š¾ Archived View for library.inu.red āŗ file āŗ kevin-carson-contra-reisman.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:44:18. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
ā”ļø Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Contra Reisman Author: Kevin Carson Date: December 14, 2006 Language: en Topics: debate, a response, critique, right libertarianism Source: Retrieved on 4th September 2021 from https://mutualist.blogspot.com/2006/12/contra-reisman-compendium-of-posts.html
Well, George Reisman (or should I say Herr Doktor Doktor Reisman) is on
a roll with what appears to be an anti-Carson theme, so it looks like
Iāll be getting some more free publicity.
I should mention that after seeing so many of Reismanās almost comically
bowdlerized misreadings of my work (and worse, his continuing
reassetions of them in the face of my corrections), I begin to wonder
whether his obtuseness is just a pose: whether heās not instead
following a deliberate strategy of counting on the far greater
readership of his venues, and knowingly repeating arguments that have
been shown to be erroneous, in the confidence that most of his readers
will be familiar only with his own assertions and not my responses.
Certainly anyone willing to take the trouble to read both Reismanās
review of my book in JLS and my own rejoinder to Reisman will have ample
reason to doubt either his reading comprehension skills or his
sincerity, and never to accept his characterization of anyone elseās
work without seeing it firsthand for themselves.
I have some hope that this strategy of Reismanās, if it is indeed his
strategy, will backfire. The people who accept his grossly distorted
version of my positions, as presented in his review article, without
bothering to read even my rejoinder, are likely to be firmly in
Reismanās camp anyway. On the other hand, anyone who out of curiosity
follows up a Reismanās bizarre misreadings with a reading of my
rejoinder will never trust him again.
Quasibillās comment on an earlier thread seem to bear this out:
To be honest, it was the utter vapidity of Dr. Resimanās critique of
your book that convinced me that there was something to be learned from
your arguments.
Not that Reisman makes many good arguments (I think he takes Rothbardās
prediction about experts specializing where they are weakest as a
challenge to live up to), but his inability to address your arguments on
the merits combined with his resort to ad hominems and vitriol were
telling indicators of where the truth in the debate lay.
Iām still not a fan of mutualist property and banking theory, but Iāve
learned a lot by reading your critiques of the standard Misesian
position.
So despair not, your exchange with Reisman has at least one partial
convert to show for it!
Reismanās criticisms do more to promote my ideas among thinking people
than anything I could possibly write. So bring it on!
I spent a lot of time in my rejoinder pointing out as many of Reismanās
errors and mischaracterizations as my space constraints would permit,
and I donāt have the time or energy to repeat all of them. All I can say
is, if youāre interested itās easy to click on the links above and read
both Reismanās review and my rejoinder in their entirety and see for
yourself. And if you canāt be bothered to do that, please donāt pretend
that you know jack shit about my position on anything.
This time, in any case, Reismanās target is mutualist property theory
(his remarks are also crossposted on his personal blog). Heās no longer
calling me a āMarxist,ā as he did by my count ten times in his review
for JLS. So I guess that in itself is a marked improvement in his
historical literacy in recent months.
Now heās attacking my positions under the label āmutualism,ā although he
apparently has at best a weak grasp on the existence of individualist
anarchism in the nineteenth century, its actual tenets, or the extent to
which it has been addressed (often somewhat positively) by Rothbard and
many of his followers. After reading Reismanās reference to āwhat
[Carson] calls āindividualist anarchism,āā I canāt help but think of a
befuddled Montgomery Burnsā encountering some (to him) newfangled
phenomenon: āIām beginning to like this so-called āiced-cream.āā Or:
āAhoy! Ahoy!... I suspect you need more practice working your telephone
machine.ā
But what strikes me most about Reismanās attacks is less their substance
than their tone. As I say, he acts as though the history of
individualist anarchism is something that just recently dropped into his
lap. And in confronting it, he distances himself not only from
Rothbardās halfway friendly treatment of it, but from the Rothbardiansā
entire critique of historical capitalism and from all of their points of
agreement with New Left historiography.
What weāre left with is pure right-wing Mises, without any admixture of
Rothbardian leaven. The degree to which he has become a self-parody of
the extreme Austrian right can be illustrated by these quotes from his
review article, in which he takes extreme umbrage at any suggestion that
workers might possess Hayekās ādistributed idiosyncratic knowledge,ā or
be capable of significant innovation in an economy of cooperatively
owned enterprises:
Here Carson, the āindividualistā anarchist shows himself to be quite the
collectivist, attributing to the average person qualities of independent
thought and judgment that are found only in exceptional individuals....
Carson is simply unaware that innovation is the product of exceptional,
dedicated individuals who must overcome the uncomprehending dullness of
most of their fellows, and often their hostility as well.
Egad! Maybe he should write a book of management theory entitled My
Struggle Against Stupidity, Lies, and Ignorance. Austrian economics,
indeed!
Of course, this last bit of frothy-mouthed rug chewing comes less from
Austrianism, even its far right fringe, than from the outer fringes of
Randroidism. The source of Reismanās antipathy to the Untermenschen
outside Galtās Gulch is suggested by the fact that he lists Rand ahead
of the Austrians in his intellectual influences. Thatās not to say that
Rand fits in the intellectual box constructed for her by right-wing
Randroids like Reisman; some Objectivists like Chris Sciabarra have
refined aspects of her thought into indispensible tools of libertarian
analysis, and some Austrians like Roderick Long are appreciative of her
genuine contributions. In any case, the aspects of Randianism that
Reisman stresses donāt mesh very well with the mainstream of
contemporary Austrian thought, and only imperfectly with the Old Man
himself.
Reisman, interestingly, expresses a suspicion of me....
I cannot help but suspect that what Carson is actually opposed to is not
at all force, fraud, or actual injustice in the history of mankind but
the existence of large inequalities of wealth and income, whatever their
basis.
...that mirror-images my own suspicions of him. I cannot help but
suspect that what Reisman actually supports is not free market
principles as such, but āthe existence of large inequalities of wealth
and income, whatever their basis.ā
As I wrote in my rejoinder to Reismanās review, I suspect he is forced
for tactical reasons to distance himself from the last forty years of
Rothbardian critiques of state capitalism. I was struck by the parallel
between Friedrich Engels and George Reisman, in the extent to which they
found it necessary to retreat stragetically from so many of the
positions of their own respective sides, in order to maintain some
defensible ground. I quote at length:
On the matter of primitive accumulation, there is an amazing parallel
between Reisman and that most vulgar of vulgar Marxists, Friedrich
Engels. Engels, in Anti-DĆ¼hring, argued that the process of primitive
accumulation would have taken place in exactly the same way without any
state expropriation whatsoever, solely through the effects of success
and failure in the free market. Essentially, Engels retreated from
Marxās entire body of work on primitive accumulation, in which he
described the massive expropriation of the peasantry, āwritten in fire
and blood.ā Engels, in effect, embraced the ābourgeois nursery taleā of
primitive accumulation, ridiculed by Marx and Oppenheimer alike, in
which the present distribution of property reflects an endless series of
victories by the industrious ant over the lazy grasshopper. Marx
himself, for that matter, was on the defensive about the logical
implications of his history of primitive accumulation. Why? There was an
entire school of radical classical liberals and market-oriented
Ricardian socialists who argued that state robbery and state-enforced
unequal exchange were the causes of economic exploitation. As Maurice
Dobb wrote in his introduction to Marxās Contribution to the Critique of
Political Economy:
ā...the school of writers to whom the name of the Ricardian Socialists
has been given ... who can be said to have held a āprimitiveā theory of
exploitation, explained profit on capital as the product of superior
bargaining power, lack of competition and āunequal exchanges between
Capital and Labour.ā... This was the kind of explanation that Marx was
avoiding rather than seeking. It did not make exploitation consistent
with the law of value and with market competition, but explained it by
departures from, or imperfections in, the latter. To it there was an
easy answer from the liberal economists and free traders: namely, ājoin
with us in demanding really free trade and then there can be no āunequal
exchangesā and exploitation.ā (Marx 1970, p. 13)ā
And as I commented in my book, this āeasy answerā was exactly the
approach taken by Thomas Hodgskin and the individualist anarchists of
America. The greatest of the latter, Benjamin Tucker, reproached as
merely a āconsistent Manchester man,ā wore that label as a badge of
honor. Engels was facing something similar, in Eugen DĆ¼hringās āforce
theoryā of economic exploitation. He was forced to retreat from Marxās
history of primitive accumulation, because he found the implications of
that history politically and strategically intolerable. I suspect
Reisman is forced to repudiate it for similar reasons.
I suspect, furthermore, that Reisman is forced to repudiate all of
Rothbardās insights, especially his points of agreement with the New
Left, on the history of state capitalism, for the same tactical reasons.
Acknowledging the role of the state in creating the present corporate
economy would destroy his romantic Galtās Gulch fantasy of big business
as an āoppressed minority.ā In short, Reisman is forced to destroy much
of Austrianism in order to save it.
At times, my suspicions go so far as doubting the genuineness of his
ostensible lack of reading comprehension or ability to grasp unfamiliar
arguments. Reismanās critiques of my work follow a rather disturbing
pattern. He originally makes a criticism of my book that displays a
seemingly total lack of reading comprehension or a total unwillingness
to respond to what I actually said. But after I rub his nose in his
bowdlerized misreading, he continues to talk past me, making the same
assertions over and over as if Iād never said a word.
Iāve seen some past material of Reismanās that displays a considerable
capacity for following nuanced thoughts and appreciating fine
distinctions (i.e., his contrast of the āesotericā and āexotericā
doctrines of Bohm-Bawerk), so I have reason to suspect that his pose of
intellectual ham-handedness is just that: a pose.
Anyway, now to his substantive points.
First, Reisman quotes from his original review article:
Thus, for example, if I, a legitimate owner of a piece of property,
legitimate even by Carsonās standards, decide to rent it out to a tenant
who agrees to pay the rent, the property, according to Carson, becomes
that of the tenant, and my attempt to collect the mutually-agreed-upon
rent is regarded as a violent invasion of his [the tenantās] āabsolute
right of property.ā In effect, Carson considers as government
intervention the governmentās upholding the rights of a landlord against
a thief.
This is question-begging. What constitutes agression or theft depends on
the prior definition of property rights. I have argued that no system of
property rights rules, whether Lockean, mutualist, or Georgist, can be
logically deduced from the axiom of self-ownership. According to the
arguments of āHogeyeā Bill Orton, from which I have borrowed
extensively, such property rights rules are conventional. And as I have
argued myself in elaborating this principle, the choice between such
rival sets of rules can only be made on consequentialist grounds: on the
extent to which they tend to promote other values that we consider
fundamental. This was the point of contention between Roderick Long and
myself in his review article (in which he argued with far more
effectiveness and less pissiness than Reisman) and my rejoinder.
Reisman continued, in his review:
He believes he has the right to prohibit me and the tenant from entering
into an enforceable contract respecting the payment of rent and that
such action is somehow not a violation of our freedom of contract and
not government intervention.
The term āenforceableā is the crux of the matter. The enforceability of
a contract, in any society, stateless or otherwise, depends on the
willingness of third parties to accept its validity. In a local
community where the majority consensus is for title based on occupancy
and use, any attempt to enforce title based on Lockean principles will
ultimately cost more than itās worth. For that reason, the mutual
defense associations and free juries in a Tuckerite or Warrenite
community would likely have exclusionary clauses for occupants seeking
aid against landlords in Lockean communities, and anarcho-capitalist
defense agencies would likewise exclude enforcement of landlord claims
against occupants in mutualist communities. Both would refuse to defend
property owners against rental collection in Georgist communities. And
in sparsely settled areas, the default position would likely be some
form of de facto occupancy and use, since the costs of excluding
squatters from vacant land would likely exceed any return on its value.
Following in the same vein in his blog post, Reisman attempts to portray
the Ingalls-Tucker property doctrine in the context of a simple breach
of contract:
Here there is a mutually and voluntarily agreed upon rental contract,
but after taking possession, the new occupant decides that he is the
owner of the land and will not pay any āabsentee landlord rent,ā which
Carson believes it is his absolute right to decide. Has he not obtained
anotherās legitimate property and is now refusing to pay for it? And,
having taken it, and both refusing to pay for it and refusing to give it
back, is he thus not stealing that property?
Would he have been able to obtain the use and occupancy of the land if
it had been known or suspected that this is how he would behave, once
having obtained it? Obviously, he would not have been able to, and the
assurance of his not behaving in this way is a written and signed
enforceable rental contract.
In a society where property is established by occupancy and use,
obviously, it would be a pretty obtuse would-be landlord who did not
āknow or suspectā that something like this would occur. Reisman
considers the hypothetical operation of occupancy and use tenure not in
the context of a legal system organized on that principle, but in an
atomistic fashion, with individual cases operating in the context of a
larger society based on the present rules.
He ignores my repeated stress on the principle that no system of
property rights rules can survive without a local consensus on those
rules, reflected in some body of law, which the local population is
willing to enforce in civil disputes. Owner-occupancy, like Lockean
absentee landlordism, would only be viable in a community where a
majority of people were agreed on those rules. So any landowner who
entered into a rental agreement with a tenant, like an employer entering
a contract by which his employee agreed to sell himself into slavery,
would do so knowing that the contract would be considered null and void
on its face. By the very fundamentals of mutualist property laws, a
contract to treat someone else as the real owner of a property which one
occupies oneself would be considered repugnant.
I donāt, however, dispute the possibility that a person might make
contractual agreement to quit a piece of land on certain terms. I have
raised that possibility myself in the case of mortgaging real property
to a mutual bank. The question is by what civil remedies the contract
would be enforced. A parallel case is that of bankruptcy, as Lysander
Spooner considered it. Certain remedies are allowed the creditor (i.e.,
seizure of existing assets), while others are denied (i.e., debtorās
prison or any claim on the future income of the defaulting debtor). In a
libertarian society, bank accounts and moveable assets might be forfeit
in the event of a default on an agreement to quit oneās property, and
assorted sanctions by third parties (including a refusal to enter into
further agreements with the party in default) would be likely; the
sanctions and universal shunning of those who defaulted on their āobsā
in Eric Frank Russellās āAnd Then There Were Noneā is a pretty good
illustration of the principle. In short, the injured party would have
access to many remedies short of being treated as actual owner of a
property which he did not occupy.
And I have also repeatedly stressed, in quite conciliatory terms, the
possibility for peaceful coexistence between such rival systems of
property rights rules. In a panarchy or āanarchy without adjectives,ā
there would have to be some sort of meta-agreement between communities
based on different systems of property, in which each one agreed not to
attempt to enforce property rights claims in another community that were
at odds with the local rules. David Friedman has envisioned similar
meta-agreements on questions other than property, in which (say) a
protection agency in the Jerry Garcia Peopleās Collective refused to
defend members against prosecution for adultery against members of the
Sword of Jehovah Covenant Community.
Reisman also ignores the fact that the boundary between Ingalls-Tucker
and Lockean rules is fairly blurry. As Iāve pointed out before, the
thought of Tucker himself underwent some evolution on just how he
imagined his usufructory property system operating. At times, he made a
simple equation of rent to taxation, and argued that tenants should
simply stop paying rent en masse. At others, he seemed to view building
rent as legitimate, and to believe that free access to vacant land would
drive rents down the level of building rent alone, while mutual banking
would drive building rent down to simple amortization costs. But in the
latter case, arguably most vacant land would likewise be consider
unowned under a radical application of Lockean rules.
All of Reismanās arguments on property so far can at least be plausibly
written off as legitimate misunderstandings of a topic with which he
isnāt very familiar. But he proceeds to an argument which puts the
needle on my disingenuousness meter off the end of the dial:
Non-use is alleged justification for legitimate property being seized,
and, as Iāve shown, not just land but also homes and apartments, and by
implication, automobiles, clothing, and everything else that is not
being used by its owner.
Huh?!! Surely anyone even vaguely acquainted with the history of
political economy should be aware that philosophies that treat property
in land as fundamentally different do so for a reason: the almost
totally inelastic supply of sites. That state of affairs has led not
only mutualists and Georgists to see land as different, but even Locke
himself--ever heard of the Lockean Proviso, Herr Doktor? If Reisman
wants to reject such arguments for treating property in land
differently, thatās fine. Rothbard made some pretty good efforts at
countering the Georgist argument from scarcity, although I donāt think
he succeeded. But I have a hard time believing that Reisman is
addle-brained enough to sincerely believe that thereās a danger of
Tuckerites or Georgists applying their scarcity-based theories of
property in land to moveable property. Anyone making such an argument in
a freshman Great Ideas paper would justifiably earn a big red āF.ā
Others in the comments thread have raised questions about the difficulty
of determining how much of a tract was āused,ā how much labor must be
mixed with a given amount of land to establish ownership, and the
potential difficulties encountered by those going on extended vacations
or letting land lie fallow in a crop-rotation system. The proper answer,
of course, is that such questions would be settled by convention in a
local community where the juries setting the rules would be motivated by
a desire to minimize inconvenience. And the reliance on convention in
working out the practical application of mutualist doctrine is no
greater than is the case with Lockean doctrine; one could just as easily
question just what constitutes sufficient admixture of labor for Lockean
homesteading, or what is necessary to construe abandonment or
relinquishment of claim on a piece of property. In fact David Heinrich,
the same commenter who raises questions about an extended vacation,
discusses constructive abandonment of apartment buildings in terms that
considerably undermine Reismanās moral indignation about āsqattersā in
the main post.
One manās āneighborsā is another manās āarmed gangā--to George Reisman,
anyway (he crossposts it to his personal blog, as well).
To get the superficial stuff out of the way first, I canāt help noticing
Reisman is putting āiced-creamā--er, āmutualismā--in quotes, as though
it were something I just invented. Iād like to take credit for it, I
really would, but I donāt think Iād get away with it. Reisman ought to
do a Google on Proudhon, Warren, Tucker, et al. Itās a good thing Iām
not a Galambosian, or Iād be paying royalties on the āphilosophy of
thieves.ā
Reisman makes enough allusions, however distorted, to arguments I made
in my last response, and to arguments I and others made in the comments
at his Mises Blog post, to indicate that he at least attempted to follow
the debate.
But he seems to have gotten fixated on the idea that the main
application of mutualist property theory would be by cuckoos in the
Lockean nest, waiting to surprise unsuspecting landlords after they sign
a lease. He still doesnāt grasp the idea that itās a rival, internally
consistent set of private property rules that could only exist in a
society where majority consensus backed it up. He assumes most of the
present system into existence in his hypothetical scenario, with
mutualist property relations being introduced only through individual
perversity. He changes one little thing in a system that, in every other
particular, is the present one. Ever see that episode of The
Honeymooners where Ralph imagined how heād live as a rich man? āAnd Iād
put a telephone on the fire escape, so I could handle my big business
deals if I had to sleep out there when it was hot.ā I suspect Reisman of
a similar lack of imagination.
He presents a hypothetical case:
Thus, to elaborate on the case I presented in my last post, āMutualism:
A Philosophy for Thieves,ā let us imagine that our legitimate land
ownerālegitimate even by Carsonās standardsāhas spent several years
clearing or draining his land, pulling out stumps, removing rocks and
boulders, digging a well, building a barn and a house, and putting up
fences to keep in his livestock. It is this land that he agrees to rent
to a tenant, or, what is not too different, sell on a thirty-year
mortgage, which he himself will carry, on the understanding that every
year for thirty years he will receive a payment of interest and
principal.
The tenant or mortgagee signs a contractual agreement promising to pay
rent, or interest and principal, and takes possession of the property.
Being a secret mutualist, however, he thereupon proclaims that the
property is now his, on the basis of the mutualist doctrine that, in
Carsonās words, āoccupancy and use is the only legitimate standard for
establishing ownership of land.ā
This is a clear theft not only of the land, but also of the product of
labor. A worker has toiled for years and is now arbitrarily deprived of
the benefit of his labor, and this in the name of the protection of the
rights of workers!
Of course, this case is irrelevant. Mutualist property rules could only
exist on a stable basis if there were a local consensus on them,
embodied in some code of libertarian common law. And under those
circumstances, it would be a singularly obtuse would-be landlord who
entered into such an agreement knowing the local legal system. It would
make about as much sense as somebody in Canada, around 1850, making a
contract in which somebody else sold himself into slavery for $10,000.
Heād be laughed out of court if he attempted to enforce the contract; if
he pleaded hardship for losing his money, the likely response would be
that life is necessarily hard for someone that stupid.
On the other hand, a closeted mutualist tenant who attempted to surprise
his landlord in such a manner, in a Lockean-consensus community, would
fare about as well as an absentee landlord attempting to collect rent in
a Tuckerite-consensus community.
Hereās an opposing case for you: Imagine Iām renting a house under a
Lockean property system, and get permission to plant a garden on it. I
invest a lot of effort in composting and green manuring, and even spend
money on granite dust, greensand, rock phosphate and the like to improve
the soil. When I get done with it, what was hardpan clay has been
transformed into rich, black, friable soil. And when I cease renting, I
lose the value of all the improvements I made. Thatās the sort of thing
that happens all the time under Lockeanism. But I suspect that Reisman
would say that I made the improvements with my eyes open, and am
entitled to no sympathy because I knew what the rules were. I certainly
doubt that heās shedding any tears over the invested labor that the
South Central Farmers are in danger of losing.
The difference is, when it happens under the system heās defending, itās
just life; when it happens under the system heās demonizing, itās an
outrage.
Hereās another example of the same double-standard:
Mutualists pretend that there will be communities in which such behavior
is accepted and routine, and chide opponents for their lack of knowledge
of anthropology for not understanding this. They do not care to admit
that the only thing which can enforce such a practice is the threat of
physical force against those who would put an end to it, i.e., for all
practical purposes, the existence of some form of tyrannical state. Yes,
mutualists are āanarchistsā who turn out to be statists!
And just how could Lockean practice persist unless it was enforced by
similar threats against those who would put an end to it (what Reisman
calls a āstateā)? To put it in more neutral language, neither the
Lockean nor the mutualist property system could function without the
willingness of the majority of oneās neighbors to recognize oneās rights
claims under that system and to back them up with what they perceive as
defensive force, if necessary. If such a consensus, backed up by the
power of the community, is a āstateā under mutualism, then itās also a
āstateā under Lockeanism.
Reisman continues:
It is possible to see why this must be so by starting with a condition
in which there is no government. In this state of affairs, our exploited
worker-victim easily proves to his neighbors that a ālying, thieving
mutualistā has stolen his land and deprived him of the benefit of years
of work. If his neighbors have neither been lobotomized nor castrated,
they will probably contemplate lynching this āmutualist.ā In any case,
they proceed with our victim to his land and are ready forcibly to evict
the āmutualist.ā What will stop them from doing so and thus putting an
end to any practice of Mutualismās depraved concept of āproperty
rightsā?
The only thing that will stop them is the threat or actuality of greater
force exerted by mutualists, i.e., by a mutualist armed gang. If the
mutualist gang has its way, it constitutes a de facto mutualist state,
which must continue in existence indefinitely in order to uphold the
mutualist concept of āproperty rights.ā
See, when thereās a consensus on Lockean rules, and neighbors band
together to enforce each otherās rights under those rules, itās a
defensive action on behalf of all thatās right and holy. When neighbors
band together to enforce a consensus on mutualist rules, on the other
hand, itās a band of thugs.
But any system of property rules requires a majority consensus of people
willing to enforce each otherās rights under that system, and such a
majority will tend to view attempts to enforce any rival system as
āaggression.ā In the one case, Reisman calls it a āstateā or āarmed
gang.ā In the other, he doesnāt. All Reisman proves, in so doing, is
that he likes one system and hates the other--something we already knew.
Refusing to admit any parallel in the cases just demonstrates a
tribalistic emotional attachment to his own set of rules; it certainly
does nothing to validate those rules.
Reisman simply starts from the assumption that the system of rules he
favors is right and proper, and that other systems of rules are
pernicious. He then uses loaded terminology, both god-terms and
devil-terms, to describe analogous phenomena in the respective systems.
I believe itās called begging the question.
Perhaps Iām overpsychologizing things, but Reisman seems almost
pathologically deficient in the empathy or imagination, or whatever it
takes to put oneself in someone elseās place sufficiently to be able to
understand, on its own terms, an argument he disagrees with.
But at least he seems to be attempting to engage, however feebly,
arguments that have been made in response to his last statement--and not
just reasserting his original statements. Thatās a definite improvement.
Addendum. George Reisman isnāt the only person who has attempted to
challenge me with hypothetical scenarios. Iāve been asked more than
once, in various discussion threads at Mises Blog and here, how a
mutualist property system would handle this or that case. The short
answer, in many cases, is āI donāt know.ā
Manuel Lora, an anarcho-capitalist, put it quite well in reference to
his own system:
I cannot provide an answer for every conceivable question regarding the
organization of society. At best, one can offer opinions but not
guarantees. And that does not mean that an answer would not exist, itās
just that right now, itās impossible to know what it is. Furthermore, we
could have several answers and even overlapping answers. With
government, there is only one way to do things. Freedom is unknown, yet
no less valid if weāre today unable to answer questions about a reality
that does not exist. [via iceberg]
I can, however, put forth certain principles that would likely govern
its practical application. Most importantly, any libertarian common law
code based on mutualist property rules would be worked out in a
mutualist community, the community being one made up overwhelmingly of
small property owners who see their own property as the basis of
security and independence, and see the distributive ownership of
property in general as a bulwark of social stability against polarizing
inequality and class conflict. The main evil to be prevented by their
law code, accordingly, would be the concentration of large amounts of
property in a few hands (particularly exclusion of homesteaders from
large tracts of vacant land, or large-scale ownership of many rental
properties by a single landlord).
For situations short of this, such as the one Reisman brings up in his
latest post, the practical application of mutualist principle would be
worked out by the local community in such a way as to avoid stepping on
their own toes; and the majority of people in a community of small
property owners would hardly wish to live in fear that their property
might be seized by a squatter as soon as they went on vacation or let
some of it lie fallow for a year. In other words, their application of
mutualist law would be on the principle that the law is made for man,
rather than the reverse.
For hard cases like the one Reisman presents, there is a variety of ways
a jury of sympathetic neighbors might deal with it in a mutualist legal
system, without undermining the central values of mutualist property
law. I already discussed one possible way: the community might be
willing to enforce a contractual agreement for a post-transfer payment
for transfer of possession, by all means short of dispossessing the new
owner: the remedies of the injuried party might extend to seizure of
movable assets, shunning or exclusion from mutually organized social
services, and the like (for a picture of how this might work, recall the
story about the lazy guy who repeatedly skipped out on his āobsā in
Russellās āAnd Then There Were None,ā and wound up starving because
nobody would do business with him). This would be no more an impairment
of the specifics of such a contract than the absence of debt slavery for
bankruptcy is an impairment of debtorsā obligations in our society.
On the other hand, the community might be willing to evict an occupant
and restore the land to the original owner in cases where fraud was
involved in the transfer of possession, on the grounds that the
transaction was rendered null and void. Such fraud would be equivalent
to violent dispossession, in which case the community would be justified
in the use of force to restore the original owner. (I got this
suggestion from Joshua Holmes, aka Wild Pegasus, in the comments to
Reismanās post).
I can also imagine, consistent with mutualist principle, a local jury
enforcing a contract to pay amortization costs of labor and improvements
in return for a transfer of possession. Thereās no reason they could not
do this, consistent with mutualist principle, and still refuse to
enforce an extended rental agreement.
A mutualist community might do any, or all, or none of these things, or
some that I havenāt thought of. I just donāt know.
Itās interesting that critics portray such practical discretion as
backtracking or inconsistency, when no system could exist without it.
Lockean systems, for example, involve largely conventional provisions
for constructive abandonment and salvage, adverse possession, etc., none
of which can be derived in all its specifics from the basic principles
of Lockean theory. As Sheldon Richman commented, any system, for its
practical application, requires large elements of seemingly arbitrary
convention.
Mutualism, on the other hand, is judged in the worst possible light, on
the assumptions that neighbors either would be looking for the first
opportunity to screw each other over, or would apply some cartoonish
version of pure mutualist principle with no discretion or common sense
whatever.
As I pointed out above, in a mutualist community any landowner who
sought to negotiate payment for a transfer of possession would do so in
the awareness of what the legal code allowed and did not allow. It would
be decidedly odd, in such a community of small landowners, if the common
law did not make some provision for the transfer of possession and
recouping of improvement outlays (perhaps one of the expedients I listed
above, or perhaps some other) other than a thirty year mortgage or an
extended rental. I also wonder about the specifics of the hardship case
that motivated the owner to dispossess himself of the property he had
worked so hard to develop; whatever the specifics, I find it unlikely
that a community of congenial neighbors with a vigorous tradition of
mutual aid would fail to provide any means of hardship relief short of
the alternatives Reisman mentions. Shawn Wilbur, for example, said this
in a comment on an earlier post:
Itās not hard to imagine a mutualism that includes summer homes and
caretaking arrangements. On the other hand, i live in a town where
something like half of the real estate is in the hands of a handful of
folks, who live off the needs of a much larger group of folks for a
place to live. thatās a very different situation. The concentration of
real property here has consequences that make certain kinds of basic
personal security and justice much harder to attain. A mutualist society
would undoubtedly attempt to reorganize itself along other lines.
George Reisman was interviewed on his article āMutualism: A Philosophy
for Thievesā on FMNN eRadio with John St. George (āChemical Aliā Massoud
tipped me off to this). The websiteās blurb about the interview has the
campy feel of Reefer Madness, or a 1950s FBI propaganda film on
āInternational Communismā: āTHE MUTUALIST: Ever lurking, ever searching
to simply āsquatā and take your land. Is this the next step from Eminent
Domain?ā
Of course, Reisman gives mutualist property rights theory the same
clueless overall treatment as he did in āMutualismās Support for
Exploitation of Labor and State Coercion.ā His hypothetical scenarios
all involve, not mutualism as a coherent set of property rules enforced
by majority social consensus in a locality, but as the private
philosophy of some individual con artist attempting to scam an
unsuspecting landlord in a Lockean society. And the need for mutualist
owner-occupiers to appeal to the consensus of their neighbors for
enforcement of their property rights is characterized as dependence on a
state or āband of thugsā for enforcement--even at the same time Reisman
shows Lockeans enforcing their property rights by the very same sort of
appeal to their neighbors. Iāve already dealt with his ham-handed
treatment, at length (see the synopsis of links to the debate at the
bottom of this post).
But here are some more howlers you might enjoy:
Q. Does mutualism have its roots in socialism or communism?
A. Iād say itās about eighty percent Marxism. It accepts Marxās theory
of how wages and profits are determined. See, Marx claimed that profit
income is stolen from the workers, that property... that workers should
have all the income that results. They are the producers, allegedly, and
the businessmen arenāt.
This is the level of knowledge of nineteenth century political
philosophy Iād expect from a B- student in an undergrad Western Civ
class. It would be a lot more accurate to say that the entire socialist
movement, including Marx, Proudhon, and free market radicals like
Hodgskin and the American individualists, all accepted the radical
Ricardian theory of how wages and profits were determined.
The mutualists say you donāt need socialism, the problem [of profits]
would be addressed if the government... didnāt do anything that stood in
the way of banks being formed that would create a flood of new and
additional money that would drive interest rates down close to zero. The
mutualists think that expanding the quantity of money can permanently
reduce the rate of interest and then indirectly the rate of profit
pretty close to zero, and they think the only reason that this doesnāt
happen is the government is restricting the ability of the banking
system to create money.
OK, breathe deeply now. Take a look at this passage from my rejoinder
article, made directly in response to the sort of misreading Reisman
makes above:
On money and banking issues, Rothbard made the mistake of interpreting
the Greene-Tucker system of mutual banking as an attempt at inflationary
expansion of the money supply. Although the Greene-Tucker doctrine is
often casually lumped together (in a broader category of āmoney cranksā)
with social crediters, bimetallists, etc., it is actually quite
different. Greene and Tucker did not propose inflating the money supply,
but rather eliminating the monopoly price of credit made possible by the
stateās entry barriers: licensing of banks, and large capitalization
requirements for institutions engaged in providing only secured loans.
Most libertarians are familiar with such criticisms of professional
licensing as a way of ensuring monopoly income for the providers of
medical, legal and other services. Licensing and capitalization
requirements, likewise, enable providers of credit to charge a monopoly
price for their services.
In fact, Rothbard himself made a similar analysis of the life insurance
industry, in which state reserve requirements served as market entry
barriers and thus inflated the cost of insurance far above the levels
necessary for purely actuarial requirements.
Now, as I see it, there are only three possibilities: 1) Reisman just
goes on repeating his assertion without ever having bothered to read my
response to it; 2) he read my response but is unable to understand how
it contradicts what he wrote; or 3) heās deliberately persisting in a
conscious mischaracterization. So heās either lazy, lacking in reading
comprehension, or a liar. Iād really prefer to believe #1 or #2 because,
despite all my online wrangling with him, he doesnāt seem like a bad
guy--more clueless than malicious.
But for crying out loud, before you criticize something, make sure
youāve got a clue about what youāre criticizing! Iāve been criticized by
Lockeans who actually understand my position (see Roderick Longās review
article in JLS), and believe me, theyāre a lot more effective than
Reisman. It takes a lot less work for me to make fun of a critic who
comes up with howlers like these, than to put the effort into answering
effective criticisms by someone who understands what heās criticizing.
And some people who never heard of mutualism before they saw Reismanās
article have followed the trackbacks to my responses, compared what I
actually said to his clownish mischaracterizations of it, and wound up
thinking the worse of him. Frequent commenter quasibill, who still
disagrees with me on the nature of property rights, learned in that very
way never to trust Reismanās account of anything. Iām just afraid people
will suspect Iām paying Reisman to write this stuff. Heās certainly not
doing himself any favors.
I feel like Iāve lifted up a rock and seen whatās crawling under it.
My immediate reaction was to say ālikewiseā; but I thought better of it,
because I donāt really see Reisman that way. More than anything, Iām a
little taken aback by his utter revulsion, his delenda est,
root-and-branch attitude. Itās as though he just suddenly discovered the
broad segment of free market libertarian thought in this country that
has taken a radical view of land. Heās not only writing off me (big
deal) and Warren and Tucker; heās writing off Henry George, Bolton Hall,
Oppenheimer, Nock, Frank Chodorov, Spencer Heath, etc., etc. Itās not
just that he disagrees with me on the nature of property rights in land
(thatās entirely legitimate), itās that heās entirely incapable of
seeing the Lockean and other more radical strands of classical
liberalism as common members of a larger category. There have been
plenty of radical Lockeans in the Rothbardian camp (including Rothbard
himself) whoāve seen these āland cranksā as fellow travellers (if
misguided ones) in the free market movement, and appreciated their
contributions in areas where they agreed. Reisman, on the other hand,
really does act like heās turned a rock over. But I donāt see how a
āprofessor emeritusā whoās a prominent libertarian figure can be so
abysmally ignorant about the history of his own movement.