can also be translated as “view,” “judgment,” or

“estimation.” Hegel “often stresses the etymological link with mein

(‘mine’),”[3] and Stirner is likely to have found it amusing. For Hegel,

Meinung was merely of use for distinguishing particulars and was thus of

no significance to universal Reason or universal Thought. For Stirner,

these universals were spooks, and particulars (and more specifically

myself in particular) were what mattered. So Meinung is how you and I

actually experience out world, or to put it more simply, each of us

experiences it from our own point of view. To emphasize this, I have

chosen to translate Meinung as “view” in this text.

There are a few other choices I made in translation that I think need

some comment. “Mensch” can be translated either as “person” or “human

being.” In this text, Stirner uses it in the context of his critique of

humanism, and so I decided it made the most sense to translate it as

“human being.” In a couple of passages in this text, Stirner contrasts

“Mensch” to “Unmensch.” In Byington’s translation of Der Einzige und

Sein Eigentum, he chose to simply translate the latter word as “unman.”

But in German, the word refers to a “monster,” and knowing Stirner’s

enjoyment of playing with words and ideas in ways that are likely to get

the goat of his opponents, I think that he most likely meant just that.

To further emphasize Stirner’s intent of contrasting this with the

abstract, conceptual human being, I chose to translate the term as

“inhuman monster.” This leads to such delightful statements as: “You are

an inhuman monster, and this is why you are completely human, a real and

actual human being, a complete human being.”

The German word “PrĂ€dikat” could be translated as “predicate” or

“attribute” (among other possibilities). In this text, Stirner uses it

specifically in reference to god or to humanity as the new god. Thus, he

is using it in an anti-theological sense rather than a grammatical

sense. I have thus chosen to use the theological term “attribute” rather

than the grammatical term “predicate” to translate it.

The word “Vorstellung” only appears twice in this work, and in both

instances it is in reference to the ways that Stirner’s opponents chose

to depict egoism. Though “Vorstellung” is often translated into English

as “representation,” it has a far more active connotation than this

English word. It is more an active depiction or conceptualization that

one is inventing. Certainly this what Stirner is saying about his

opponents. Thus, I have translated the word as “depiction” here.

There is a passage in which Stirner criticizes “Bedenken.” One can

translate this word as “qualms,” “scruples,” “misgiving,” or “doubts.”

In this text, it is obvious that he is talking about moral scruples. In

the context, Stirner uses a couple of other words in ways rather

different from their usual present-day meanings. He uses

“Bedenklichkeit” and “Unbedenklichkeit” in ways that in the context only

make sense if they are translated as “scrupulousness” for the former

word and “unscrupulousness” or “lack of scruples” for the latter. But in

present-day German “Bedenklichkeit” is usually translated as

“seriousness,” “precariousness” or “anxiety”; and “Unbedanklichkeit” is

usually translated as “harmlessness.” Since in this passage, Stirner

plays a lot on “Bedenken,” “Denken” and “Gedenken” (wordplay sadly lost

in translation), it is possible that he was also playing with these

other two terms — implying that scrupulousness causes anxiety and that a

lack of scruples is harmless compared to the moral dogmas of

scrupulousness. In any case, I chose translate the words in the way that

would make sense in context, as “scrupulousness” for the first word, and

“unscrupulousness” or “lack of scruples” for the second.

Finally, I want to say that translating this work has been an act of

egoistic love. I wanted to see a full English translation of it, and

took the tools and means in hand to create it. I have had much enjoyment

in doing so.

 

Wolfi Landstreicher

Stirner’s critics by Max Stirner

The following three notable writings have come out against The Unique

and Its Own:

Gazette”;

in the latest volume of Wigand’s Quarterly Review;

Szeliga presents himself as a critic, Hess as a socialist and the author

of the second piece as Feuerbach.

A brief response might be useful, if not to the critics mentioned above,

at least to some other readers of the book.

The three opponents are in agreement about the terms that draw the most

attention in Stirner’s book, i.e., the “unique” and “egoist.” It will

therefore be very useful to take advantage of this unity and first of

all discuss the points mentioned.

Szeliga, after first having in all seriousness allowed the unique “to

become” and identified it with a “man” (page 4: “The unique wasn’t

always unique, nor always a man, but was once a baby and then a young

boy”), makes him an “individual of world history” and finally, after a

definition of spooks (from which it emerges that “a spirit lacking

thought is a body, and that the pure and simple body is the absence of

thought”), he finds that the unique is “therefore the spook of spooks.”

It is true that he adds, “For the critic who doesn’t just see in

universal history fixed ideas replacing each other, but creative

thoughts continually developing, for the critic, however, the unique is

not a spook, but an act of creative self-consciousness, which had to

arise in its time, in our time, and fulfill its determined task”; but

this act is merely a “thought,” a “principle” and a book.

When Feuerbach deals with the unique, he limits himself to considering

it as a “unique individual,” chosen from a class or species and “opposed

as sacred and inviolable to other individuals.” In this choosing and

opposing “the essence of religion remains. This man, this unique, this

incomparable being, this Jesus Christ, is only and exclusively God. This

oak, this place, this bull, this day is sacred, not the others.” He

concludes: “Chase the Unique in Heaven from your head, but also chase

away the Unique on earth.”

Hess strictly only alludes to the unique. He first identifies Stirner

with the unique, and then says of the Unique: “He is the headless,

heartless trunk, i.e., he has the illusion of being so, because in

reality he doesn’t just lack spirit, but body as well; he is nothing

other than his illusions.” And finally he pronounces his judgment on

Stirner, “the unique”: “He is boasting.”

From this, the unique appears as “the spook of all spooks,” as “the

sacred individual, which one must chase from the head” and as the “pale

boaster.”

Stirner names the unique and says at the same time that “Names don’t

name it.” He utters a name when he names the unique, and adds that the

unique is only a name. So he thinks something other than what he says,

just as, for example, when someone calls you Ludwig, he isn’t thinking

of a generic Ludwig, but of you, for whom he has no word.

What Stirner says is a word, a thought, a concept; what he means is

neither a word, nor a thought, nor a concept. What he says is not the

meaning, and what he means cannot be said.

One flattered oneself that one spoke about the “actual, individual”

human being when one spoke of the human being; but was this possible so

long as one wanted to express this human being through something

universal, through an attribute? To designate this human being,

shouldn’t one, perhaps, have recourse not to an attribute, but rather to

a designation, to a name to take refuge in, where the view, i.e., the

unspeakable, is the main thing? Some are reassured by “real, complete

individuality,” which is still not free of the relation to the species;

others by the “spirit,” which is likewise a determination, not complete

indeterminacy. This indeterminacy only seems to be achieved in the

unique, because it is given as the specific unique being, because when

it is grasped as a concept, i.e., as an expression, it appears as a

completely empty and undetermined name, and thus refers to a content

outside of or beyond the concept. If one fixes it as a concept — and the

opponents do this — one must attempt to give it a definition and will

thus inevitably come upon something different from what was meant. It

would be distinguished from other concepts and considered, for example,

as “the sole complete individual,” so that it becomes easy to show it as

nonsense. But can you define yourself; are you a concept?

The “human being,” as a concept or an attribute, does not exhaust you,

because it has a conceptual content of its own, because it says what is

human and what a human being is, i.e., because it is capable of being

defined so that you can remain completely out of play. Of course, you as

a human being still have your part in the conceptual content of the

human being, but you don’t have it as you. The unique, however, has no

content; it is indeterminacy in itself; only through you does it acquire

content and determination. There is no conceptual development of the

unique, one cannot build a philosophical system with it as a

“principle,” the way one can with being, with thought, with the I.

Rather it puts an end to all conceptual development. Anyone who

considers it a principle, thinks that he can treat it philosophically or

theoretically and inevitably takes useless potshots against it. Being,

thought, the I, are only undetermined concepts, which receive their

determinateness only through other concepts, i.e., through conceptual

development. The unique, on the other hand, is a concept that lacks

determination and cannot be made determinate by other concepts or

receive a “nearer content”; it is not the “principle of a series of

concepts,” but a word or concept that, as word or concept, is not

capable of any development. The development of the unique is your

self-development and my self-development, an utterly unique development,

because your development is not at all my development. Only as a

concept, i.e., only as “development,” are they one and the same; on the

contrary, your development is just as distinct and unique as mine.

Since you are the content of the unique, there is no more to think about

a specific content of the unique, i.e., a conceptual content.

What you are cannot be said through the word unique, just as by

christening you with the name Ludwig, one doesn’t intend to say what you

are.

With the unique, the rule of absolute thought, of thought with a

conceptual content of its own, comes to an end, just as the concept and

the conceptual world fades away when one uses the empty name: the name

is the empty name to which only the view can give content.

But it is not true, as Stirner’s opponents present it, that in the

unique there is only the “lie of what has been called the egoistic world

up to now”; no, in its nakedness and its barrenness, in its shameless

“candor,” (see Szeliga, p. 34) the nakedness and barrenness of concepts

and ideas come to light, the useless pomposity of its opponents is made

clear. It becomes obvious that the biggest “phrase” is the one that

seems to be the word most full of content. The unique is the frank,

undeniable, clear — phrase; it is the keystone of our phrase-world, this

world whose “beginning was the word.”

The unique is an expression with which, in all frankness and honesty,

one recognizes that he is expressing nothing. Human being, spirit, the

true individual, personality, etc. are expressions or attributes that

are full to overflowing with content, phrases with the greatest wealth

of ideas; compared with these sacred and noble phrases, the unique is

the empty, unassuming and completely common phrase.

The critics suspected something of the sort about the unique; they

treated it as a phrase. But they considered the unique as if it claimed

to be a sacred and noble phrase, and they disputed this claim. But it

wasn’t meant to be anything more than a common phrase, and therefore

actual, which the inflated phrases of its opponents can never be, and

therefore a desecration of phrase-making.

The unique is a word, and everyone should always be able to think

something when he uses a word; a word should have thought content. But

the unique is a thoughtless word; it has no thought content. So then

what is its content, if it is not thought? It is content that cannot

exist a second time and so also cannot be expressed, because if it could

be expressed, actually and wholly expressed, it would exist for a second

time; it would exist in the “expression.”

Since the content of the unique is not thought content, the unique

cannot be thought or said; but since it cannot be said, it, this perfect

phrase, is not even a phrase.

Only when nothing is said about you and you are merely named, are you

recognized as you. As soon as something is said about you, you are only

recognized as that thing (human, spirit, christian, etc.). But the

unique doesn’t say anything because it is merely a name: it says only

that you are you and nothing but you, that you are a unique you, or

rather your self. Therefore, you have no attribute, but with this you

are at the same time without determination, vocation, laws, etc.

Speculation was directed toward finding an attribute so universal that

everyone would be understood in it. However, such an attribute wasn’t

supposed to express in each instance what each one should be, but rather

what he is. Therefore, if “human” was this attribute, one shouldn’t mean

by it something that everyone has to become, since otherwise all the

things that one has not yet become would be excluded, but something that

everyone is. Now, “human” also actually expresses what everyone is. But

this What is an expression for what is universal in everyone, for what

everyone has in common with each other, so it isn’t an expression for

“everyone,” it doesn’t express who everyone is. Are you thoroughly

defined when one says you are a human being? Has one expressed who you

are completely? Does the attribute, “human,” fulfill the task of the

attribute, which is to express the subject completely, or doesn’t it, on

the contrary, completely take subjectivity away from the subject, and

doesn’t it say what the subject is rather than saying who he is?

Therefore, if the attribute should include everyone in itself, everyone

should appear as subject, i.e., not only as what he is, but as who he

is.

But how can you present yourself as who you are, if you don’t present

yourself? Are you a doppelganger or do you exist only once? You are

nowhere except in yourself, you are not in the world a second time, you

are unique. You can emerge only if you appear in the flesh.

“You are unique,” isn’t this a sentence? If in the sentence “you are

human,” you don’t come in as the one who you are, do you actually come

in as you in the sentence “you are unique”? The sentence “you are

unique” means nothing but “you are you,” a sentence that logic calls

nonsense, because it doesn’t make judgments on anything, it doesn’t say

anything, because it is empty, a sentence that is not a sentence. (In

the book on page 232, the absurd sentence is considered as “infinite” or

indeterminate; here however, after the page, it is considered as an

“identical” sentence.)

What the logician treats with contempt is undoubtedly illogical or

merely “formally” logical; but it is also, considered logically, only a

phrase; it is logic dying in a phrase.

The unique should only be the last, dying expression (attribute) of you

and me, the expression that turns into a view: an expression that is no

longer such, that falls silent, that is mute.

You — unique! What thought content is here, what sentence content? None!

Whoever wants to deduce a precise thought-content of the Unique as if it

were a concept, whoever thinks that with “unique” one has said about you

what you are, would show that they believe in phrases, because they

don’t recognize phrases as phrases, and would also show that they seek

specific content in phrases.

You, inconceivable and inexpressible, are the phrase content, the phrase

owner, the phrase embodied; you are the who, the one of the phrase. In

the unique, science can dissolve into life, in which your this becomes

who and this who no longer seeks itself in the word, in the Logos, in

the attribute.

Szeliga takes the pain to show that the unique “measured by its own

principle of seeing spooks everywhere becomes the spook of all spooks.”

He senses that the unique is an empty phrase, but he overlooks the fact

that he himself, Szeliga, is the content of the phrase.

The unique in Heaven, which Feuerbach places beside the unique on earth,

is the phrase without a phrase-owner. The unique considered here is God.

This is the thing that guaranteed that religion would last, that it had

the unique at least in thought and as a phrase, that it saw it in

Heaven. But the heavenly unique is only a unique in which no one has an

interest, whereas Feuerbach instead, whether he likes it or not, is

interested in Stirner’s unique, because he would have to treat it oddly,

if he wanted to chase his own unique from his head. If the heavenly

unique were one that existed in its own head rather than in Feuerbach’s,

it would be difficult to chase this unique from its head.

Hess says of the unique: “he’s boasting.” Undoubtedly, the unique, this

obvious phrase, is an empty boast; it is Feuerbach’s phrase without the

phrase-owner. But isn’t it a pathetic boast to call a long and broad

thing a boast only because one can’t find anything in it but the boast?

Is Hess, this unique Hess, therefore nothing but a boast? Most certainly

not!

The critics display even more irritation against the “egoist” than

against the unique. Instead of delving into egoism as Stirner meant it,

they stop at their usual childish depiction of it and roll out to

everyone the well-known catalogue of sins. Look at egoism, the horrible

sin that this Stirner wants to “recommend” to us.

Against the Christian definition: “God is love,” critics in old

Jerusalem could rise up and cry: “So now you see that the Christians are

announcing a pagan God; because if God is love, then he is the pagan god

Amor, the god of love!” What need do the Jewish critics have to deal

with love and the God who is love, when they have spit on the love-god,

on Amor for so long?

Szeliga characterizes the egoist like this: “The egoist hopes for a

carefree, happy life. He marries a rich girl — and now he has a jealous,

chatterbox wife — in other words his hope was realized and it was an

illusion.”

Feuerbach says: “There is a well-founded difference between what is

called egoistic, self-interested love, and what is called unselfish

love. What? In a few words this: in self-interested love, the object is

your courtesan; in unselfish love, she is your beloved. I find

satisfaction in both, but in the first I subordinate the essence to a

part; in the second I instead subordinate the part, the means, the organ

to the whole, to the essence. Thus, I satisfy myself, my full, entire

essence. In short, in selfish love, I sacrifice the higher thing to the

lower thing, a higher pleasure to a lower pleasure, but in unselfish

love, I sacrifice the lower thing to the higher thing.”

Hess asks: “First of all, what is egoism in general, and what is the

difference between the egoistic life and the life of love?” This

question already reveals his kinship with the other two. How can one

assert such a contrast between egoistic life and the life of love

against Stirner, since for him the two get along quite well? Hess

continues: “Egoistic life is the life of the animal world, which tears

itself down and devours itself. The animal world is precisely the

natural history of life that tears itself down and destroys itself, and

all our history up to now is nothing but the history of the social

animal world. But what distinguishes the social animal world from the

animal world of the forest? Nothing but its consciousness. The history

of the social animal world is precisely the history of the consciousness

of the animal world, and as the predator is the final point of the

natural animal world, so the conscious predator is the highest point of

the social animal world. As egoism is mutual alienation of the species,

so the consciousness of this alienation (egoistic consciousness) is

religious consciousness. The animal world of the forest has no religion,

simply because it lacks consciousness of its egoism, of its alienation,

i.e., consciousness of sin. The earliest consciousness of humanity is

consciousness of sin. — When egoistic theory, egoistic consciousness,

religion and philosophy had reached their peak, egoistic practice also

had to reach its peak. It has reached it in the modern, Christian,

shopkeeper’s world. This is the ultimate point of the social animal

world. — The free competition of our modern shopkeeper’s world is not

only the perfect form of modern murder with robbery, but is at the same

time the consciousness of the mutual, human alienation. Today’s

shopkeeper’s world is the mediated form of conscious and basic egoism,

corresponding to its essence.”

These are quite popular characterizations of egoism, and one is only

surprised that Stirner didn’t make such simple reflections and let

himself abandon the hateful monster, considering how stupid, vulgar and

predatorily murderous egoism is. If he had thought, like Szeliga, that

the egoist is nothing but a numbskull who marries a rich girl and ends

up with a bickering wife, if he would have seen, like Feuerbach, that

the egoist can’t have a “sweetheart,” or if he would have recognized,

like Hess, the human-beast in egoism or would have sniffed out the

predatory murderer there, how could he not have conceived a “profound

horror” and a “legitimate indignation” towards it! Murder with robbery

alone is already such infamy that it really is enough for Hess to cry

out this single phrase against Stirner’s egoist in order to raise all

honest people against him and have them on Hess’s side: the phrase is

well chosen — and moving for a moral heart, like the cry of “heretic”

for a mass of true believers.

Stirner dares to say that Feuerbach, Hess and Szeliga are egoists.

Indeed, he is content here with saying nothing more than if he had said

Feuerbach does absolutely nothing but the Feuerbachian, Hess does

nothing but the Hessian, and Szeliga does nothing but the Szeligan; but

he has given them an infamous label.

Does Feuerbach live in a world other than his own? Does he perhaps live

in Hess’s world, in Szeliga’s world, in Stirner’s world? Since Feuerbach

lives in this world, since it surrounds him, isn’t it the world that is

felt, seen, thought by him, i.e., in a Feuerbachian way? He doesn’t just

live in the middle of it, but is himself its middle; he is the center of

his world. And like Feuerbach, no one lives in any other world than his

own, and like Feuerbach, everyone is the center of his own world. World

is only what he himself is not, but what belongs to him, is in a

relationship with him, exists for him.

Everything turns around you; you are the center of the outer world and

of the thought world. Your world extends as far as your capacity, and

what you grasp is your own simply because you grasp it. You, the unique,

are “the unique” only together with “your property.”

Meanwhile, it doesn’t escape you that what is yours is still itself its

own at the same time, i.e., it has its own existence; it is the unique

the same as you. At this point you forget yourself in sweet

self-forgetfulness.

But when you forget yourself, do you then disappear? When you don’t

think of yourself, have you utterly ceased to exist? When you look in

your friend’s eyes or reflect upon the joy you would like to bring him,

when you gaze up at the stars, meditate upon their laws or perhaps send

them a greeting, which they bring to a lonely little room, when you lose

yourself in the activity of the infusion of tiny animals under a

microscope, when you rush to help someone in danger of burning or

drowning without considering the danger you yourself are risking, then

indeed you don’t “think” of yourself, you “forget yourself.” But do you

exist only when you think of yourself, and do you dissipate when you

forget yourself? Do you exist only through self-consciousness? Who

doesn’t forget himself constantly, who doesn’t lose sight of himself

thousands of times in an hour?

This self-forgetfulness, this losing of oneself, is for us only a mode

of self-enjoyment, it is only the pleasure we take in our world, in our

property, i.e. world-pleasure.

It is not in this self-forgetfulness, but in forgetting that the world

is our world, that unselfishness, i.e., duped egoism, has its basis. You

throw yourself down before a “higher,” absolute world and waste

yourself. Unselfishness is not self-forgetfulness in the sense of no

longer thinking of oneself and no longer being concerned with oneself,

but in the other sense of forgetting that the world is “ours,” of

forgetting that one is the center or owner of this world, that it is our

property. Fear and timidity toward the world as a “higher” world is

cowardly, “humble” egoism, egoism in its slavish form, which doesn’t

dare to grumble, which secretly creeps about and “denies itself”; it is

self-denial.

Our world and the sacred world — herein lies the difference between

straightforward egoism and the self-denying egoism that cannot be

confessed and crawls about incognito.

What happens with Feuerbach’s example of the courtesan and the beloved?

In the first case, one has a commercial relationship without personal

interest (and doesn’t it happen in countless other, completely different

cases of commercial relationships that one can only be satisfied if one

has an interest in the person with whom one deals, if one has a personal

interest?), in the second case one has a personal interest. But what is

the meaning of the second relationship? Most likely mutual interest with

the person. If this interest between the people disappears from the

relationship, it would become meaningless, because this interest is its

only meaning. So what is marriage, which is praised as a “sacred

relationship,” if not the fixation of an interesting relationship

despite the danger that it could become dull and meaningless? People say

that one shouldn’t get divorced “frivolously.” But why not? Because

frivolity is a “sin” if it concerns a “sacred thing.” There must be no

frivolity! So then there is an egoist, who is cheated out of his

frivolity and condemns himself to go on living in an uninteresting but

sacred relationship. From the egoistic union, a “sacred bond” has

developed; the mutual interest the people had for each other ceases, but

the bond without interest remains.

Another example of the uninteresting is work, which passes for one’s

lifework, for the human calling. This is the origin of the prejudice

that one has to earn his bread, and that it is shameful to have bread

without having worked a bit to get it: this is the pride of the wage.

Work has no merit in itself and does no honor to anyone, just as the

life of the idler brings him no disgrace. Either you take an interest in

work activity, and this interest doesn’t let you rest, you have to be

active: and then work is your desire, your special pleasure without

placing it above the laziness of the idler which is his pleasure. Or you

use work to pursue another interest, a result or a “wage,” and you

submit to work only as a means to this end; and then work is not

interesting in itself and has no pretension of being so, and you can

recognize that it is not anything valuable or sacred in itself, but

simply something that is now unavoidable for gaining the desired result,

the wage. But the work that is considered as an “honor for the human

being” and as his “calling” has become the creator of economics and

remains the mistress of sacred socialism, where, in its quality as

“human labor,” it is supposed to “develop human capacities,” and where

this development is a human calling, an absolute interest. (We will have

more to say about this further on).

The belief that something other than self-interest might justify

applying oneself to a given thing, the belief that leaves self-interest

behind, generates a lack of interest, “sin” understood as a tendencies

towards one’s own interest.

Only in the face of sacred interest does one’s own interest become

“private interest,” abominable “egoism,” “sin” — Stirner points out the

difference between sacred interest and one’s own interest briefly on

page 224: “I can sin against the former, the latter I can only throw

away.”

Sacred interest is the uninteresting, because it is an absolute

interest, or an interest for its own sake, and it’s all the same whether

you take an interest in it or not. You are supposed to make it your

interest; it is not originally yours, it doesn’t spring from you, but is

an eternal, universal, purely human interest. It is uninteresting,

because there is no consideration in it for you or your interest; it is

an interest without interested parties, because it is a universal or

human interest. And because you are not its owner, but are supposed to

become its follower and servant, egoism comes to an end before it, and

“lack of interest” begins.

If you take just one sacred interest to heart, you’ll be caught and

duped about your own interests. Call the interest that you follow now

sacred, and tomorrow you will be its slave.

All behavior toward anything considered absolutely interesting, or

valuable in and for itself, is religious behavior or, more simply,

religion. The interesting can only be interesting through your interest,

the valuable can only have value insofar as you give it value, whereas,

on the other hand, what is interesting despite you is an uninteresting

thing, what is valuable despite you is a valueless thing.

The interest of those spirits, like that of society, of the human being,

of the human essence, of the people as a whole, their “essential

interest,” is an alien interest and should be your interest. The

interest of the beloved is your interest and is of interest to you only

so long as it remains your interest. Only when it stops being an

interest of yours can it become a sacred interest, which should be yours

although it is not yours. The relationship that was interesting up to

that point now becomes a disinterested and uninteresting relationship.

In commercial and personal relationships, your interest comes first, and

all sacrifices happen only to benefit this interest of yours, while on

the contrary, in the religious relationship, the religious interest of

the absolute or of the spirit, i.e., the interest alien to you, comes

first, and your interests should be sacrificed to this alien interest.

Therefore, duped egoism consists in the belief in an absolute interest,

which does not spring from the egoist, i.e., is not interesting to him,

but rather arises imperiously and firmly against him, an “eternal”

interest. Here the egoist is “duped,” because his own interest, “private

interest,” is not only left unconsidered, but is even condemned, and yet

“egoism” remains, because he welcomes this alien or absolute interest

only in the hope that it will grant him some pleasure.

This absolute interest, which is supposed to be interesting without

interested persons, and which is also therefore not the unique’s thing,

but for which instead human beings are supposed to view themselves as

“vessels of honor” and as “weapons and tools,” Stirner calls simply “the

sacred.” Indeed, the sacred is absolutely uninteresting, because it has

the pretension of being interesting even though no one is interested in

it; it is also the “universal,” i.e., the thing of interest that lacks a

subject, because it is not one’s own interest, the interest of a unique.

In other words, this “universal interest” is more than you — a “higher”

thing; it is also without you — an “absolute”; it is an interest for

itself — alien to you; it demands that you serve it and finds you

willing, if you let yourself be beguiled.

To stay with Feuerbach’s touching definition of the courtesan, there are

those who would gladly be lewd, because physical desire never gives them

rest. But they are told, do you know what lewdness is? It is a sin, a

vulgarity; it defiles us. If they were to say we don’t want lewd

interests to cause us to neglect other interests that are even more

important to us than the enjoyment of the senses, this would not be a

religious consideration, and they would make their sacrifice not to

chastity, but to other benefits of which they cannot deprive themselves.

But if instead they deny their natural impulse for the sake of chastity,

this occurs due to religious considerations. What interest do they have

in chastity? Unquestionably, no natural interest, because their nature

advises them to be lewd: their actual, unmistakable and undeniable

interest is lewdness. But chastity is a scruple of their spirit, because

it is an interest of the spirit, a spiritual interest: it is an absolute

interest before which natural and “private” interests must remain

silent, and which makes the spirit scrupulous. Now some throw off this

scruple with a “jerk” and the cry: “How stupid!” because, however

scrupulous or religious they may be, here an instinct tells them that

the spirit is a grouchy despot opposed to natural desire — whereas

others overcome this scruple by thinking more deeply and even reassure

themselves theoretically: the former overcome the scruples; the latter —

thanks to their virtuosity of thinking (which makes thinking a need and

a thing of interest for them) — dissolve the scruple. Thus, lewdness and

the courtesan only look so bad because they offend the “eternal

interest” of chastity.[4]

The spirit alone has raised difficulties and created scruples; and from

this it seems to follow that they could only be eliminated by means of

the spirit or thought. How bad it would be for those poor souls who have

let themselves be talked into accepting these scruples without

possessing the strength of thought necessary to become the masters of

the same! How horrible if, in this instance they would have to wait

until pure critique gave them their freedom! But sometimes these people

help themselves with a healthy, homemade levity, which is just as good

for their needs as free thought is for pure critique, since the critic,

as a “virtuoso” of thought, possesses an undeniable impulse to overcome

scruples through thought.

Scruples are as much an everyday occurrence as talking and chatting; so

what could one say against them? Nothing; only everyday scruples are not

sacred scruples. Everyday scruples come and go, but sacred scruples last

and are absolute; they are scruples in the absolute sense (dogmas,

articles of faith, basic principles). Against them, the egoist, the

desecrator, rebels and tests his egoistic force against their sacred

force. All “free thought” is a desecration of scruples and an egoistic

effort against their sacred force. If, after a few attacks, much free

thought has come to a stop, after a few attacks, before a new sacred

scruple, which would disgrace egoism, nonetheless free thought in its

freest form (pure critique) will not stop before any absolute scruple,

and with egoistic perseverance desecrates one scrupulous sanctity after

another. But since this freest thought is only egoistic thought, only

mental freedom, it becomes a sacred power of thought and announces the

Gospel that only in thought can one find redemption. Now even thought

itself appears only as a sacred thing, as a human calling, as a sacred

scruple: hereafter, only a scruple (a realization) dissolves scruples.

If scruples could only be dissolved through thought, people would never

be “mature” enough to dissolve them.

Scrupulousness, even if it has achieved the pure scruple or purity of

critique, is still only religiosity; the religious is the scrupulous.

But it remains scrupulousness, when one thinks one is only able to put

an end to scruples through scruples, when one despises a “convenient”

lack of scruples as the “egoistic aversion to work of the mass.”

In scrupulous egoism, all that is missing for putting the emphasis on

egoism rather than scrupulousness and seeing egoism as the victor is the

recognition of the lack of scruples. So it doesn’t matter whether it

wins through thought or through a lack of scruples.

Is thought perhaps “rejected” through this? No, only its sanctity is

denied, it is rejected as a purpose and a calling. As a means it is left

to everyone who gains might through this means. The aim of thought is

rather the loss of scruples, because the thinker in every instance

starts out, with his thought on this, to finally find the right point or

to get beyond thought and put an end to this matter. But if one

sanctifies the “labor of thought,” or, what is the same, calls it

“human,” one no less gives a calling to human beings than if one

prescribed faith to them, and this leads them away from the lack of

scruples, rather than leading them to it as the real or egoistic meaning

of thought. One misleads people into scrupulousness and deliberation, as

one promises them “well-being” in thought; weak thinkers who let

themselves be misled can do nothing more than comfort themselves with

some thought due to their weak thinking, i.e., they can only become

believers. Instead of making light of scruples, they become scrupulous,

because they imagine that their well-being lies in thought. (Footnote:

The religious turmoil of our times has its reason in this: it is a

immediate expression of this scrupulousness).

But scruples, which thought created, now exist and can certainly be

eliminated through thought. But this thought, this critique, achieves

this aim only when it is egoistic thought, egoistic critique, i.e., when

egoism or self-interest is asserted against scruples or against the

uninteresting, when self-interest is openly professed, and the egoist

criticizes from the egoistic viewpoint, rather than from the christian,

socialist, humanist, human, free thought, spiritual, etc., viewpoint

(i.e., like a christian, a socialist, etc.), because the self-interest

of the unique, thus your self-interest, gets trampled underfoot

precisely in the sacred, or human, world, and this same world, which

Hess and Szeliga for example, reproach as being egoist, on the contrary

has bound the egoist to the whipping post for thousands of years and

fanatically sacrificed egoism to every “sacred” thing that has rained

down from the realm of thought and faith. We don’t live in an egoistic

world, but in a world that is completely sacred down to its lowest scrap

of property.

It might seem that it must, indeed, be left to every individual to rid

himself of scruples as he knows how, but that it is still the task of

history to dissolve scruples through critical reflection. But this is

just what Stirner denies. Against this “task of history,” he maintains

that the history of scruples and the reflections that relate to them is

coming to an end. Not the task of dissolving, but the capriciousness

that makes short work of scruples, not the force of thought, but the

force of a lack of scruples seems to come into play. Thinking can serve

only to reinforce and ensure the lack of scruples. “Free thought” had

its starting point in unscrupulous egoistic revolt against sacred

scruples; it started from the lack of scruples. Anyone who thinks freely

makes no scruples over the most sacred of scruples: the lack of scruples

is the spirit and the egoistic worth of free thought. The worth of this

thought lies not in the thinker, but in the egoist, who egoistically

places his own power, the force of thought, above sacred scruples, and

this doesn’t weaken you and me at all.

To describe this lack of scruples, Stirner uses (p. 197) expressions

like “jerk, leap, jubilant whoop,” and says “the vast significance of

unthinking jubilation could not be recognized in the long night of

thinking and believing.” He meant nothing less by this than, first of

all, the hidden, egoistic basis of each and every critique of a sacred

thing, even the blindest and most obsessed, but in the second place, the

easy form of egoistic critique, which he tried to carry out by means of

his force of thought (a naked virtuosity). He strove to show how a

person without scruples could use thought as a critique of scruples from

his own viewpoint, as the unique. Stirner didn’t leave the “deliverance

of the world” in the hands of thinkers and the scrupulous anymore.

Jubilation and rejoicing becomes a bit ridiculous when one contrasts

them with the mass and volume of deep scruples that still cannot be

overcome with so little effort. Of course, the mass of scruples

accumulated in history and continually reawakened by thinkers cannot be

eliminated with mere rejoicing. Thinkers cannot get past it if their

thinking does not receive full satisfaction at the same time, since the

satisfaction of their thinking is their actual interest. Thought must

not be suppressed by jubilation, in the way that, from the point of view

of faith, it is supposed to be suppressed by faith. Anyway, as an actual

interest and, therefore, your interest, you can’t let it be suppressed.

Since you have the need to think, you cannot limit yourself to driving

scruples out through jubilation; you also need to think them away. But

it is from this need that Stirner’s egoistic thought has arisen, and he

made a first effort, even if still very clumsy, to relate the interests

of thought to unscrupulous egoism, and his book was supposed to show

that uncouth jubilation still has the potential, if necessary, to become

critical jubilation, an egoistic critique.

Self-interest forms the basis of egoism. But isn’t self-interest in the

same way a mere name, a concept empty of content, utterly lacking any

conceptual development, like the unique? The opponents look at

self-interest and egoism as a “principle.” This would require them to

understand self-interest as an absolute. Thought can be a principle, but

then it must develop as absolute thought, as eternal reason; the I,

should it be a principle, must, as the absolute I, form the basis of a

system built upon it. So one could even make an absolute of

self-interest and derive from it as “human interest” a philosophy of

self-interest; yes, morality is actually the system of human interest.

Reason is one and the same: what is reasonable remains reasonable

despite all folly and errors; “private reason” has no right against

universal and eternal reason. You should and must submit to reason.

Thought is one and the same: what is actually thought is a logical truth

and despite the opposing manias of millions of human beings is still the

unchanging truth; “private” thought, one’s view, must remain silent

before eternal thought. You should and must submit to truth. Every human

being is reasonable, every human being is human only due to thought (the

philosopher says: thought distinguishes the human being from the beast).

Thus, self-interest is also a universal thing, and every human being is

a “self-interested human being.” Eternal interest as “human interest”

kicks out against “private interest,” develops as the “principle” of

morality and sacred socialism, among other things, and subjugates your

interest to the law of eternal interest. It appears in multiple forms,

for example, as state interest, church interest, human interest, the

interest “of all,” in short, as true interest.

Now, does Stirner have his “principle in this interest, in the interest?

Or, contrarily, doesn’t he arouse your unique interest against the

“eternally interesting” against — the uninteresting? And is your

self-interest a “principle,” a logical — thought? Like the unique, it is

a phrase — in the realm of thought; but in you it is unique like you

yourself.

It is necessary to say a further word about the human being. As it

seems, Stirner’s book is written against the human being. He has drawn

the harshest judgments for this, as for the word “egoist,” and has

aroused the most stubborn prejudices. Yes, the book actually is written

against the human being, and yet Stirner could have gone after the same

target without offending people so severely if he had reversed the

subject and said that he wrote against the inhuman monster. But then he

would have been at fault if someone misunderstood him in the opposite,

i.e., the emotional way, and placed him on the list of those who raise

their voice for the “true human being.” But Stirner says: the human

being is the inhuman monster; what the one is, the other is; what is

said against the one, is said against the other.

If a concept lacks an essence, nothing will ever be found that

completely fits that concept. If you are lacking in the concept of human

being, it will immediately expose that you are something individual,

something that cannot be expressed by the term human being, thus, in

every instance, an individual human being. If someone now expects you to

be completely human and nothing but human, nonetheless you wouldn’t be

able to strip yourself of your individuality, and precisely because of

this individuality, you would be an inhuman monster, i.e. a human being

who is not truly human, or a human being who is actually an inhuman

monster. The concept of human being would have its reality only in the

inhuman monster.

The fact that every actual human being, measured by the concept of human

being, is an inhuman monster, was expressed by religion with the claim

that all human beings “are sinners” (the consciousness of sin); today

the sinner is called an egoist. And what has one decided in consequence

of this judgment? To redeem the sinner, to overcome egoism, to find and

realize the true human being. One rejected the individual, i.e., the

unique, in favor of the concept; one rejected the inhuman monster in

favor of the human being, and didn’t recognize that the inhuman monster

is the true and only possible reality of the human being. One absolutely

wanted a truly human reality of human beings.

But one aspired to an absurdity. The human being is real and actual in

the inhuman monster; every inhuman monster is — a human being. But you

are an inhuman monster only as the reality of the human being, an

inhuman monster only in comparison to the concept of human being.

You are an inhuman monster, and this is why you are completely human, a

real and actual human being, a complete human being. But you are even

more than a complete human being, you are an individual, a unique human

being. Human being and inhuman monster, these contrasts from the

religious world lose their divine and diabolical, and thus their sacred

and absolute, meaning, in you, the unique.

The human being, which our saints agonize so much to recognize, insofar

as they always preach that one should recognize the human being in the

human being, gets recognized completely and actually only when it is

recognized as the inhuman monster. If it is recognized as such, all

religious or “human” impositions cease, and the domination of the good,

the hierarchy, comes to an end, because the unique, the altogether

common human being (not Feuerbach’s virtuous “common man”[5]), is at the

same time the complete human being.

While Stirner writes against the human being, at the same time and in

the same breath, he writes against the inhuman monster, as opposed to

the human being; but he doesn’t write against the human being who is an

inhuman monster or the inhuman monster who is a human being — i.e., he

writes for the utterly common unique, who is a complete human being for

himself anyhow, because he is an inhuman monster.

Only pious people, sacred socialists, etc., only “saints” of every kind

prevent the human being from being recognized and appreciated in the

human being. They alone paralyze pure human intercourse, as they have

always limited common egoistic intercourse and strive to limit it. They

have introduced a sacred intercourse, and where possible they would like

to make it the Holy of Holies.

Actually, Szeliga also says various things about what the egoist and

egoism are, but he has exhausted the topic with his example of the rich

girl and the nagging wife. He depicts the egoist as having a horror of

work, as a man who “hopes that roasted pigeons will fly into his mouth,”

who “preserves nothing worthy of the name of hope,” etc. By this he

means a man who wants to live comfortably. If instead he’d defined the

egoist as a sleepyhead, it would have been even clearer and simpler.

Just as Szeliga betrays that his egoist can only be measured by an

absolute, insofar as he measures him by “real hopes,” Feuerbach, who is

generally more the master of the appropriate word, repeats the same

thing in an even more determined way, saying of the selfish person (the

egoist) that “he sacrifices what is higher to what is lower”; and of the

unselfish person that he “sacrifices the lower thing to the higher

thing.” What is “higher and lower”? Isn’t it something which is directed

toward you and of which you are the measure? If something was worthwhile

for you, and precisely for you in this moment — because you are you only

in the moment, only in the moment are you actual; as a “universal you,”

you would instead be “another” in each moment — if it counted for you at

this moment as somewhat “higher” than something else, you would not

sacrifice it to the latter. Rather, in each moment, you sacrifice only

what in that precise moment seems “lower” or less important to you.

Thus, if Feuerbach’s “higher thing” is supposed to have a meaning, it

has to be a higher thing separate and free from you, from the moment; it

has to be an absolute higher thing. An absolute higher thing is such

that you are not asked if it is the higher thing for you; rather it is

the higher thing despite you. Only in this way can one speak of a higher

thing and a “more elevated enjoyment” that “is sacrificed.” In

Feuerbach, such a “higher thing” is the enjoyment of the beloved in

contrast to the enjoyment of the courtesan, or the lover in contrast to

the courtesan; the first is higher, the second lower. If for you perhaps

the courtesan is the higher pleasure, because for you in the moment, she

is the only pleasure you desire, what does this matter to great noble

hearts like Feuerbach, who take pleasure only in the “beloved” and

decree, with the measure of their pure hearts, the beloved must be the

higher thing! Only the one who is attached to a beloved, and not a

courtesan, “satisfies his full, complete essence.” And in what does this

full, complete essence consist? Certainly not in your essence of the

moment, in what you are right now in essence, nor even in the essence

that you are generally, but rather in the “human essence.” For the human

essence the beloved is the highest. — So who is the egoist in

Feuerbach’s sense? The one who sins against “the higher thing” against

the absolute higher thing (i.e., higher in spite of your opposing

interest), against the uninteresting; thus, the egoist is — the sinner.

The same would be true of Szeliga’s egoist, if he had more power over

his expressions.

Hess is the one who says most unequivocally that the egoist is the

sinner. Of course, in saying this, Hess also confesses in a complete and

undisguised way that he has not, even distantly, understood what

Stirner’s book is getting at. Doesn’t Stirner deny that the egoist is

the sinner and that conscious egoism (conscious is the sense that Hess

intends it) is the consciousness of sin? If a European kills a

crocodile, he acts as an egoist against crocodiles, but he has no

scruples about doing this, and he is not accused of “sin” for it. If

instead an ancient Egyptian, who considered the crocodile to be sacred,

had nonetheless killed one in self-defense, he would have, indeed,

defended his skin as an egoist, but at the same time, he would have

committed a sin; his egoism would have been sin, — he, the egoist, a

sinner. — From this, it should be obvious that the egoist is necessarily

a sinner before what is “sacred,” before what is “higher”; if he asserts

his egoism against the sacred, this is, as such, a sin. On the other

hand, though, that is only a sin insofar as it is measured by the

criterion of the “sacred,” and the only egoist who drags the

“consciousness of sin” along with him is the one who is possessed at the

same time by the consciousness of the sacred. A European who kills a

crocodile is aware of his egoism in doing this, i.e., he acts as a

conscious egoist; but he doesn’t imagine that his egoism is a sin and he

laughs at the Egyptian’s consciousness of sin.

Against the “sacred,” the egoist is always a sinner; toward the

“sacred,” he can’t become anything other than — a criminal. The sacred

crocodile marks the human egoist as the human sinner. The egoist can

cast off the sinner and the sin from himself only if he desecrates the

sacred, just as the European beats the crocodile to death without sin

because His Holiness, the Crocodile, is for him a crocodile without

holiness.

Hess says: “Today’s mercantile world is the conscious and basic mediated

form of egoism, corresponding to its essence.” This present world, which

is full of philanthropy, completely agrees with socialism in principle

(see, for example, in the Gesellschaftsspiegel [Society Mirror] or the

WestphÀlischen Dampfboot [Westphalian Steamboat][6], how socialist

principles are completely the same as the “Sunday thoughts” and ideals

of all good citizens or bourgeois) — this world in which the great

majority can be brought to give up their advantages in the name of

sacred things and where the ideals of brotherhood, philanthropy, right,

justice, the ideals of being and doing for others, etc., don’t just pass

from one person to another, but are a horrible and ruinous seriousness —

this world that yearns for true humanity and hopes to finally find true

redemption through socialists, communists, philanthropists of every sort

— this world in which socialist endeavors are nothing but the obvious

sense of the “shopkeeper’s soul” and are well-received by all

right-thinking people — this world whose principle is the “welfare of

all people” and the “welfare of humanity,” and that only dreams of this

welfare because it doesn’t yet know how it is supposed to produce this

welfare and does not yet trust in the socialist actualization of its pet

idea — this world that lashes out violently against all egoism, Hess

vilifies as an “egoistic” world. And yet, he is right. Because the world

is agitating against the devil, the devil sits on its neck. Only Hess

should have reckoned sacred socialism along with this egoistic,

sin-conscious world.

Hess calls free competition the complete form of murder with robbery and

also the complete consciousness of the mutual human alienation (i.e.,

egoism). Here again, egoism should still be guilty. Why then did one

decide on competition? Because it seemed useful to each and all. And why

do socialists now want to abolish it? Because it doesn’t provide the

hoped-for usefulness, because the majority do badly from it, because

everyone wants to improve his position and because the abolition of

competition seems advisable for this purpose.

Is egoism the “basic principle” of competition, or, on the contrary,

haven’t egoists just miscalculated about this? Don’t they have to give

it up precisely because it doesn’t satisfy their egoism?

People introduced competition because they saw it as well-being for all;

they agreed upon it and experimented collectively with it. This thing,

this isolation and separation, is itself a product of association,

agreement, shared convictions, and it didn’t just isolate people, but

also connected them. It was a legal status, but this law was a common

tie, a social federation. In competition, people come to agreement

perhaps in the way that hunters on a hunt may find it good for the hunt

and for each of their respective purposes to scatter throughout the

forest and hunt “in isolation.” But what is most useful is open to

argument. And now, sure enough, it turns out — and, by the way,

socialists weren’t the first ones to discover it — that in competition,

not everyone finds his profit, his desired “private advantage,” his

value, his actual interest. But this comes out only through egoistic or

selfish calculations.

But meanwhile, some have prepared their own depiction of egoism and

think of it as simply “isolation.” But what in the world does egoism

have to do with isolation? Do I become an egoist like this, by fleeing

from people? I may isolate myself or get lonely, but I’m not, for this

reason, a hair more egoistic than others who remain among people and

enjoy contact with them. If I isolate myself, this is because I no

longer find pleasure in society, but if instead I remain among people,

it is because they still offer me a lot. Remaining is no less egoistic

than isolating oneself.

Of course, in competition everyone stands alone; but if competition

disappeared because people see that cooperation is more useful than

isolation, wouldn’t everyone still be an egoist in association and seek

his own advantage? Someone will object that one seeks it at the expense

of others. But one won’t seek it at the expense of others, because

others no longer want to be such fools as to let anyone live at their

expense.

But “the egoist is someone who thinks only of himself!” — This would be

someone who doesn’t know and relish all the joys that come from

participation with others, i.e., from thinking of others as well,

someone who lack countless pleasures — thus a poor sort. But why should

this desolate loner be an egoist in comparison to richer sorts?

Certainly, for a long time, we were able to get used to considering

poverty a disgrace, as a crime, and the sacred socialists have clearly

proven that the poor are treated like a criminals. But sacred socialists

treat those who are in their eyes contemptibly poor in this way, just as

much as the bourgeoisie do it to their poor.

But why should the person who is poorer with respect to a certain

interest be called more egoistic than the one who possesses that

interest? Is the oyster more egoistic that the dog; is the Moor more

egoistic than the German; is the poor, scorned, Jewish junkman more

egoistic than the enthusiastic socialist; is the vandal who destroys

artworks for which he feels nothing more egoistic than the art

connoisseur who treats the same works with great love and care because

he has a feeling and interest for them? And now if someone — we leave it

open whether such a one can be shown to exist — doesn’t find any “human”

interest in human beings, if he doesn’t know how to appreciate them as

human beings, wouldn’t he be a poorer egoist with regard to this

interest rather than being, as the enemies of egoism claim, a model of

egoism? One who loves a human being is richer, thanks to this love, than

another who doesn’t love anyone. But there is no distinction between

egoism and non-egoism in this at all, because both are only pursuing

their own interest.

But everyone should have an interest in human beings, love for human

beings!

But see how far you get with this “should,” with this law of love. For

two millennia this commandment has been led people by the heart, and

still today, socialists complain that our proletarians get treated with

less love than the slaves of the ancients, and yet these same socialists

still raise their voices quite loudly in favor of this — law of love.

If you want people to take an interest in you, draw it out of them and

don’t remain uninteresting sacred beings holding out your sacred

humanity like a sacred robe and crying like beggars: “Respect our

humanity, that is sacred!”

Egoism, as Stirner uses it, is not opposed to love nor to thought; it is

no enemy of the sweet life of love, nor of devotion and sacrifice; it is

no enemy of intimate warmth, but it is also no enemy of critique, nor of

socialism, nor, in short, of any actual interest. It doesn’t exclude any

interest. It is directed against only disinterestedness and the

uninteresting; not against love, but against sacred love, not against

thought, but against sacred thought, not against socialists, but against

sacred socialists, etc.

The “exclusiveness” of the egoist, which some want to pass off as

isolation, separation, loneliness, is on the contrary full participation

in the interesting by — exclusion of the uninteresting.

No one gives Stirner credit for his global intercourse and his union of

egoists from the largest section of his book, “My Intercourse.”

With regard to the three opponents specifically mentioned it would be a

tedious task to go through all the twisted passages of their writings.

In the same way, I have little intention at this time of more closely

examining the principles that they represent or would like to represent,

specifically Feuerbach’s philosophy, pure critique and socialism. Each

of these deserves a treatise of its own, for which another occasion may

well be found. Therefore, we add only a few considerations.

Szeliga

Szeliga starts this way: “Pure critique has shown, etc.,” as if Stirner

hadn’t spoken about this subject (e.g., on page 469 of The Unique). In

the first two pages, Szeliga presents himself as the “critic whom

critique leads to sit down as one with the object being observed, to

recognize it as mind born of mind, enter into the innermost depths of

the essence he is to fight, etc.” Szeliga hasn’t in the least entered

into the innermost depths of Stirner’s book, as we’ve shown, and so we

would like to consider him here not as the pure critic, but simply as

one of the mass who wrote a review of the book. We’ll look to see if

Szeliga does what he would have critique do, without noting whether

critique would do the same thing, and so instead of saying, for example,

this “critique will follow the life course of the unique,” we will say:

“Szeliga will follow, etc.”

When Szeliga expresses one of his thoughts in a completely conceptual

way with the word “ape,” one could say that pure critique expresses a

similar thought with a different word; but words aren’t indifferent for

either Szeliga or critique, and one would be doing wrong to critique if

one tried to impose Szeliga’s “ape” upon its thought which might be

differently nuanced: the ape is the true expression of thought only for

Szeliga.

From page 24 to page 32, Szeliga expressly takes the cause of pure

critique. But wouldn’t pure critique perhaps find this poetic manner of

taking its cause quite awkward?

We don’t welcome his invocation of the Critical Muse, which is supposed

to have inspired or “gave rise to” him, and pass over everything that he

says in praise of his muse, even “the new action of self-perfecting for

which the unique (i.e., Stirner, whom Szeliga, Feuerbach and Hess call

the “unique”) gives him the opportunity.”

One can see how Szeliga is able to keep up with the life course of the

unique if one compares, for example, the first paragraph on page 6 of

his writing with pages 468–478 of The Unique [in “My Self-Enjoyment”].

Szeliga opposes the courage of thinking to Stirner’s

“thoughtlessness”[7] as if to a kind of cowardice. But why doesn’t he

“enter into the innermost depths of the essence he is to fight”; why

doesn’t he examine whether this thoughtlessness doesn’t get along quite

well with the courage of thinking? He should have precisely “sat down as

one with the object being observed.” But who could ever enjoy sitting

down as one with an object as despicable as thoughtlessness. The mere

need to name it makes one want to spit it out.

Stirner says of pure critique: “From the standpoint of thought, there is

no force at all that can be higher than your own, and it is a pleasure

to see how easily and playfully this dragon devours every other worm of

thought[8].” Since Szeliga presents the thing as if Stirner was also

acting as a critic, he thinks that “the unique (like an ape) entices the

Dragon — critique — and spurs it to devour the worms of thought,

starting with those of freedom and unselfishness.” But what critique

does Stirner apply? Most likely not pure critique, because this,

according to Szeliga’s own words, only fights against “particular”

freedom against “true” freedom, in order to “educate ourselves to the

idea of true, human freedom in general.” What does Stirner’s egoistic,

and so not at all “pure,” critique have to do with the “idea of

unselfish, true, human freedom,” with the freedom “which is not a fixed

Idea, because (a very pointed reason) it is not fixed in the state or in

society or in a creed or in any other particularity, but is recognized

in every human being, in all self-consciousness, and leaves to everyone

the measure his freedom, but at the same time measures him according to

its measure?” (The idea of freedom, which recognizes itself and measures

every human being according to the mass, in which he is included. Just

as God recognizes himself and measures human beings according to the

mass, giving each their measure of freedom as he divides them into the

unrepentant and the elect.)

On the other hand, the unique “should have loosed the dragon, critique,

against another worm of thought, right and law.” But again, this is not

pure critique, but self-interested critique. If Stirner practiced pure

critique, then he would have to, as Szeliga expresses it, “demand the

renunciation of privilege, of right based on violence, the renunciation

of egoism”; thus, he would have to lead “true, human” right in the

struggle against that “based on violence,” and admonish people that they

should adhere to the true right. Stirner never uses pure critique, never

goads this dragon to do anything, has no need of it and never achieves

his results by means of the “progressive purity of critique.” Otherwise,

he would also have to imagine like Szeliga, for example, that “love must

be a new creation which critique tries to lead to the heights.” Stirner

doesn’t have such Szeligian magnificence, as “true freedom, the

suppression of egoism, the new creation of love,” in mind at all.

As we said, we’ll pass over the passages in which Szeliga really

campaigns against Stirner for the cause of critique, as one would have

to attack nearly every sentence. “Work avoidance, laziness, idle

essence, corruption” play a particularly lovely role in these passages;

but then he also speaks of the “science of human beings” which the human

being must create from the concept of “human being,” and on page 32 he

says: “The human being to discover is no longer a category, and

therefore not something particular outside of the human being.” If

Szeliga had understood that since the unique is a completely empty term

or category, it is therefore no longer a category, he might have

acknowledged it as “the name of that which for him is still nameless.”

But I fear he doesn’t know what he’s saying when he says: “no longer a

category.”

Finally, “the new act of self-perfection, in which the unique gave

opportunity to pure critique,” consists in this, that “the world, which

the unique completes, has in him and through him given its fullest

denial,” and that “critique can only bid farewell to it, to this old

exhausted, shattered, corrupted world.” Such a courteous

self-perfection!

Feuerbach

Whether Stirner has read and understood Feuerbach’s The Essence of

Christianity could only be demonstrated by a particular critique of that

book, which shouldn’t be set forth here. Therefore, we’ll limit

ourselves to a few points.

Feuerbach believes that he is speaking in Stirner’s sense when he says:

“This is precisely a sign of Feuerbach’s religiosity, of his

restriction, that he is still infatuated with an object, that he still

wants something, still loves something — a sign that he has still not

risen to the absolute idealism of egoism.” But has Feuerbach even looked

at the following passages from The Unique? “The meaning of the law of

love may be this: every human being must have Something that stands

above him.” (p. 381). This Something of sacred love is the spook. “The

one who is full of sacred (religious, moral, human) love, loves only the

spook, etc.” (p. 383). A bit later, on pages 383–395, for example: “It

is not as my feeling that love becomes an obsession, but through the

alienation of the object, through the absolute love-worthy object, etc.”

“My love is my own when it exists in a particular and egoist interest;

consequently, the object of my love is actually my object or my

property.” “I’ll stick with the old love song and love my object,”

thence my “something.”

Where Stirner says: “I have based my cause on nothing,” Feuerbach makes

it “the Nothing,” and so concludes from this that the egoist is a pious

atheist. However, the Nothing is a definition of God. Here Feuerbach

plays with a word with which Szeliga (on page 33 of the “Nordeutsche

BlĂ€tter”) struggles in a Feuerbachian way. Furthermore, Feuerbach says

on page 31 of The Essence of Christianity: “The only true atheist is the

one for whom the attributes of the divine essence, like love, wisdom,

justice are nothing, and not the one for whom only the subject of these

attributes is nothing.” Doesn’t Stirner achieve this, especially if the

Nothing is not loaded on him in place of nothing?

Feuerbach asks: “How does Feuerbach allow (divine) attributes to

remain?” and answers: “Not in this way, as attributes of God, no, but as

attributes of nature and humanity, as natural, human properties. When

these attributes are transferred from God into the human being, they

immediately lose their divine character.” Stirner answers against it:

Feuerbach allows the attributes to exist as ideals — as essential

determinations of the species, which are “imperfect” in individual human

beings and only become perfect “in the mass of the species,” as the

“essential perfection of perfect human beings,” thus as ideals for

individual human beings. He doesn’t allow them to continue to exist as

divine attributes, insofar as he doesn’t attribute them to their

subject, God, but as human attributes, insofar as he “transfers them

from God to the human being.” Now Stirner directs his attack precisely

against the human, and Feuerbach ingenuously comes back with the “human

being” and means that if only the attributes were made “human,” or moved

into the human being, they would immediately become completely “profane

and common.” But human attributes are not at all more common and profane

than divine attributes, and Feuerbach is still a long way from being “a

true atheist” in the way he defines it, nor does he want to be one.

“The basic illusion,” Feuerbach says, “is God as subject.” But Stirner

has shown that the basic illusion is rather the idea of “essential

perfection,” and that Feuerbach, who supports this basic prejudice with

all his might, is therefore, precisely, a true christian.

“Feuerbach shows,” he continues, “that the divine is not divine, God is

not God, but only the human essence loving itself, affirming itself and

appreciating itself to the highest degree.” But who is this “human

essence”? Stirner has shown that this human essence is precisely the

spook that is also called the human being, and that you, the unique

essence, are led to speak as a Feuerbachian by the attaching of this

human essence to “self-affirmation.” The point of contention that

Stirner raised is thus again completely evaded.

“The theme, the core of Feuerbach’s writing,” he continues, “is the

abolition of the split into an essential and non-essential I — the

deification of the human being, i.e., the positioning, the recognition

of the whole human being from head to foot. Isn’t the divinity of the

individual specifically announced at the end as the shattered secret of

religion?” “The only writing in which the slogan of modern times, the

personality, individuality, has ceased to be a senseless phrase is

precisely The Essence of Christianity.” But what the “whole human being”

is, what the “individual, personality, individuality” are, is shown in

the following: “For Feuerbach, the individual is the absolute, that is,

the true, actual essence. But why doesn’t he say: this exclusive

individual? Because, in that case, he wouldn’t know what he wanted —

from that standpoint, which he denies, he would sink back into the

religious standpoint.” — So “the whole human being” is not “this human

being,” not the common, criminal, self-seeking human being. Of course,

Feuerbach would fall into the religious standpoint that he rejects if he

described this exclusive individual as the “absolute essence.” But it

wouldn’t be because he was saying something about this individual, but

rather because he describes him as something religious (the “absolute

essence”) or rather uses his religious attributes for this, and secondly

because he “sets up an individual” as “sacred and untouchable by all

other individuals.” Thus, with the words cited above, nothing is said

against Stirner, since Stirner does not talk about a “sacred and

untouchable individual,” nor of an “incomparable and exclusive

individual that is God or can become God”; it doesn’t occur to him to

deny that the “individual” is “communist.” In fact, Stirner has granted

validity to the words “individual” and “particular person” because he

lets them sink into the expression “unique.” But in doing so, he does

what he recognizes specifically in the part of his book entitled “My

Power,” saying on page 275: “In the end, I still have to take back half

the style of expression that I wanted to make use of only so long as,

etc.”

When later, against Stirner’s statement, “I am more than a human being,”

Feuerbach raises the question: “Are you also more than male?,” one must

indeed write off the entire masculine position. He continues like this:

“Is your essence or rather — since the egoist scorns the word essence,

even though he uses it — [Stirner inserts:] perhaps Stirner only

cleanses it of the duplicity it has, for example, in Feuerbach, where it

seems as if he is actually talking of you and me when he speaks of our

essence, whereas instead he is talking about a completely subordinate

essence, namely the human essence, which he thus makes into something

higher and nobler. Instead of having you in mind — the essence, you, you

who are an essence, instead he concerns himself with the human being as

“your essence” and has the human being in mind instead of you. Stirner

uses the word essence, for example on page 56, saying: “You, yourself,

with your essence, are of value to me, for your essence is not something

higher, it is not higher and more universal than you. It is unique, as

you are, because it is you.” — [end of Stirner’s insertion] is your I

not masculine? Can you sever masculinity from what is called mind? Isn’t

your brain, the most sacred and elevated organ of your body,

definitively masculine? Are your feelings, your thoughts unmanly? Are

you merely a male animal, a dog, an ape, a stallion? What else is your

unique, incomparable, and consequently sexless I, but an undigested

residue of the old christian supernaturalism?”

If Stirner had said: You are more than a living essence or animal, this

would mean, you are still an animal, but animality does not exhaust what

you are. In the same way, he says: “You are more than a human being,

therefore you are also a human being; you are more than a male, but you

are also a male; but humanity and masculinity do not express you

exhaustively, and you can therefore be indifferent to everything that is

held up to you as ‘true humanity’ or ‘true masculinity.’ But you can

always be tortured and have tortured yourself with these pretentious

duties. Still today, holy people intend to grab hold of you with them.”

Feuerbach is certainly no mere animal male, but then is he nothing more

than a human male? Did he write The Essence of Christianity as a male,

and did he require nothing more than to be a male to write this book?

Instead, wasn’t this unique Feuerbach needed for that, and could even

another Feuerbach, Friedrich, for example — who is still also a male —

have brought it off? Since he is this unique Feuerbach, he is also, at

the same time, a human being, a male, a living essence, a Franconian,

etc. But he is more than all this, since these attributes have reality

only through his uniqueness. He is a unique male, a unique human being,

etc.; indeed, he is an incomparable male, an incomparable human being.

So what does Feuerbach want with his “consequently sexless I”? Since

Feuerbach is more than male, is he consequently sexless? Feuerbach’s

holiest, most elevated organ is undoubtedly manly, definitively manly,

and it is also, among other things, Caucasian, German, etc. But all this

is only true, because it is a unique thing, a distinct, unique thing, an

organ or brain which will not come forth a second time anywhere in the

world, however full the world may be of organs, of organs as such or of

absolute organs.

And is this unique Feuerbach supposed to be “an undigested residue of

old christian supernaturalism”?

From this, it is also quite clear that Stirner does not, as Feuerbach

says, “separate his I in thought from his sensible, male essence” just

as the refutation Feuerbach makes on page 200 of [Wigand’s] Quarterly

would collapse if Feuerbach didn’t present the unique wrongly, as

lacking individuality as he depicts it as sexless.

“To realize the species means to actualize an arrangement, a capacity, a

determination for human nature generally.” Rather, the species is

already realized through this arrangement; whereas what you make of this

arrangement is a realization of your own. Your hand is fully realized

for the purposes of the species, otherwise it wouldn’t be a hand, but

perhaps a paw. But when you train your hands, you do not perfect them

for the purposes of the species, you do not realize the species that is

already real and perfect, because your hand is what the species or the

species-concept of “hand” implies, and is thus a perfect hand — but you

make of them what and how you want and are able to make them; you shape

your will and power into them; you make the species hand into your own,

unique, particular hand.

“Good is what accords with the human being, what fits it; bad,

despicable, what contradicts it. Ethical relationships, e.g., marriage,

are thus not sacred for their own sake, but only for the sake of human

beings, because they are relationships between human beings, and thus

are the self-affirmation, the self-enjoyment of the human essence.” But

what if one were an inhuman monster who didn’t think these ethical

relations were fitting for him? Feuerbach will demonstrate to him that

they are fitting for the human being, the “actual sensual, individual

human essence,” and so also must fit him. This demonstration is so

thorough and practical that already for thousands of years, it has

populated the prisons with “inhuman monsters,” i.e., with people who did

not find fitting for them what was nonetheless fitting for the “human

essence.”

Of course, Feuerbach is not a materialist (Stirner never says he is, but

only speaks of his materialism clothed with the property of idealism);

he is not a materialist, because, although he imagines that he is

talking about the actual human being, he doesn’t say a thing about it.

But he is also not an idealist, because though he constantly talks about

the human essence, an idea, he makes out that he is talking about the

“sensual human essence.” He claims to be neither a materialist not an

idealist, and I’ll grant him this. But we will also grant what he

himself wants to be, and passes himself off as, in the end: he is a

“common man, a communist.” Stirner has already seen him as such, e.g., p

413.

About the point upon which alone this all would hang, namely Stirner’s

assertion that the human essence is not Feuerbach’s or Stirner’s or any

other particular human being’s essence, just as the cards are not the

essence of the house of cards; Feuerbach circles about this point,

indeed, he doesn’t get it at all. He sticks with his categories of

species and individual, I and thou, human being and human essence, with

complete complacency.

Hess

Hess has the “historical development of German philosophy behind him” in

his pamphlet, “The Last Philosophers,” but has before him “the

development of the philosophers Feuerbach, Bruno Bauer and Stirner,

disengaged from life” and knows from his own development, not exactly

disengaged from life, that the development of these philosophers “had to

turn into nonsense.” But is a development disengaged from life not

“nonsense,” and is a development not disengaged from life not likewise

“nonsense”? But, no, he has sense, because he flatters the sense of the

great masses which imagine that underneath the philosopher there is

always one who understands nothing of life.

Hess begins this way: “It never occurs to anyone to maintain that the

astronomer is the solar system that he has understood. But the

individual human being, who has understood nature and history, is

supposed to be the species, the all, according to our last German

philosophers.” But how, if the latter also never occurs to anyone? Who

has ever said that the individual human being is the species because he

has “understood” nature and history? Hess has said this and no one else.

He even cites Stirner as a reference, here: “As the individual is all

nature, so is he also the whole species.” But did Stirner say that the

individual first had to understand in order to be able to be the entire

species? Rather, Hess, this individual, actually is the entire “human”

species and can serve, with skin and hair, as a source for Stirner’s

statement. What would Hess be if he were not perfectly human, if he

lacked even the smallest thing for being human? He could be anything

except a human being; — he could be an angel, a beast or a depiction of

a human being, but he can only be a human being if he is a perfect human

being. The human being can be no more perfect than Hess is, there is no

more perfect human being than — Hess. Hess is the perfect human being,

or if one wants to use the superlative, the most perfect human being.

Everything, all that belongs to the human being is in Hess. Not even the

smallest crumb of what makes a human being human is missing in Hess. Of

course, the case is similar for every goose, every dog, every horse.

So is there no human being more perfect than Hess? As a human being —

none. As a human being, Hess is as perfect as — every human being, and

the human species contains nothing that Hess does not contain; he

carries it all around with him.

Here is another fact, that Hess is not just a human being, but an

utterly unique human being. However, this uniqueness never benefits the

human being, because the human being can never become more perfect than

it is. — We don’t want to go into this further, since what is said above

is enough to show how strikingly Hess can find Stirner guilty of

“nonsense” simply with an “understood solar system.” In an even clearer

way, on page 11 of his pamphlet, Hess exposes Stirner’s “nonsense” and

shouts with satisfaction: “This is the logic of the new wisdom!”

Hess’s expositions on the development of Christianity, as socialist

historical intuitions, don’t matter here; his characterization of

Feuerbach and Bruno Bauer is utterly the sort that would have to come

from one who has “laid philosophy aside.”

He says of socialism that “it carries out the realization and negation

of philosophy seriously and speaks not only of that, but of philosophy

as a mere apprenticeship to negate and to realize in social life.” He

could have also added that socialism wants to “realize” not only

philosophy, but also religion and Christianity. Nothing easier than

this, when, like Hess, one knows life, in particular the misery of life.

When the manufacturer, Hardy, in The Wandering Jew, falls into misery,

he is completely open to the teachings of the Jesuits, particularly when

he could hear all the same teachings, but in a “human,” melodious form,

from the “human” priest Gabriel. Gabriel’s lessons are more pernicious

than Rodin’s.

Hess quotes a passage from Stirner’s book, page 341, and deduces from it

that Stirner has nothing against “practically existing egoism, except

the lack of consciousness of egoism.” But Stirner doesn’t at all say

what Hess makes him say, that “all the errors of present day egoists

consist in not being conscious of their egoism.” In the passage cited,

Stirner says: “If only the consciousness of this existed.” Of what? Not

of egoism, but of the fact that grabbing is not a sin. And after

twisting Stirner’s words, Hess dedicates the entire second half of his

pamphlet to the struggle against “conscious egoism.” Stirner says in the

middle of the passage that Hess quotes: “One should simply know this,

that the technique of grabbing is not contemptible, but the clear act in

which some egoists agree among themselves to express themselves.” Hess

omits this, because he has no more understanding of egoists agreeing

among themselves than what Marx already said earlier about shopkeepers

and universal rights (for example in the Deutsch-Französischen

JahrbĂŒchern); Hess repeats this, but with none of the keen skill of his

predecessor. — Stirner’s “conscious egoist” doesn’t merely not adhere to

the consciousness of sin, but also to the consciousness of law, or of

universal human rights.

Hess finishes with Stirner like this: “No, you precocious child, I don’t

at all create and love in order to enjoy, I love from love, I create

from a creator’s desire, from a vital instinct, from an immediate

natural desire. When I love in order to enjoy, then I not only do not

love, but I also do not enjoy, etc.” But does Stirner challenge such

trivialities anywhere? Doesn’t Hess rather attribute “nonsense” to him

in order to be able to call him a “precocious child”? In other words,

“Precocious child” is the final judgment to which Hess comes, and he

repeats it in the conclusion. Through such final judgments, he manages

to put “the historical development of German philosophy behind him.”

On page 14, Hess lets “the species break up into individuals, families,

tribes, people, races.” This disintegration, he says, “this alienation

is the first form of the existence of the species. To come into

existence, the species must individualize itself.” From whence only Hess

knows all that the species “must” do. “Form of existence of the species,

alienation of the species, individualization of the species,” he gets

all this from the philosophy that he has put behind him, and to top it

off, commits his beloved “robbery with murder” insofar as he “robs”

this, for example, from Feuerbach and at the same time “murders”

everything in it that is actually philosophy. He could have learned

precisely from Stirner that the pompous phrase “alienation of the

species” is “nonsense,” but where could he have gotten the weapons

against Stirner if not from philosophy, which he has put behind him, of

course, through a socialist “robbery with murder” — ?

Hess closes the second part of his book with the discovery that

“Stirner’s ideal is bourgeois society, which takes the state to itself

.” Hegel has shown that egoism is at home in bourgeois society. Whoever

has now put Hegelian philosophy behind him, also knows, from this

philosophy behind him, that anyone who “recommends” egoism has his ideal

in bourgeois society. He will later take the opportunity to speak

extensively about bourgeois society; then it will seem that it is no

more the site of egoism than the family is the site of selflessness. The

sense of bourgeois society is rather the life of commerce, a life that

can be pursued by saints in sacred forms — as happens all the time today

— as by egoists in an egoistic form — as happens now only in the

activity of a few acting clandestinely. For Stirner, bourgeois society

does not at all lie at the heart, and he doesn’t at all think of

extending it so that it engulfs the state and the family. So Hess could

suspect such a thing about Stirner only because he came to him through

Hegelian categories.

The selfless Hess has become accustomed to a particular, gainful and

advantageous phrase by noting repeatedly that the poor Berliners get

hold of their wisdom from the Rhine, i.e., from Hess and the socialists

there, and also from France, but unfortunately through stupidity, these

beautiful things get ruined. So, for example, he says: “Recently, there

has been talk of the embodied individual among us; the actual human

being, the realization of the idea, so that it can be no surprise to us

if tidings of it have reached Berlin and there have moved certain

philosophical heads from their bliss. But the philosophical heads have

understood the thing philosophically.” — We had to mention this so much

to spread what is, for us, a well-deserved reputation; we add also that

already in the Rhenish Gazette, although not in “recent times,” the

actual human being and similar topics were spoken about a lot, and

exclusively by Rhenish correspondents.

Immediately thereafter, Hess wants “to make what he means by the actual,

living human being conceivable to philosophers.” Since he wants to make

it conceivable, he reveals that his actual human being is a concept,

thus not an actual human being. Rather, Hess himself is an actual human

being, but we want to grant him what he means by an actual human being,

since on the Rhine (“among us”), they speak about it enough.

Stirner says: “If you consume what is sacred, you have made it property!

You digest the host and you get rid of it!” Hess answers: “As if we

haven’t consumed our sacred property for a long time!” Of course, we

consumed property as a sacred thing, a sacred property; but we did not

consume its sacredness. Stirner says: “If you consume what is sacred

(Hess doesn’t take this with much precision and makes Stirner say

“sacred property” instead of “what is sacred”), you make it property,

etc.,” i.e., something (dirt, for example) that you can throw away.

“Reason and love are generally without reality,” Hess makes Stirner say.

But doesn’t he speak of my reason, my love? In me they are real, they

have reality.

“We may not develop our essence from the inside out,” Stirner is

supposed to say. Of course, you may develop your essence, but “our

essence,” “the human essence,” that is another thing, which the whole

first part of the book deals with. Anyway, Hess again makes no

distinction between your essence and our essence, and in doing so,

follows Feuerbach.

Stirner is accused of knowing only the beginnings of socialism, and even

these only through hearsay, otherwise he would have to know, for

example, that on the political terrain communism has already been

divided for quite some time into the two extremes of egoism (intĂ©rĂȘt

personnel[9]) and humanism (dévouement[10]). This contrast that is so

important for Hess, who may possibly know a thousand more things about

socialism than Stirner, although the latter has seen through socialism

better, was subordinated by Stirner, and could only have seemed

important to him if his thinking about egoism was as thoroughly unclear

as that of Hess.

The fact that Stirner, by the way, “knows nothing of society” is

something that all socialist and communists understand, and there is no

need for Hess to prove it. If Stirner had known anything about it, how

could he have dared to write against Your Holiness, and what’s more, to

write so ruthlessly, in so much detail!

Anyone who hasn’t read Stirner’s book immediately recognizes without

question how precisely he judged and how little he needed to justify the

following judgment: “Stirner’s opposition to the state is the utterly

common opposition of the liberal bourgeoisies who put the blame on the

state when people fall into poverty and starve.”

Hess reprimands Stirner like this: “Oh, unique, you are great, original,

brilliant! But I would have been glad to see your ‘union of egoists’,

even if only on paper. Since this isn’t granted to me, I will allow

myself to characterize the real concept of your union of egoists.” He

wants to characterize the “concept” of this union, indeed, he does

characterize it; saying authoritatively that it is “the concept of

introducing now in life the most uncouth form of egoism, wildness.”

Since the “concept” of this union is what interests him, he also

explains that he wants to see it on paper. As he sees in the unique

nothing but a concept, so naturally, this union, in which the unique is

the vital point, also had to become a concept for him. But if one

repeats Hess’s own words to him: “Recently, there has been talk of the

unique among us, and tidings of it have also reached Köln; but the

philosophical head in Köln has understood the thing philosophically,”

has a concept been preserved?

But he goes further and shows that “all our history up to now has been

nothing but the history of egoistic unions, whose fruit — ancient

slavery, medieval bondage and modern, fundamental, universal servitude —

are known to us all.” First of all, here Hess puts “egoistic union” —

because he needs to take it in precisely this way! — in place of

Stirner’s “union of egoists.” His readers, who he wants to persuade —

one sees in his preface what type of people he has to persuade, namely

people whose works, like those of Bruno Bauer, derive from an

“incitement to reaction,” in other words, exceptionally smart and

political heads) — these readers, of course, immediately find it correct

and beyond doubt that nothing but “egoistic unions” has ever existed. —

But is a union in which most of those involved are hoodwinked about

their most natural and obvious interests, a union of egoists? Have

“egoists” come together where one is the slave or serf of the other?

There are, it’s true, egoists in such a society, and in this sense, it

might in some aspects be called an “egoistic union”; but the slaves have

not really sought this society from egoism, and are instead, in their

egoistic hearts, against these lovely “unions,” as Hess calls them. —

Societies in which the needs of some get satisfied at the expense of

others, in which, for example, some can satisfy their need for rest only

by making others work until they are exhausted; or lead comfortable

lives by making others live miserably or perhaps even starve; or live

the high life because others are so addle-brained as to live in want,

etc. — Hess calls such societies egoistic unions, and since he is free

“of the secret police of his critical conscience,” impartially and

against police orders, he identifies this egoistic league of his with

Stirner’s union of egoists. Stirner probably also needs the expression

“egoistic union,” but it is explained first of all through the “union of

egoists,” and secondly, it is explained correctly, whereas what Hess

called by this name is rather a religious society, a community held in

sacred respect through rights, laws and all the formalities or

ceremonies of justice.

It would be another thing indeed, if Hess wanted to see egoistic unions

not on paper, but in life. Faust finds himself in the midst of such a

union when he cries: “Here I am human, here I can be human” — Goethe

says it in black and white. If Hess attentively observed real life, to

which he holds so much, he will see hundreds of such egoistic unions,

some passing quickly, others lasting. Perhaps at this very moment, some

children have come together just outside his window in a friendly game.

If he looks at them, he will see a playful egoistic union. Perhaps Hess

has a friend or a beloved; then he knows how one heart finds another, as

their two hearts unite egoistically to delight (enjoy) each other, and

how no one “comes up short” in this. Perhaps he meets a few good friends

on the street and they ask him to accompany them to a tavern for wine;

does he go along as a favor to them, or does he “unite” with them

because it promises pleasure? Should they thank him heartily for the

“sacrifice,” or do they know that all together they form an “egoistic

union” for a little while?

To be sure, Hess wouldn’t pay attention to these trivial examples, they

are so utterly physical and vastly distinct from sacred society, or

rather from the “fraternal, human society” of sacred socialists.

Hess says of Stirner: “he remains constantly under the secret police of

his critical conscience.” What is he saying here, if not that when

Stirner criticizes, he doesn’t want to go on a binge of critique, to

babble, but really just wants to criticize? Hess, however, would like to

show how right he is in not being able to find any difference between

Stirner and Bruno Bauer. But has he ever generally known how to find any

difference other than that between sacred socialists and “egoistic

shopkeepers”? And is even this difference anything more than

histrionics? What need does he have to find a difference between Bruno

Bauer and Stirner, since critique is undoubtedly — critique? Why, one

might ask, does Hess have to concern himself with such strange birds, in

whom, only with great difficult, will he ever find sense except by

attributing his own senseto them, as he did in his pamphlet, and who,

therefore, (as he says in his preface) “had to turn into nonsense” — why

since he has such a wide human field of the most human action before

him?

To close, it might not be inappropriate to remind the critics of

Feuerbach’s Critique of the Anti-Hegel, page 4.[11]

 

[1] However, outside of the title of Stirner’s book, I have chosen to

translate the word “Eigentum” as “property.” The word can also translate

as “possession” as in the phrase “to acquire possession of the book” or

as “ownership.” It is useful to keep all these translations in mind when

you read the word “property” in this text.

[2] I made use of the following online glossaries of Hegelian

terminology for this purpose:

www.london.ac.uk

;

www.class.uidaho.edu

;

web.mac.com

[3]

G. W. F. Hegel, Théodore F. Geraets (translator), Wallis Arthur

Suchting (translator), Henry Silton Harris (translator) The

Encyclopaedia Logic: Part I of the Encyclopaedia of

Philosophical Sciences with the ZusÀtze (Indianapolis,

1991), in “Notes to Glossary,” p. 351.

[4] Throughout this passage and the following several paragraphs,

Stirner is playing on the words “Bedenken” (scruples) and “Denken”

(thinking or thought), a bit of wordplay lost in translation. It also

helps to know that “Bedenken” can also translate as “reflection” or

“doubt,” and in some places, Stirner seems to play on all these meanings

as well. — translator

[5] This is the single instance where I have chosen to translate

“Mensch” as man, in order to emphasize the distinction Stirner is

making. He is emphasizing that what is actually “common” to every human

being is that he or she is unique, as opposed to Feuerbach’s idealized

concept of the “common man.” — translator.

[6] Two socialist/left democratic publications of the time. Moses Hess

published the first oF these.

[7] Or “mindlessness,” giving further evidence of Stirner’s familiarity

with eastern philosophy. However, in context, “thoughtlessness” works

better here. — translator

[8] “Worm” here is being used in its archaic sense of a specific type of

dragon... In the original Stirner uses “Drachen” and “WĂŒrm.” I have used

the corresponding terms in my translation. — translator

[9] “personal interest,” in French in the original — translator

[10] “devotion,” in French in the original — translator

[11] Perhaps a reference to this appropriate passage: “He always has

other things than his opponent in his head. He cannot assimilate his

ideas and consequently cannot make them out with his understanding. They

move in confusion like Epicurian atoms in the empty space of his own

self. And his understanding is the accident that brings them together

with special external expedient accents into an apparent whole.” —

translator’s note