💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › murray-bookchin-libertarian-municipalism-an-overview.gm… captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:31:12. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Libertarian Municipalism: An Overview
Author: Murray Bookchin
Date: 1991
Language: en
Topics: municipalism
Source: Retrieved on April 28, 2009 from http://dwardmac.pitzer.edu/anarchist_archives/bookchin/gp/perspectives24.html
Notes: This article was originally published as the introduction to the Social Ecology Project’s Readings in Libertarian Municipalism, a collection of writings on the subject. Green Perspectives — October 1991

Murray Bookchin

Libertarian Municipalism: An Overview

Perhaps the greatest single failing of movements for social

reconstruction — I refer particularly to the Left, to radical ecology

groups, and to organizations that profess to speak for the oppressed —

is their lack of a politics that will carry people beyond the limits

established by the status quo.

Politics today means duels between top-down bureaucratic parties for

electoral office, that offer vacuous programs for “social justice” to

attract a nondescript “electorate.” Once in office, their programs

usually turn into a bouquet of “compromises.” In this respect, many

Green parties in Europe have been only marginally different from

conventional parliamentary parties. Nor have socialist parties, with all

their various labels, exhibited any basic differences from their

capitalist counter parts. To be sure, the indifference of the

Euro-American public — its “apoliticism” — is understandably depressing.

Given their low expectations, when people do vote, they normally turn to

established parties if only because, as centers of power, they can

produce results of sorts in practical matters. If one bothers to vote,

most people reason, why waste a vote on a new marginal organization that

has all the characteristics of the major ones and that will eventually

become corrupted if it succeeds? Witness the German Greens, whose

internal and public life increasingly approximates that of other parties

in the new Reich.

That this “political process” has lingered on with almost no basic

alteration for decades now is due in great part to the inertia of the

process itself. Time wears expectations thin, and hopes are often

reduced to habits as one disappointment is followed by another. Talk of

a “new politics,” of upsetting tradition, which is as old as politics

itself, is becoming unconvincing. For decades, at least, the changes

that have occurred in radical politics are largely changes in rhetoric

rather than structure. The German Greens are only the most recent of a

succession of “nonparty parties” (to use their original way of

describing their organization) that have turned from an attempt to

practice grassroots politics — ironically, in the Bundestag, of all

places! — into a typical parliamentary party. The Social Democratic

Party in Germany, the Labor Party in Britain, the New Democratic Party

in Canada, the Socialist Party in France, and others, despite their

original emancipatory visions, barely qualify today as even liberal

parties in which a Franklin D. Roosevelt or a Harry Truman would have

found a comfortable home. Whatever social ideals these parties may have

had generations ago have been eclipsed by the pragmatics of gaining,

holding, and extending their power in their respective parliamentary and

ministerial bodies.

It is precisely such parliamentary and ministerial objectives that we

call “politics” today. To the modern political imagination, “politics”

is precisely a body of techniques for holding power in representative

bodies — notably the legislative and executive arenas — not a moral

calling based on rationality, community, and freedom.

A Civic Ethics

Libertarian municipalism represents a serious, indeed a historically

fundamental project, to render politics ethical in character and

grassroots in organization. It is structurally and morally different

from other grassroots efforts, not merely rhetorically different. It

seeks to reclaim the public sphere for the exercise of authentic

citizenship while breaking away from the bleak cycle of parliamentarism

and its mystification of the “party” mechanism as a means for public

representation. In these respects, libertarian municipalism is not

merely a “political strategy.” It is an effort to work from latent or

incipient democratic possibilities toward a radically new configuration

of society itself-a communitarian society oriented toward meeting human

needs, responding to ecological imperatives, and developing a new ethics

based on sharing and cooperation. That it involves a consistently

independent form of politics is a truism. More important, it involves a

redefinition of politics, a return to the word’s original Greek meaning

as the management of the community or polis by means of direct

face-to-face assemblies of the people in the formulation of public

policy and based on an ethics of complementarily and solidarity.

In this respect, libertarian municipalism is not one of many pluralistic

techniques that is intended to achieve a vague and undefined social

goal. Democratic to its core and nonhierarchical in its structure, it is

a kind of human destiny, not merely one of an assortment of political

tools or strategies that can be adopted and discarded with the aim of

achieving power. Libertarian municipalism, in effect, seeks to define

the institutional contours of a new society even as it advances the

practical message of a radically new politics for our day.

Means and Ends

Here, means and ends meet in a rational unity. The word politics now

expresses direct popular control of society by its citizens through

achieving and sustaining a true democracy in municipal assemblies —

this, as distinguished from republican systems of representation that

preempt the right of the citizen to formulate community and regional

policies. Such politics is radically distinct from statecraft and the

state a professional body composed of bureaucrats, police, military,

legislators, and the like, that exists as a coercive apparatus, clearly

distinct from and above the people. The libertarian municipalist

approach distinguishes statecraft — which we usually characterize as

“politics” today — and politics as it once existed in precapitalist

democratic communities.

Moreover, libertarian municipalism also involves a clear delineation of

the social realm — as well as the political realm — in the strict

meaning of the term social: notably, the arena in which we live our

private lives and engage in production. As such, the social realm is to

be distinguished from both the political and the statist realms.

Enormous mischief has been caused by the interchangeable use of these

terms — social, political, and the state. Indeed, the tendency has been

to identify them with one another in our thinking and in the reality of

everyday life. But the state is a completely alien formation, a thorn in

the side of human development, an exogenous entity that has incessantly

encroached on the social and political realms. Often, in fact, the state

has been an end in itself, as witness the rise of Asian empires, ancient

imperial Rome, and the totalitarian state of modern times. More than

this, it has steadily invaded the political domain, which, for all its

past shortcomings, had empowered communities, social groupings, and

individuals.

Such invasions have not gone unchallenged. Indeed, the conflict between

the state on the one hand and the political and social realms on the

other has been an ongoing subterranean civil war for centuries. It has

often broken out into the open — in modern times in the conflict of the

Castilian cities (comuneros) against the Spanish monarchy in the 1520s,

in the struggle of the Parisian sections against the centralist Jacobin

Convention of 1793, and in endless other clashes both before and after

these encounters.

Today, with the increasing centralization and concentration of power in

the nation-state, a “new politics” — one that is genuinely new — must be

structured institutionally around the restoration of power by

municipalities. This is not only necessary but possible even in such

gigantic urban areas as New York City, Montreal, London, and Paris. Such

urban agglomerations are not, strictly speaking, cities or

municipalities in the traditional sense of those terms, despite being

designated as such by sociologists. It is only if we think that they are

cities that we become mystified by problems of size and logistics. Even

before we confront the ecological imperative of physical

decentralization (a necessity anticipated by Frederick Engels and Peter

Kropotkin alike), we need feel no problems about decentralizing them

institutionally. When Francois Mitterand tried to decentralize Paris

with local city halls a few years ago, his reasons were strictly

tactical (he wanted to weaken the authority of the capital’s right-wing

mayor). Nonetheless, he failed not because restructuring the Large

metropolis was impossible but because the majority of the affluent

Parisians supported the mayor.

Clearly, institutional changes do not occur in a social vacuum. Nor do

they guarantee that a decentralized municipality, even if it is

structurally democratic. will necessarily be humane, rational, and

ecological in dealing with public affairs. Libertarian municipalism is

premised on the struggle to achieve a rational and ecological society, a

struggle that depends on education and organization. From the beginning,

it presupposes a genuinely democratic desire by people to arrest the

growing powers of the nation-state and reclaim them for their community

and their region. Unless there is a movement — hopefully an effective

Left Green movement — to foster these aims, decentralization can lead to

local parochialism as easily as it can lead to ecological humanist

communities.

But when have basic social changes ever been without risk? The case that

Marx’s commitment to a centralized state and planned economy would

inevitably yield bureaucratic totalitarianism could have been better

made than the case that decentralized libertarian municipalities will

inevitably be authoritarian and have exclusionary and parochial traits.

Economic interdependence is a fact of life today, and capitalism itself

has made parochial autarchies a chimera. While municipalities and

regions can seek to attain a considerable measure of self-aufficiency,

we have long left the era when self-aufficient communities that can

indulge their prejudices are possible.

Confederalism

Equally important is the need for confederation — the interlinking of

communities with one another through recallable deputies mandated by

municipal citizens’ assemblies and whose sole functions are coordinative

and administrative. Confederation has a long history of its own that

dates back to antiquity and that surfaced as a major alternative to the

nation state. From the American Revolution through the French Revolution

and the Spanish Revolution of 1936, confederalism constituted a major

challenge to state centralism. Nor has it disappeared in our own time,

when the breakup of existing twentieth-century empires raises the issue

of enforced state centralism or the relatively autonomous nation.

Libertarian municipalism adds a radically democratic dimension to the

contemporary discussions of confederation (as, for example, in

Yugoslavia and Czechoslovakia) by calling for confederations not of

nation-states but of municipalities and of the neighborhoods of giant

megalopolitan areas as well as towns and villages.

In the case of libertarian municipalism’ parochialism can thus be

checked not only by the compelling realities of economic interdependence

but by the commitment of municipal minorities to defer to the majority

wishes of participating communities. Do these interdependencies and

majority decisions guarantee us that a majority decision will be a

correct one? Certainly not — but our chances for a rational and

ecological society are much better in this approach than in those that

ride on centralized entities and bureaucratic apparatuses. I cannot help

but marvel that no municipal network has been emergent among the German

Greens, who have hundreds of representatives in city councils around

Germany but who carry on a local politics that is completely

conventional and self enclosed within particular towns and cities.

Many arguments against libertarian municipalism — even with its strong

confederal emphasis derive from a failure to understand its distinction

between policy-making and administration. This distinction is

fundamental to libertarian municipalism and must always be kept in mind.

Policy is made by a community or neighborhood assembly of free citizens;

administration is performed by confederal councils composed of mandated,

recallable deputies of wards, towns, and villages. If particular

communities or neighborhoods — or a minority grouping of them choose to

go their own way to a point where human rights are violated or where

ecological mayhem is permitted, the majority in a local or regional

confederation has every right to prevent such malfeasances through its

confederal council. This is not a denial of democracy but the assertion

of a shared agreement by all to recognize civil rights and maintain the

ecological integrity of a region. These rights and needs are not

asserted so much by a confederal council as by the majority of the

popular assemblies conceived as one large community that expresses its

wishes through its confederal deputies. Thus policy-making still remains

local, but its administration is vested in the confederal network as a

whole. The confederation in effect is a Community of communities based

on distinct human rights and ecological imperatives.

If libertarian municipalism is not to be totally warped of its form and

divested of its meaning, it is a desideratum that must be fought for. It

speaks to a time — hopefully, one that will yet come when people feel

disempowered and actively seek empowerment. Existing in growing tension

with the nation-state, it is a process as well as a destiny, a struggle

to be fulfilled, not a bequest granted by the summits of the state. It

is a dual power that contests the legitimacy of the existing state

power. Such a movement can be expected to begin slowly, perhaps

sporadically, in communities here and there that initially may demand

only the moral authority to alter the structuring of society before

enough interlinked confederations exist to demand the outright

institutional power to replace the state. The growing tension created by

the emergence of municipal confederations represents a confrontation

between the state and the political realms. This confrontation can be

resolved only after libertarian municipalism forms the new politics of a

popular movement and ultimately captures the imagination of millions.

Certain points, however, should be obvious. The people who initially

enter into the duel between confederalism and statism will not be the

same human beings as those who eventually achieve libertarian

municipalism. The movement that tries to educate them and the struggles

that give libertarian municipalist principles reality will turn them

into active citizens, rather than passive “constituents.” No one who

participates in a struggle for social restructuring emerges from that

struggle with the prejudices, habits, and sensibilities with which he or

she entered it. Hopefully, then, such prejudices — like parochialism —

will increasingly be replaced by a generous sense of cooperation and a

caring sense of interdependence.

Municipalizing the Economy

It remains to emphasize that libertarian municipalism is not merely an

evocation of all traditional antistatist notions of politics. Just as it

redefines politics to include face-to-face municipal democracies

graduated to confederal levels, so it includes a municipalist and

confederal approach to economics. Minimally, a libertarian municipalist

economics calls for the municipalization of the economy, not its

centralization into state-owned “nationalized” enterprises on the one

hand or its reduction to “worker-controlled” forms of collectivistic

capitalism on the other. Trade-union control of “worker controlled”

enterprises (that is, syndicalism) has had its day. This should be

evident to anyone who examines the bureaucracies that even revolutionary

trade unions spawned during the Spanish Civil War of 1936. Today,

corporate capitalism too is increasingly eager to bring the worker into

complicity with his or her own exploitation by means of “workplace

democracy.” Nor was the revolution in Spain or in other countries spared

the existence of competition among worker-controlled enterprises for raw

materials, markets, and profits. Even more recently, many Israeli

kibbutzim have been failures as examples of nonexploitative,

need-oriented enterprises, despite the high ideals with which they were

initially founded.

Libertarian municipalism proposes a radically different form of economy

one that is neither nationalized nor collectivized according to

syndicalist precepts. It proposes that land and enterprises be placed

increasingly in the custody of the community more precisely, the custody

of citizens in free assemblies and their deputies in confederal

councils. How work should be planned, what technologies should be used,

how goods should be distributed are questions that can only be resolved

in practice. The maxim “from each according to his or her ability, to

each according to his or her needs” would seem a bedrock guide for an

economically rational society, provided to be sure that goods are of the

highest durability and quality, that needs are guided by rational and

ecological standards, and that the ancient notions of limit and balance

replace the bourgeois marketplace imperative of “grow or die.”

In such a municipal economy — confederal, interdependent, and rational

by ecological, not simply technological, standards — we would expect

that the special interests that divide people today into workers,

professionals, managers, and the like would be melded into a general

interest in which people see themselves as citizens guided strictly by

the needs of their community and region rather than by personal

proclivities and vocational concerns. Here, citizenship would come into

its own, and rational as well as ecological interpretations of the

public good would supplant class and hierarchical interests.

This is the moral basis of a moral economy for moral communities. But of

overarching importance is the general social interest that potentially

underpins all moral communities, an interest that must ultimately cut

across class, gender, ethnic, and status lines if humanity is to

continue to exist as a viable species. This interest is the one created

in our times by ecological catastrophe. Capitalism’s “grow or die”

imperative stands radically at odds with ecology’s imperative of

interdependence and limit. The two imperatives can no longer coexist

with each other — nor can any society founded on the myth that they can

be reconciled hope to survive. Either we will establish an ecological

society, or society will go under for everyone, irrespective of his or

her status.

Will this ecological society be authoritarian, or possibly even

totalitarian, a hierarchial dispensation that is implicit in the image

of the planet as a “spaceship” Or will it be democratic? If history is

any guide, the development of a democratic ecological society, as

distinguished from a commend ecological society, must follow its own

logic. One cannot resolve this historical dilemma without getting to its

roots. Without a searching analysis of our ecological problems and their

social sources, the pernicious institutions that we now have will lead

to increased centralization and further ecological catastrophe. In a

democratic ecological society, those roots are literally the grass roots

that libertarian municipalism seeks to foster.

For those who rightly call for a new technology, new sources of energy,

new means of transportation, and new ecological lifeways, can a new

society be anything less than a Community of communities based on

confederation rather than statism? We already live in a world in which

the economy is “overglobalized,” overcentralized, and

overbureaucratized. Much that can be done locally and regionally is now

being done largely for profit, military needs, and imperial appetites —

on a global scale with a seeming complexity that can actually be easily

diminished.

If this seems too “utopian” for our time, then so must the present flood

of literature that asks for radically sweeping shifts in energy

policies, far-reaching reductions in air and water pollution, and the

formulation of worldwide plans to arrest global warming and the

destruction of the ozone layer be seen as “utopian.” Is it too much, it

is fair to ask, to take such demands one step further and call for

institutional and economic changes that are no less drastic and that in

fact are based on traditions that are deeply sedimented in American —

indeed, the world’s — noblest democratic and political traditions?

Nor are we obliged to expect these changes to occur immediately. The

Left long worked with minimum and maximum programs for change, in which

immediate steps that can be taken now were linked by transitional

advances and intermediate areas that would eventually yield ultimate

goals. Minimal steps that can be taken now include initiating Left Green

municipalist movements that propose popular neighborhood and town

assemblies — even if they have only moral functions at first — and

electing town and city councilors that advance the cause of these

assemblies and other popular institutions. These minimal steps can lead

step-by-step to the formation of confederal bodies and the increasing

legitimation of truly democratic bodies. Civic banks to fund municipal

enterprises and land purchases; the fostering of new ecologically

oriented enterprises that are owned by the community; and the creation

of grassroots networks in many fields of endeavor and the public weal —

all these can be developed at a pace appropriate to changes that are

being made in political life.

That capital will likely “migrate” from communities and confederations

that are moving toward libertarian municipalism is a problem that every

community, every nation, whose political life has become radicalized has

faced. Capital, in fact, normally “migrates” to areas where it can

acquire high profits, irrespective of political considerations.

Overwhelmed by fears of capital migration, a good case could be

established for not rocking the political boat at any time. Far more to

the point are that municipally owned enterprises and farms could provide

new ecologically valuable and health-nourishing products to a public

that is becoming increasingly aware of the low-quality goods and staples

that are being foisted on it now.

Libertarian municipalism is a politics that can excite the public

imagination, appropriate for a movement that is direly in need of a

sense of direction and purpose. The papers that appear in this

collection offer ideas, ways, and means not only to undo the present

social order but to remake it drastically — expanding its residual

democratic traditions into a rational and ecological society.

Addendum

This addendum seems to be necessary because some of the opponents of

libertarian municipalism — and, regrettably, some of its acolyte —

misunderstand what libertarian municipalism seeks to achieve indeed,

misunderstand its very nature.

For some of its instrumental acolytes, libertarian municipalism is

becoming a tactical device to gain entry into so called independent

movements and new third parties that call for “grassroots politics,”

such as those proposed by NOW and certain Labor leaders In the name of

“libertarian municipalism,” some radical acolytes of the view are

prepared to blur the tension that they should cultivate between the

civic realm and the state — presumably to gain greater public attention

in electoral campaigns for gubernatorial, congressional, and other state

offices. These radicals regrettably warp libertarian municipalism into a

mere “tactic” or “strategy” and drain it of its revolutionary content.

But those who propose to use tenets of libertarian municipalism for

“tactical” reasons as a means to enter another reformist party or

function as its “left wing” have little in common with the idea.

Libertarian municipalism is not a product of the formal logic that has

such deep roots in left-wing “analyses” and “strategies” today, despite

the claims of many radicals that “dialectics” is their “method.” The

struggle toward creating new civic institutions out of old ones (or

replacing the old ones altogether) and creating civic confederations is

a self formative one, a creative dynamic formed from the tension of

social conflict. The effort to work along these lines is as much a part

of the end as the process of maturing from the child to the adult — from

the relatively undifferentiated to the fully differentiated — with all

its difficulties. The very fight for a municipal confederation, for

municipal control of “property,” and for the actual achievement of

worldwide municipal confederation is directed toward achieving a new

ethos of citizenship and community, not simply to gain victories in

largely reformist conflicts.

Thus, libertarian municipalism is not merely an effort simply to “take

over” city councils to construct a more “environmentally friendly” city

government. These adherents or opponents of libertarian municipalism, in

effect, look at the civic structures that exist before their eyes now

and essentially (all rhetoric to the contrary aside) take them as they

exist. Libertarian municipalism, by contrast, is an effort to transform

and democratize city governments, to root them in popular assemblies, to

knit them together along confederal lines, to appropriate a regional

economy along confederal and municipal lines.

In fact, libertarian municipalism gains its life and its integrity

precisely from the dialectical tension it proposes between the

nation-state and the municipal confederation. Its “law of life,” to use

an old Marxian term, consists precisely in its struggle with the state.

The tension between municipal confederations and the state must be clear

and uncompromising. Since these confederations would exist primarily in

opposition to statecraft, they cannot be compromised by state,

provincial, or national elections, much less achieved by these means.

Libertarian municipalism is formed by its struggle with the state,

strengthened by this struggle, indeed defined by this struggle. Divested

of this dialectical tension with the state, of this duality of power

that must ultimately be actualized in a free “Commune of communes,”

libertarian municipalism becomes little more than “sewer socialism.”

Many heroic comrades who are prepared to do battle (one day) with the

cosmic forces of capitalism find that libertarian municipalism is too

thorny, irrelevant, or vague to deal with and opt for what is basically

a form of political particularism. Our spray-can or “alternative cafe”

radicals may choose to brush libertarian municipalism aside as “a

ludicrous tactic,” but it never ceases to amaze me that well-meaning

radicals who are committed to the “overthrow” of capitalism (no less!)

find it too difficult to function politically — and, yes, electorally —

in their own neighborhoods for a new politics based on a genuine

democracy. If they cannot provide a transformative politics for their

own neighborhood relatively modest task — or diligently work at doing so

with the constancy that used to mark the more mature left movements of

the past, I find it very hard to believe that they will ever do much

harm to the present social system. Indeed, by creating cultural centers,

parks, and good housing, they may well be improving the system by giving

capitalism a human face without diminishing its under lying unfreedom as

a hierarchical and class society.

A bouquet of struggles for “identity” has often fractured rising radical

movements since SDS in the 1960s, ranging from foreign to domestic

nationalisms. Because these identity struggles are so popular today,

some of the critics of libertarian municipalism invoke “public opinion”

against it. But when has it been the task of revolutionaries to

surrender to “public opinion” not even the “public opinion” of the

oppressed, whose views can often be very reactionary? Truth has its own

life — regardless of whether the oppressed masses perceive or agree on

what is true. Nor is it “elitist” to invoke truth, in contradiction to

even radical public opinion, when that opinion essentially seeks a march

backward into the politics of particularism and even racism. It is very

easy to drop to all fours these days, but as radicals our most important

need is to stand on two feet — that is, to be as fully human as possible

— and to challenge the existing society in behalf of our shared common

humanity, not on the basis of gender, race, age, and the like.

Critics of libertarian municipalism even dispute the very possibility of

a “general interest.” If, for such critics, the face-to-face democracy

advocated by libertarian municipalism and the need to extend the

premises of democracy beyond mere justice to complete freedom do not

suffice as a “general interest,” it would seem to me that the need to

repair our relationship with the natural world is certainly a “general

interest” that is beyond dispute — and, indeed, it remains the “general

interest” advanced by social ecology. It may be possible to coopt many

dissatisfied elements in the present society, but nature is not

cooptable. Indeed, the only politics that remains for the Left is one

based on the premise that there is a “general interest” in democratizing

society and preserving the planet Now that traditional forces such as

the workers’ movement have ebbed from the historical scene, it can be

said with almost complete certainty that without libertarian

municipalism, the left will have no politics whatever.

A dialectical view of the relationship of confederalism to the

nation-state, an understanding of the narrowness, introverted character,

and parochialism of identity-movements. and a recognition that the

workers’ movement is essentially dead all illustrate that if a new

politics is going to develop today, it must be unflinchingly public, in

contrast to the alternative-cafe “politics” advanced by many radicals

today. It must be electoral on a municipal basis, confederal in its

vision, and revolutionary in its character.

Indeed, in my view, libertarian municipalism, with its emphasis on

confederalism, is precisely the “Commune of communes” for which

anarchists have fought over the past two centuries. Today, it is the

“red button” that must be pushed if a radical movement is to open the

door to the public sphere. To leave that red button untouched and slip

back into the worst habits of the post-1968 New Left, when the notion of

“power” was divested of utopian or imaginative qualities, is to reduce

radicalism to yet another subculture that will probably live more on

heroic memories than on the hopes of a rational future.

April 3, 1991; addendum, October 1, 1991