💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › murray-bookchin-thoughts-on-libertarian-municipalism.gm… captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:36:38. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Thoughts on Libertarian Municipalism
Author: Murray Bookchin
Date: January 2000
Language: en
Topics: libertarian municipalism, Dual Power
Source: http://social-ecology.org/wp/1999/08/thoughts-on-libertarian-municipalism/

Murray Bookchin

Thoughts on Libertarian Municipalism

Age, chronic illnesses, and the summer heat oblige me to remain at

home—hence I am very sorry that I cannot participate in your conference

on libertarian municipalism. I would like, however—thanks to Janet

Biehl, who will read these remarks—to welcome you to Vermont and to wish

you well during the course of your discussions over the next three days.

Some issues have recently arisen in discussions of libertarian

municipalism, and I would like to offer my views on them. One of the

most important involves the distinction that should be drawn between

libertarian municipalism and communitarianism, a distinction that is

often lost in discussions of politics.

Communitarianism

By communitarianism, I refer to movements and ideologies that seek to

transform society by creating so-called alternative economic and living

situations such as food cooperatives, health centers, schools, printing

workshops, community centers, neighborhood farms, “squats,”

unconventional lifestyles, and the like. Allowing for the works of

Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, the notable spokespersons of communitarianism

have been Martin Buber, Harry Boyte, and Colin Ward, among many others.

The word communitarian is often interchangeable with the word

cooperative, a form of production and exchange that is attractive

because the work is not only amiably collective but worker-controlled or

worker-managed.

At most, communitarianism seeks to gently edge social development away

from privately owned enterprises—banks, corporations, supermarkets,

factories, and industrial systems of agriculture—and the lifeways to

which they give rise, into collectively owned enterprises and values. It

does not seek to create a power center that will overthrow capitalism;

it seeks rather to outbid it, outprice it, or outlast it, often by

presenting a moral obstacle to the greed and evil that many find in a

bourgeois economy. It is not a politics but a practice, whose

constituency is often a relatively small group of people who choose to

buy from or work in a particular cooperative enterprise.

Citing Proudhon as one of the fathers of communitarianism dates the

inception of this ideology and practice back about 150 years, to an age

when most workers were craftspersons and most food cultivators were

peasants. During the intervening years, many cooperatives have been

formed with the most far-reaching hopes and idealistic intentions—only

to fail, stagnate, or turn into profit-oriented enterprises. In order to

survive in the capitalist marketplace and withstand the competition of

larger, more predatory, profit-oriented enterprises, they have normally

been obliged to adapt to it.

Where cooperatives have been able to maintain themselves against

capitalist competition, they tend to become introverted, basically

centered on their internal problems and collective interests; and to the

extent that they link together, they do so in order to focus on ways and

means to stay alive or expand as enterprises. Above all, they rarely, if

ever, become centers of popular power—partly because they are not

concerned with addressing issues of power as such, and partly too

because they have no way of mobilizing people around visions of how

society should be controlled.

While working and/or living in cooperatives may be desirable in order to

imbue individuals with collectivist values and concerns, they do not

provide the institutional means for acquiring collective power.

Underpinning their social ideas—before these ideas fade into dim

memory—is the hope that they can somehow elbow capitalism out, without

having to confront capitalist enterprises and the capitalist state. Time

tends to increase these parochial tendencies, making cooperatives more

introverted, more parochial, more like collective capitalists than

social collectivists, and ultimately more capitalistic than socialistic

in their practices and interests.

Libertarian municipalism, by contrast, is decidedly a confrontational

form of face-to-face democratic, antistatist politics. Looking outward

to the entire municipality and beyond, it is decidedly concerned with

the all-important question of power, and it poses the questions: Where

shall power exist? By what part of society shall it be exercised?

Institutions and Constitutions

Above all, it asks, what institutions can make the exercise of

nonstatist power possible and effective? I once read a Spanish anarchist

slogan that declared: “Make war on institutions, not on people.” I find

this slogan disturbing because it implies that ideally people can

somehow become “autonomous” from institutional obligations, and that

institutions as such are straitjackets that prevent them from

discovering their “true selves” and engaging in self-determination.

No—this is grossly fallacious. Animals, to be sure, can live without

institutions (often because their behavior is imprinted in them

genetically), but human beings require institutions, however simple or

complex, to mold their societies. In a free society, these institutions

would be rationally constituted “forms of freedom” (as I called them

back in the 1960s) by which people would organize and express their own

powers collectively as well as personally.

Moreover, such a free society would have a constitution and laws,

formulated and adopted by directly democratic and discursive assemblies.

In the mid-19th century, while he was a member of the French Chamber of

Deputies, Proudhon refused to vote in favor of a draft Constitution that

was oriented toward the protection of property and the construction of a

State. While I approve of his negative vote, I thoroughly reject the

reasons he gave for it. “No!” he declared, “I did not vote against the

Constitution because it was good or bad, but because it was a

Constitution.” This frivolous behavior reduced him, intellectually as

well as politically, to the world of arbitrary power, against which

oppressed Greek peasants such as Hesiod had cried out in the eighth

century BCE, denouncing the “barons” who had all but enserfed and

exploited the Hellenic peasantry of the ancient world and demanding a

society based on laws, not on the whims of men.

Contrary to Proudhon and other anarchist theorists who have rejected

laws as such, constitutions and laws have long been demands of oppressed

people as instrumentalities for controlling, indeed eliminating, the

arbitrary power exercised by kings, tyrants, nobles, and dictators. To

ignore this historic fact and fall back on an “instinct for mutual aid”

as the basis for social organization, or “an instinct for revolution,”

or “an instinct for sharing” is to retreat from a much-desired civilized

world into the realm of animality, a social zoology that has no

application to humanity as a potentially innovative species that makes

and remakes both itself and the world.

Should Cooperative Work Precede Political Work?

Some libertarian municipalists have argued that before we seek political

power for our democratic ends, we must first “work over” a community by

participating in communitarian activities and establishing cooperatives

that will cement mutualistic ways of living throughout the community.

Only then, we are told, will a community be “ready” for a libertarian

municipalist effort. But do cooperatives really have mutualistic effects

on their communities?

Not necessarily—indeed, all too often, for those involved, forming and

maintaining a cooperative becomes an end in itself. When cooperatives do

manage to survive, their relations with other cooperatives become

strained—far from treating each other mutualistically, they turn their

faces against each other and even enter into mutual competition.

Moreover, a cooperative’s members often become an in-group in the very

community they had initially set out to educate—and they abdicate all

educational activities, having come to view the people in their

community solely as mere customers. Forced by capitalism to adopt

methods of capitalist organization, they hire managers and business

consultants of one kind or another—presumably in pursuit of

efficiency—with the result that, far from giving their community a

political education, they deceive it in their own interests, dressing up

their capitalist enterprise with the “virtuous” name cooperative instead

of openly calling themselves a company or corporation.

Libertarian municipalism tries in every way to avoid losing its identity

in the job of building, maintaining, and expanding cooperatives—and

thereby sinking into a communitarian morass. Rather, it seeks to recover

and to go beyond Aristotle’s definition of “man” as a zoon politikon, a

“political being.” In Aristotle’s Politics, “man,” or at least Greeks,

are meant to live in a polis (usually mistranslated as “city state”) or

a municipality. For Aristotle, this is one form of our actualization and

fulfillment as human beings. To use a religious term, human beings,

insofar as they realize their humanity, are destined to be polis– and

city-dwellers. Our teloi, which include a rationally and democratically

constituted system of laws—of duties as well as rights—include as well

this ability to be citizens, that is to say, to be educated in order to

be competent to assume all the obligations of self-government.

They must be capable intellectually as well as physically of performing

all the necessary functions in their community that today are undertaken

by the State—that apparatus of soldiers, police, bureaucrats,

legislative representatives and the like. The State justifies its

existence in great part not only on the indifference of its constituents

to public affairs but also—and significantly—on the alleged inability of

its constituents to manage public affairs. It claims to have a unique

competence, while considering its constituents to be incompetent

children who need competent “parents” to manage their affairs. Once

citizens are capable of self-management, however, the State can be

liquidated both institutionally and subjectively, replaced by free and

educated citizens in popular assemblies.

Education for Citizenship

If citizens are to be competent to replace the State, then education for

citizenship, or paideia, must be rigorous and involve the building of

character and ethical integrity as well as gaining knowledge. This is

even more the case when it comes to eliminating hierarchy. Rigorous

education and training, in turn, involve a systematic, carefully

planned, organized learning process. Citizens cannot be produced if the

education and training of the young occur in contexts where the

student—usually an inchoate self that has not yet been formed—is called

upon to “let everything hang out” in the name of “self-expression.” It

is precisely this concern for paideia that made Greek political

philosophy so great: it included educational ideas for the making of

competent citizens, who would not only think systematically but learn to

use weapons in their own defense and in defense of the democracy. The

Athenian democracy, let me note, was established when the aristocratic

cavalry was replaced by the hoplite footsoldier—the civic guard of the

fifth century BCE, which guaranteed the supremacy of the people over the

formerly supreme nobility.

Power and Polity

In contrast to communitarianism, libertarian municipalism is concerned

with the problem of power, especially how ordinary people can acquire

it. By power, I do not refer to the psychological feeling of empowerment

that one may gain from attending an inspiring meeting or rally. Some

fashionable forms of “self-empowerment” are often little more than

emotional highs that could more or less be acquired by taking drugs

Rather, I mean the tangible power embodied in organized forms of freedom

that are rationally conceived and democratically constituted. In

contrast to those who would simply use the demand for power as a means

to make propaganda and theater, or who would refuse to accept power,

even if offered, if they could potentially use it to empower the people

in popular assemblies, libertarian municipalism seeks to attain

collective, communal power.

A libertarian municipalist polity would thus be a constituted

community—one that has rationally and democratically created its own

constitution and laws; whose citizens have been fashioned ethically and

intellectually by the character-building process of paideia; and which,

because of its competence, armed power, democratic institutions, and

discursive approach to issues and problems can not only replace the

State but perform the socially necessary roles in the community formerly

taken over by the State.

This is the political realm, the authentic world of politics, in which

we are obliged to form a movement to recover and develop before it is

effaced entirely by a Disneyland world. To dissolve this political realm

into communitarian institutions and activities is to overlook the very

need to reestablish this realm, indeed to play the reactionary role of

diffusing it into an night where all is black and indistinguishable.

Dual Power

The issue of dual power should also be clarified, as this phrase has

recently been gaining currency in libertarian circles as a “theory.” The

Marxists, more specifically Trotsky, had no “theory” of dual power. The

notion of a “dual power” was well rooted in Russian socialist politics

long before Trotsky devoted a chapter to the concept in his History of

the Russian Revolution, a chapter that occupies a mere nine pages, most

of which are descriptive. The word dvoevlasty (“dual power”) was used by

Russian revolutionaries of all kinds as early as February 1917, simply

to describe the dual arrangement in which the Petrograd Soviet and the

Provisional Government tried to govern Russia—an arrangement that had

come to an end by the October Revolution.

As a “theory,” however, “dual power” was more popular in Germany and

Austria immediately after the First World War, in 1918-19, when the

Raete or councils were in vogue among theorists such as Rudolf

Hilferding, Karl Kautsky, and Victor Adler. These Austro-German Marxists

thought of dual power as a permanent condition consisting of permanent

councils, through which workers could express their interests, together

with parliamentary state, through which the bourgeoisie could express

its interests. These Social Democrats divested “dual power” of its

revolutionary tension, and the term became a synonym for a two-part

government that could conceivably have existed indefinitely.

In libertarian municipalism, dual power is meant to be a strategy for

creating precisely those libertarian institutions of directly democratic

assemblies that would oppose and replace the State. It intends to create

a situation in which the two powers—the municipal confederations and the

nation-state—cannot coexist, and one must sooner or later displace the

other. Moreover, it is a confluence of the means to achieve a rational

society with the structure of that society, once it is achieved. The

diremption between means and ends is a problem that has always plagued

the revolutionary movement, but the concept of dual power as a means to

a revolutionary end and the formation of a rational society overcomes

the chasm between the method for gaining a new society and the

institutions that would structure it.

“The streets will organize you!”

A very important problem in libertarian municipalism is the question of

what kind of movement can play the educational and, yes, leadership role

required to produce these transformations. Those who denounce

libertarian municipalism as “statist” often favor instead, not only

creating cooperatives, but engaging in episodic actions, especially in

the form of demonstrations and street festivals. Even worse, some of

them prefer to engage in passing attacks on “authority” by breaking

windows or taunting police—and then go home to watch these escapades on

television—as if “liberty” and “autonomy” could be so achieved or

inspire the people.

We must at the outset dissociate ourselves from a silly cry that was

voiced by I. S. Bleikhman, the supreme personality of the Petrograd

Anarchist Communists, in July 1917. In those insurgent “July Days,” the

Kronstadt sailors together with the Petrograd garrison and most advanced

workers decided to “come out” with arms in hand to establish a soviet

government. To their appeal for organization, Bleihkman responded: “The

streets will organize you!” The streets, of course, “organized”

absolutely nothing and no one—and partly for lack of a real leadership,

the July insurrection was crushed in only a few days.

In the course of closely studying the history of past revolutions, the

most important problem I have encountered has been precisely the issue

of organization. The issue is crucial, not least because in a

revolutionary upheaval the nature of organization can spell the

difference between life and death. What has become very clear in my own

mind is that revolutionaries need to create a very proactive

organization—a vanguard, to use a term widely used until the New Left

poisoned it by associating it with the Bolsheviks—that itself has its

own rigorous paideia; that creates a responsible membership of informed

and dedicated citizens; that has a structure and a program; and that

creates its own institutions, based on a rational constitution.

Such an organization might well be regarded as a polis-in-the-making

that, while building a libertarian municipalist movement, can safeguard

its basic principles from cooptation (the usual fate of good ideas these

days), nourish their development, and apply them in complex and

difficult situations. Without a clearly definable organization, a

movement is likely to fall into the tyranny of structurelessness.

I would like to point out that if one’s basic principles are not firm

and clear, then one has no basic principles at all. One is simply

floating in the air with mere opinions and off-the-cuff notions rather

than clear ideas, thought-out views, and substantive theories

constructed on solid foundations. One may decide to change one’s basic

principles, to be sure, which itself presupposes that one had definable

principles to begin with. But the prevalence of undefined and unfixed

notions reflects the contemporary postmodern invertebrate mentality that

regards everything as relative; that rejects the existence of

fundamentals; that fosters formless, amoebic ideas; that condemns

structure as authoritarian or even totalitarian; and that regards

feelings are more important than careful thought.

Ideas are becoming cheap opinions, and principles are becoming ephemeral

slogans, which is all the more reason why we should affirm our ideas and

theories clearly. Not only for political reasons but also for cultural

ones, it is the responsibility of a libertarian municipal movement based

on Communalist principles to maintain the highest standards in its

writings, discussions, and activities.

Moreover, politics cannot be reduced to theater. Study and experience

have taught me that art does not redeem—and certainly does not produce

revolutions. Art is sensitizing, emotionally enriching, and creative—but

few schools of art, music, and the performing arts have impelled any

appreciable number of people to build barricades, let alone fight behind

them. Art may be an adjunct of the revolutionary movement, but it is not

an impetus. Hence my fear of popular theatrical efforts to “reclaim” the

streets—as though we ever had them!—with street festivals. And then

what? Nor can elections be reduced to mere theater or even to strategies

for engaging in propaganda, important as this may be. Unless we actually

run candidates in city council elections, we are not dealing with power.

And to live in fear that power might “corrupt” not only ignores the many

cases where it did not corrupt; it ignores the need to gain power.

Theater, street events, and other photogenic escapades merely play at

politics rather than engage in it.

A Vanguard Organization

A libertarian municipalist movement that is created by means of distinct

steps, with advanced ideas, education, and experience, has every right

to regard itself as a vanguard. Obviously, any other kind of movement

organization can make the same claim—no libertarian municipalist

organization can deny other organizations the right to call themselves

vanguards. But no major social change will ever occur without a

well-organized vanguard movement that is structured by a constitution

and places clear-cut requirements on the right of people to join it. I

for one have had enough of the old Clamshell Alliance-type

organizational practices that reduce membership to a revolving door in

which people enter and leave the organization after a single meeting—but

have full voting rights.

And I have had enough of consensus decision-making, in which a minority

has the bizarre right to block the majority’s decisions, and that

themselves become an obstructive tyranny while claiming absurdly that

majority decision-making is “tyrannical.” I oppose the way movement

groups often have used consensus decision-making processes to manipulate

the membership. I’m sorry, but the streets will not “organize” us. Only

a serious, responsible, and structured movement can do that.

Vacancy on the Left

Important as it is to create links between libertarian municipalism and

oppositional movements, it would be a grave error to dissolve our

movement into theirs or surrendered our identity to them. I have no

compunction about declaring that we stand on a higher ground than

anything else of which I know that calls itself “oppositional.” Like the

word revolutionary, the word opposition has been steadily cheapened and

will continue to be devalued. The political spectrum has shifted

enormously from left to right—a shift that has affected the ecology

movement, feminism, self-styled liberation movements, and the labor

movement, as well as the bourgeoisie. .

Everywhere the Right is shifting into the darkness of outright reaction,

often with dangerous racist overtones. This shift has created a vacancy

in that vast space on the political spectrum where the Left should

legitimately be. Without a well-anchored Left, indeed, there is no

political spectrum at all—and it is my deepest fear that with the

widespread ignorance and rejection of history today is dumbing down

virtually all social and political standards. Anarchists affirm the

importance of the state; Marxists try to fit their theories into a

market economy; reformists sound like conservatives; and conservatives,

not to speak of reactionaries, find a home in Telos magazine—while

bizarre coalitions try to tailor their semifascistic notions to New Left

notions.

Class Society

Some anarcho-syndicalists and anarcho-communists have recently written

that I do not “believe” in the existence of classes—an accusation that

is almost too ridiculous to answer. I have no doubt that we live in a

class society; in fact, conflicts between classes would doubtless exist

in citizens’ assemblies as well. For this reason, libertarian

municipalism does not forsake the notion of class struggle but carries

it out not only in the factories but also into the civic or municipal

arena.

It does so, that is, as long as factories continue to exist and as long

as proletarians do not imagine that they are “middle class.” But I

learned many years ago, while working in a foundry and in an auto plant

owned by General Motors, that workers regard themselves as human beings

as well as class beings. They are fathers and mothers, sisters and

brothers, and sons and daughters who are deeply concerned with the

ordinary problems of life, such as the quality of their neighborhoods,

dwellings, sanitary facilities, recreation areas, schools, air, water,

and food—in short, all the problems that concern city and rural dwellers

quite apart from their class status. These general interests, while they

do not supplant class interests, can cut across class lines, especially

the lines that divide workers from a vast variety of middle-class

people.

Even during my years working in heavy industry, I found it easier to

reach workers on the basis of environmental and neighborhood issues than

on the basis of factory issues. During the 1960s, the transclass appeal

of certain issues became obvious to me, such as in my 1963 fight against

the Edison Company’s attempt to build a nuclear reactor in New York

City. Workers no less than middle-class people simply overwhelmed me

with questions and asked me to come to their community groups and

address them. This phenomenon continues today: in November 1999, it was

not only workers but middle-class people who marched against

globalization and the World Trade Organization in Seattle—a march that

consciously or unconsciously was aimed against the very core of modern

capitalism. Such transclass issues have been emerging for decades now.

Indeed, capitalism is slowly producing these generalized concerns in all

strata of society. The much-desired “general interests” that Marx and

socialists as well as anarchists hoped would unite most of humanity as a

whole against the bourgeoisie are very much on the horizon. If we do not

recognize these general interests and formulate them in a revolutionary

way, then I shall go to my grave concluding that existing anarchist

scenes, in all their silly mutations, are a complete failure, and that

the Marxists have done no better. If we are to face the new century with

a theory that keeps pace with—or tries to see beyond—new developments,

then we will have to draw on the best we can find in anarchism and

Marxism and go beyond them by developing a more comprehensive body of

ideas to guide us toward a rational future. For the body of ideas that I

would recommend, I have given the name Communalism.

Confederation and Autonomy

Our ideas of confederation should not remain stuck in anarchist writings

of the 19th century. In Proudhon’s writings on federalism, for example,

we find an extremely naive vision of a “federation of autonomous

communes” whose component members could choose, if they so wished, to

pull out of that federation and “go it on their own.” But such

“autonomy” is no longer possible, if it was even in Proudhon’s day. A

unilateral choice to leave the federation, after all, would undermine

the entire federation itself. We no longer live in an artisanal and

craft world. Imagine if the electrical complex in upstate New York

“autonomously” decided to pull out of a confederation with the Vermont

electrical complex because it was piqued by Vermont’s behavior.

Equally troubling would be a confederation based on the kind of

“voluntary agreements” that Kropotkin found and even celebrated in the

railroad lines—no less!—of his day. If the operating principles of

19th-century railroad lines are a good example of “voluntary

agreements,” then I would humbly suggest that those formulated by J.P.

Morgan and Co. are priceless. The “anarcho”-capitalists would doubtless

exult in this view, presented in Kropotkin’s The Conquest of Bread, but

allow me to dissent from it.

A confederation should be regarded as a binding agreement, not one that

can be canceled for frivolous “voluntaristic” reasons. A municipality

should be able to withdraw from a confederation only after every citizen

of the confederation has had the opportunity to thoroughly explore the

municipality’s grievances and to decide by a majority vote of the entire

confederation that it can withdraw without undermining the entire

confederation itself.

Economics and Technology

Does libertarian municipalism have an economic theory? Yes, I should

emphasize, one that is very close to Marx’s critique of capitalism in

volume 1 of Capital. Too often, knee-jerk rejections of Marx’s brilliant

work routinely bring smiles of approval to the faces of his opponents. I

refuse to participate in such routines. However much I disagree with

many elements of Marxism, no other single analysis of capitalism even

remotely, at this late date, approximates that amazing work.

I do not see how a thoughtful libertarian municipalist theorist can

avoid studying and absorbing dialectics, or lack a rich philosophical

perspective on History, as distinguished from mere Chronicles. No single

theory can encompasses social phenomena that have yet to appear on the

existing social horizon, but what can provide us with foresight are

basic minimal principles—to which we strongly adhere until they are no

longer tenable.

Libertarian municipalism is also based on the proposition that we now

have the technology for a post-scarcity economy—one that can potentially

abolish mindless toil and possibly most of the work that enters into

industrial production today. In such a world, the communist ideal of

“from each according to ability, to each according to needs” would be

historically and technically feasible. Various fears that individual

“needs” might be expanded to accommodate greed can be removed by giving

the municipal assembly the right to determine whether certain identified

“needs” are excessive and whether their fulfillment could damage the

well-being of the entire economy.

The world is changing now at a pace that is absolutely stunning. If

capitalism does not destroy the biosphere, then in possibly thirty,

certainly fifty years the world that survives will be changed beyond our

imagination. Not only will the peasant world be gone, but so too will

much of the “nature” we often call “wild.” The automation of industry

will probably reach incredible proportions, and the earth’s features

will be vastly transformed. Whether these changes will produce an

ecological crisis, or whether science and technology can mitigate their

impact, however unsatisfactorily, I do not know, nor will I ever know,

as I am approaching the end of my own life.

This much, however, I do believe: if a libertarian municipalist movement

based on Communalist principles cannot establish a system of direct

democracy and confederation, then libertarian ideals of all kinds must

be significantly revised. But we cannot hope to establish any kind of

truly libertarian society without creating a public sphere, beginning

with a grassroots electoral politics based on the creation of popular

assemblies. In my view, this is the left libertarian movement’s last

stand. If you do not agree with me, so be it—but please, use a different

label for your ideas, leave the name “libertarian municipalism” alone,

and go your own way toward communitarian and cooperative enterprises, if

not Taoist monasteries and mystical seances. I would ask my critics not

to muddy up ideas that they don’t really like, while at the same time

claiming to support them.