💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › john-clark-the-tao-of-anarchy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:12:56. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Tao of Anarchy
Author: John Clark
Date: 1998
Language: en
Topics: taoism, Fifth Estate
Source: Retrieved on 26th April 2021 from https://www.fifthestate.org/archive/351-summer-1998/the-tao-of-anarchy/
Notes: Fifth Estate #351, Summer 1998. This essay originally appeared in John Clark’s now out-of-print The Anarchist Moment: Reflections on Culture, Nature and Power (Black Rose Books, Montreal, 1984) as “Master Lao and the Anarchist Prince.”

John Clark

The Tao of Anarchy

The Lao Tzu is one of the great anarchist classics. [1]

No significant philosophical work of either East or West has been more

thoroughly pervaded by the anarchistic spirit. None of the Western

political thinkers known as major anarchist theorists have possessed a

sensibility or expressed a world view that is as deeply anarchic as

those exhibited in this ancient text.

Anarchism is known perhaps above all for its uncompromising critique of

all forms of domination. Classical anarchism [2] made a considerable

contribution to this critique through its withering attack on the state

and economic exploitation, and through its groundbreaking analysis of

bureaucracy and technological domination.

More recently, the anarchist critique has expanded considerably. With

the growth of feminism has come an awareness of the centrality of

patriarchy to the origin and perpetuation of hierarchical society. And

the emergence of the ecological perspective has led to a careful

examination of human domination of nature. Contemporary anarchist

thought deserves recognition for incorporating these advances in a much

more comprehensive theoretical analysis. However, an examination of the

Lao Tzu reveals that over two millennia ago ancient Taoist thought had

already begun exploring rather profoundly all the dimensions of

domination that have concerned anarchists over the past century and a

half.

While the critique of domination is an important aspect of anarchism,

even more essential is the underlying positive world view that gives

direction to the project of social transformation. Classical anarchist

theory often presented a rather inspiring view of human possibilities,

and questioned certain aspects of the dominant Western world view.

A cooperative, non-dominating society

But although anarchism exhibited some awareness of a need to break with

atomistic individualism, metaphysical dualism and a mechanist view of

nature, none of its major exponents inquired deeply into the ontological

and ethical basis for a cooperative, non-dominating society.

Contemporary anarchist theory has begun to fill this gap, as it moves

toward a more dialectical and holistic anarchism that addresses crucial

philosophical questions. Especially in so far as it is inspired by an

ecological perspective, recent anarchism has begun to reconsider

fundamentally the nature of the self, society and nature. It has begun

to develop a dialectical, holistic view of reality in which the whole

(whether nature, the earth, society or the person) is looked upon as a

unity-in-diversity or unity-in-difference, and in which the development

and fulfillment of the part is seen to depend on its complex

interrelationship with and unfolding within that larger whole.

From such a viewpoint, the good of the natural world as a whole is

attained as each of the wholes it encompasses humanity, other species,

biomes, ecosystems, bio-regionalism their respective goods. Moreover,

the good of the human community is attained through each person

attaining his or her unique good. And further, the person is seen not as

an atomized individual, but as a social self, an embodiment of our

common human nature in its process of historical development, and also

as the most individualized and unique self-expression of reality, the

most ultimately creative process.

The following discussion seeks to show that on almost every key point

the Lao Tzu is in accord with such a dialectical, holistic ecological

anarchism. We discover first that the work teaches that ultimate

reality—Tao—is a holistic unity-in-diversity, that it consists of

interrelated processes of personal and universal self-realization, and

that it is a system of natural order free from domination. Second, we

find that the Lao Tzu sees the Taoist virtues of compassion, frugality,

and non-assertion as the basis for an anarchistic, non-authoritarian

personality and for corresponding non-dominating social relations. And

finally, we see that the work’s conception of the ruler-sage is founded

on an anarchist politics of the anti-political that rejects the state,

law, and coercion.

Perhaps the most pervasive theme of the Lao Tzu is its vision of an

organic unity-in-diversity. One of the most powerful metaphors in the

work is that of “the Uncarved Block” through which we are called back to

a deep, underlying reality, a primordial truth that humanity has largely

forgotten. Our customs, our social conditioning, our language, in fact

the most fundamental categories by which we interpret the world, lead us

to fragment reality, to shatter it violently into a system of

disconnected, or, at best, externally related objects and egos. A basic

problem is to create an awareness of the oneness that underlies this

multiplicity, and to do this without resorting to an illusionism which

denies reality by dissolving plurality into nothingness. Taoism in no

sense seeks an escape from the diversity and complexity of the world. On

the contrary, its unifying vision coexists with an almost Nietzschean

affirmation of individuality.

Yet the concreteness of the Taoist vision goes beyond this. The

perception of the gap between unity-in-diversity and unreconciled

division is firmly rooted in historical reality. It is essential to

understand the Lao Tzu as perhaps the most eloquent expression of

society’s recollection of its lost integrity, an evocation of the

condition of wholeness that preceded the rending of the social fabric by

institutions such as the state, private property, and patriarchy.

Significantly, the Lao Tzu encompasses a ringing condemnation of all

three of these systems, and proposes their replacement by institutions

much closer to the socially organic or holistic ones of tribal

societies. Just as Stanley Diamond has called for an understanding of

Plato which takes into account his relation to these world-historical

transformations (that is, as annihilator of the remnants of tribal

values), so we should see the place of the Lao Tzu in this conflict (as

a reaffirmation of organic society and its values) . [3]

What precisely does the Lao Tzu say about the nature of Tao as unity?

[4] Often it is said to be the origin of everything, that out of which

all arises, that on which all things depend. It is “the ancestor of all

things” (Chan, 4) and “the mother of all things.” (Chan, 1) These images

can be somewhat deceptive if they are taken to imply any separation

between Tao-and the universe. For there is no division: Tao is

all-inclusive and immanent in the Ten Thousand Things. “Analogically,

Tao in the world (where everything is embraced by it), may be compared

to rivers and streams running into the sea.” (Chan, 32) There is thus a

unity that underlies the multiplicity of the universe.

This oneness is not, however, a static unity, but rather the unity of

the interrelated parts of a creative process. This follows from the

assertion that Tao consists of both being and non being. “All things in

the world come from being. And being comes from non-being.” (Chan, 40)

As the opening chapter of the work explains, both being and non-being

are aspects of Tao, and a full comprehension of reality requires

knowledge of both the multiplicity of existing things and also of the

process of generation, the emergence from non-being into being:

“‘Non-Being’ names this beginning of Heaven and Earth;

“‘Being’ names the mother of the myriad things.

“therefore, some people constantly dwell in ‘Non-Being.’

“Because they seek to perceive its mysteries,

“While some constantly dwell in ‘Being’

“Because they seek to preserve its boundaries.

“These two [‘Non-Being’ and ‘Being’] are of the same origin,

“But have different names…” (Young and Ames)

This view of Tao immediately brings to mind many similar concepts in

both Eastern and Western thought. Notable examples include the

distinction in Vedanta between Nirguna and Saguna Brahman, Bohme’s

references to the divine Ungrund and Urgrund, and Eckhart’s evocation of

a Gottheit that is more primordial than even Gott. There have been

numerous attempts to explain the ubiquity of this coexistence of

negative and positive description in mystical and organismic thought of

many traditions. One approach is to stress the fact that in view of the

inadequacy of our objectifying, delimiting language, reality can only be

grasped by contradictory predications. The concept of the ultimate as

the totality captures one aspect of reality: the oneness of all things.

Yet it is necessary to speak of the ultimate as nothingness or

non-being, inasmuch as reality is not a mere collection of all things in

the world, but a unity in which our conventional conceptions of

“thingness” or individuation are negated. [5]

This explains part of what is intended in the Lao Tzu. But further, the

assertion of the ultimacy of both being and non-being is an assault on

all static conceptions of reality. Taoism should not be confused with

forms of organicist thought (or pseudo-organicism) that call for

“identification” with a timeless, spaceless, motionless One. The whole,

like each being, is a process of becoming in which both being and

non-being are ever-present moments. No doubt the mystery of birth was a

tremendous influence in the shaping of this conception. Just as

gestation and birth are processes through which a being emerges and

develops out of the vague and mysterious void, so the universe as being

must arise out of nothingness. Yet this is not to be taken in a mere

mythological or cosmogonal sense, for the process of generation is

asserted to be without beginning. It is thus an explanation of the

enduring structure of reality. The process is repeated in the

origination and development of each being in the universe:

Man models himself after Earth.

Earth models itself after Heaven.

Heaven models itself after Tao.

And Tao models itself after Nature. (Chan, 25)

There is thus a macrocosm-microcosm relationship between the universal

Tao and each being, although this relationship in no way negates the

individuality and uniqueness of each. For in both cases development is a

process of creative-self realization.

According to the Lao Tzu, each being has its own Tao, in the sense of

its own path of self-development and unfolding. While it is true, as

David Hall argues, that Taoism rejects “principles as transcendent

determining sources of order, 11 [6] and as Roger Ames contends, that it

negates such “authoritarian determination” as “teleological purpose,

divine design, Providence, 11 [7] it would be incorrect to conclude that

Taoism dispenses with all teleology. In fact, Tao can perhaps be

described best as the immanent telos of all beings. It is not surprising

that teleology should seem tainted by authoritarianism, given the

character of teleological philosophy from Plato and Aristotle to Hegel

and Marx. But while “orthodox” forms of teleological explanation have

certainly embodied a theoretical will to power and have served to

legitimate class domination, nationalism, and human exploitation of

nature, there is no necessary connection between teleology and

domination. Thus, in the Lao Tzu we find a teleology that recognizes

that each being has its own unique processes of self-development that

should not be imposed upon or distorted by external will or force:

To know harmony means to be in accord with the eternal.

To be in accord with the eternal means to be enlightened.

To force the growth of life means ill omen.

For the mind to employ the vital force without restraint means violence.

After things reach their prime, they begin to grow old, Which means

being contrary to Tao.

Whatever is contrary to Tao will soon perish. (Chan, 55)

The point is that we should allow each being to follow its own ideal

pattern of development, which we cannot “force,” but only hinder,

through our interference. Given the accompanying conditions for

nurturing such growth, a fullness of being will be achieved, after which

comes inevitable decline and dissolution. The famous Taoist image of the

“Uncarved Block” expresses the idea of wholeness entailed in this

self-development. The view of D.C. Lau that it means “a state as yet

untouched by the artificial interference of human ingenuity” [8] partly

misses the mark, since it implies that there can somehow be a pure,

pristine Self independent of human society, and that there is something

necessarily “artificial” about “human ingenuity.” It is true that

“carving the block” means distorting the self by interfering with its

development according to its unique telos, but society does not

necessarily have such an effect (and is, in fact, a necessary part of

attaining such a development).

All human development takes place within the context of social

relationships, and these can be the conditions for either

self-realization or self-limitation. Consequently, “human ingenuity” can

be just as much a means of preserving the “Uncarved Block” in its

uncarved state, as a factor in distorting it. Thus, tribal societies

that conceive of social relations primarily in terms of kinship, and

that hold a vitalistic or panpsychist view of nature, tend to maintain a

high degree of awareness of the social and natural roots of the sell

Civilization, in identifying the self with social status (citizenship,

class membership, property ownership, functional role, etc.) reduces the

organic social self to a narrower individual or abstract ego. The Lao

Tzu looks backward to the primordial unfragmented society and its social

self, just as it points forward to a restored organic society and a

fully social person.

In the concept of the organic self, both Taoism and contemporary

anarchism seek to transcend the narrow limits of “the individual.” As

Roger Ames notes, in a philosophy of organism the person “is understood

as a matrix of relationships which can be fully expressed only by

reference to the organismic whole,” and for this reason “the expression

‘individual’ might well be ruled altogether inappropriate in describing

a person.” [9] For similar reasons there has been a tendency in recent

holistic anarchist thought to explicitly use the term “individual” to

refer to that degraded self fabricated over the long history of social

domination, and finally perfected in modern capitalist, statist,

techno-bureaucratic society. The term “person” is reserved for the

developed social self that can-thrive only in an organic community

embracing humanity and nature.

A balance between order and chaos

Tao is thus both an organic unity-in-diversity and the ideal path of

self-development or unfolding inherent in all things. Its third

important dimension is in a sense merely the synthesis of these two.

Given the organic connectedness of all beings, the totality of all

processes of self-realization constitutes a harmonious system. Tao is

thus a “natural order” that is manifested in the life of each being and

in the functioning of the larger community of beings. As each being

strives to reach its own natural perfection, while refraining from the

quest to dominate other beings, the greatest possible order results.

Thus, the Lao Tzu proclaims the ironic truth that attempts to control

lead to disorder, and that as the degree of control becomes more

extensive, the world becomes more chaotic.

According to Taoist principles, the order of nature depends on a balance

between order and chaos. Just as the collapse of society into excessive

disorder results in tyrannically imposed order, the pursuit of

excessively rigid order produces disorder beyond the bounds of possible

control. Spontaneity and order are not opposites, as is universally held

according to political, technical, and economistic rationality, but are

rather inseparable aspects of the healthy functioning of an organic

whole.

It is on the basis of this analysis that Taoism teaches that if each

being is permitted to follow its Tao, the needs of all can be fulfilled

without coercion and domination. Note the contrast between the generous

and beneficent Tao (the gift-giving Creator Spirit of many cultures) and

the power-crazed, demanding patriarchal authoritarian God (Bakunin’s

“Monster Divine”), who requires abject subservience from his creatures:

All things depend on it for life, and it does not turn away from them.

It accomplishes its task, but does not claim credit for it.

It clothes and feeds all things but does not claim to be master over

them. (Chan, 34)

The Taoist vision penetrates the illusion of inevitable natural scarcity

(an ideology that arose with the technical, political, and economic

innovations of civilization), to apprehend the abundance of the

outpouring of nature. Every society founded on domination and struggle

within society has always perceived the human relation to nature as one

of struggle, conflict, and conquest. No matter how vastly production may

increase, scarcity persists or even expands. But in the Lao Tzu, as in

the consciousness of pre-civilized humanity (the gift economy), nature

is understood to be, rather than a collection of scarce resources, an

infinite wealth, a plenitude:

Heaven and earth unite to drip sweet dew.

Without the command of men, it drips evenly over all. (Chan, 32)

When each follows his or her own Tao, and recognizes and respects the

Tao in all other beings, a harmonious system of self-realization will

exist in nature. (At this point the Lao Tzu begins to formulate

history’s first strongly ecological ethics.) There is a kind of natural

justice that prevails, so that the needs of each are fulfilled:

The Way of Heaven reduces whatever is excessive and supplements whatever

is insufficient.

The Way of Man is different.

It reduces the insufficient to offer to the excessive. (Chan, 77)

According to Lau, in statements such as the above “heaven is conceived

of as taking an active hand in redressing the iniquities of this world,”

and “this runs counter to the view of the Tao generally to be found in

the book as something non-personal and amoral.” [10] But there is no

reason to find such an inconsistency, unless one ignores the striking

metaphysical consistency of the work, and interprets it as a more or

less eclectic anthology of traditional wisdom. For if the Tao is an

all-encompassing natural order, a unity-in-diversity in which the

immanent telos of each being is in harmony with that of all others and

of the whole, then there is no need to posit any sort of personal agency

in the universe responsible for rectifying injustice. Order and justice

are assured when each being follows its appropriate path of development.

All other systems of order are mere social conventions, and to the

degree that they deflect us from our natural end, they produce only

disorder and injustice:

Therefore, only when Tao is lost does the doctrine of virtue arise.

When virtue is lost, only then does the doctrine of humanity arise.

When humanity is lost, only then does the doctrine of righteousness

arise.

When righteousness is lost, only then does the doctrine of propriety

arise.

Now propriety is a superficial expression of loyalty and faithfulness,

and the beginning of disorder. (Chan, 38)

Insofar as morality means social convention, the Lao Tzu advocates a

perspective of “amorality.” But to the degree that it proposes a way of

life founded on universal self-realization unrestricted by domination

and instrumental rationality, it constitutes one of the most distinctive

and significant moral theories ever propounded. In a sense the moral

purpose of the Lao Tzu is its central one, for the emphasis in the work

is never on mere description of the nature of things. The inquiry into

ultimate reality is always firmly embedded in a search for a way of

life, and a true understanding of the work requires that attention be

given to the art of living that it describes. Fortunately, the author

summarizes the essentials of this art very concisely:

I have three treasures.

Guard and keep them: The first is deep love, The second is frugality,

And the third is not to dare to be ahead of the world. (Chan, 67)

While the first Taoist virtue is compassion, some passages in the Lao

Tzu give the impression that not only is love or compassion not

virtuous, but even contrary to nature. For example:

Heaven and Earth are not humane (jen).

They regard all things as straw dogs.

The sage is not humane.

He regards all people as straw dogs. (Chan, 5)

In asserting that the enlightened person regards all people as straw

dogs-worthless ritual objects-the author seems to be rejecting both

humanism and compassion. But this is only half true. While the Lao Tzu

is predicated on a certain kind of anti-humanism (in fact, this is one

of its great strengths), this does not imply a denial of the importance

of compassion. Rather, it is only through a rejection of “humanism” in

the sense of anthropocentrism that the greatest possible compassion can

arise. To act “humanely” means, at worst, merely accepting the

conventions of society concerning morality and goodness, and implies, at

best-, remaining within the biased perspective of species self-interest.

To transcend this “humane” outlook means, as Chan says, to be

“impartial, to have no favorites,” [11] but not in the sense of complete

detachment. Rather, it is the impartiality that results from

identification with the whole, an impartiality that allows one to

respect all beings and value their various goods. [12] For this reason

it is possible to assert that “the Sage has no fixed (personal) ideas.

He regards the people’s ideas as his own,” (Chan, 49) and that “he has

no personal interests.” (Chan, 7)

The person who comprehends Tao is able to take the perspective of the

other, and to overcome the egoism which treats the good of each as

antagonistic to that of the other. This is one of the implications of

the famous passage stating that: “[H]e who values the world as his body

may be entrusted with the empire.”

He who loves the world as his body may be entrusted with the empire.

(Chan, 13)

Some commentators have stressed the implicit approval of a kind of

selfishness in the concept of concern for one’s body. [13] There is an

element of truth in this view, for unless one fully affirms his or her

own existence and process of self-realization, there is no possibility

of truly valuing other beings or of affirming reality. But a further

important implication of the passage is that one should identify with

the whole. Realizing one’s own Tao is identical with participation in

the universal Tao. Thus, all self-realization-one’s own and that of all

others is valued by one who understands Tao. Compassion arises from a

“self love” that has nothing to do with egoism.

The way of life advocated in the Lao Tzu is thus based on love, respect,

and compassion for all beings. If such a life is to be lived, one must

understand the bounds of one’s own Tao: what is essential to one’s own

self-realization, what is unnecessary, and what undermines it and that

of others. The Lao Tzu expresses this idea in its teaching that one

should seek simplicity and frugality, and avoid luxury, extravagance,

and excess.

Some interpretations of the Lao Tzu hold that it advocates “asceticism.”

If this term is defined as a kind of self-denial or self-sacrifice for

the sake of some higher Good, then the truth is just the contrary. And

even if it is construed as a kind of “renunciation” (as it has sometimes

unfortunately been translated) for the sake of one’s own spiritual

growth, this misses the point somewhat. The life of “simplicity” is in

no way the impoverished life of one who seeks escape from the corrupt

world and its temptations. Rather it is something much more affirmative:

it is the consummate existence of one who has rejected whatever would

stunt or distort growth and personal fulfillment.

Simplicity is not, however, a quality with implications for personal

life alone. It refers also to social institutions which will promote

rather than hinder self-realization. A society based on social status,

or one glorifying the pursuit of material wealth and permitting economic

domination, is inevitably destructive, producing conflict, disorder,

envy, and crime:

Do not exalt the worthy, so that the people will not compete.

Do not value rare treasures, so that the people shall not steal.

Do not display objects of desire, so that the people’s hearts shall not

be disturbed. (Chan, 3)

Rather, we should “discard profit.” (Chan, 19) But in doing so, we are

losing nothing, for the pursuit of wealth and social status only

distracts one from the essential task of following one’s authentic way.

Just as the New Testament asks “what would anyone gain by winning the

whole world but losing his own life,” (Matt. 16:26, Mk. 8:36) so the Lao

Tzu places in question the value of wealth and prestige:

Which does one love more, fame or one’s own life? Which is more

valuable, one’s own life or wealth? He who hoards most will lose

heavily. (Chan, 44)

But wealth and luxury are not condemned only because of their

spiritually debilitating quality. There is also a recognition that they

are unjust and contrary to the order of nature. The Lao Tzu attacks the

institutions of civilization on the grounds that whereas nature “reduces

whatever is excessive and supplements what is insufficient,” human

society “reduces the insufficient to offer to the excessive.” (Chan, 77)

The criticism of political and economic institutions is sometimes made

quite explicit:

“The courts are exceedingly splendid,

“While the fields are exceedingly weedy,

“And the granaries are exceedingly empty.

“Elegant clothes are worn,

“Sharp weapons are carried,

“Foods and drinks are enjoyed beyond limit,

“And wealth and treasures are accumulated in excess.

“This is robbery and extravagance.

“This is indeed not Tao (the way).” (Chan, 53)

While this attack on economic and social inequity [14] seems fully in

accord with the anti-hierarchical Taoist outlook, it might seem strange

to some that the Lao Tzu would go so far as to launch an attack on

knowledge and wisdom in the name of simplicity.(” [15] Why would a work

which itself attempts to transmit wisdom about life, and which has

traditionally been attributed to an “Old Sage,” counsel one to “abandon

sageliness and discard wisdom?” (Chan, 19) The truth conveyed is not as

obscure as it might appear initially. In an organic society, knowledge

(like art, religion, and politics) is integrated into the life of the

community, rather than reified as a possession of the privileged members

of a hierarchical institution. The Lao Tzu is attacking knowledge as the

property of an elite intelligentsia or a class of literati. Just as

material wealth sets one against another and seduces people away from

their natural good, so knowledge will do likewise if it is reduced to a

means of amassing power:

“True wisdom is different from much Learning;

“Much learning means little wisdom.

“The sage has no need to hoard;

“When his own last scrap has been used up on behalf of others,

“Lo, he has more than before!” (Waley)

A final important implication of the concept of simplicity is that

certain forms of technology should be rejected and that technical

efficiency must not be accepted uncritically as a justification for

social change. The Lao Tzu exhibits an awareness that technological

development, which has always been justified as fulfilling human needs,

may in fact be destructive of human self-realization and of the social

institutions most conducive to it. It expresses a well-founded fear that

dangerous artificial wants and desires may be created, and that complex,

hierarchical social institutions, accompanied by egoism, inequality, and

disorder may arise. Consequently, the community should reject such

technology and preserve its simplicity:

“Given a small country with few inhabitants, he could bring it about

that though there should be among the people contrivances requiring ten

times, a hundred times less labor, he would not use them.” (Waley)

There is nothing in the Taoist view that implies that new non-dominating

forms of technology should be rejected. But given the fact that actual

technical innovation in the epoch of the Lao Tzu in fact served the

purposes of power and control (as it does in our own day), it is not

surprising that the work should emphasize the need for a more critical

approach to technological change.

Another important theme that runs throughout the Lao Tzu is the

necessity of avoiding competition and other forms of self-assertive and

aggressive action. What is proposed instead is “non-action” or

“actionless action” (wu-wei), activity which is in accord with one’s own

Tao and with those of all others. Since one achieves the good life by

following one’s own unique path, there is no point in striving to place

oneself “above” others. In fact to do so is self-destructive, since in

competing we subordinate ourselves to some external standard of

goodness, virtue, or success. Even if we “win,” we are defeated, since

we have conformed to the alien values of those whom we have vanquished.

Competition conflicts with Taoism’s “polycentric” viewpoint, as David

Hall calls it. Such a viewpoint emphasizes individuality and the

uniqueness of each being, and excludes individualism, which is

necessarily a comparative and competitive mentality. The Taoist sage

will therefore “succeed” through eschewing the quest for power and

prestige:

He does not show himself; therefore he is luminous.

He does not justify himself; therefore he becomes prominent.

He does not boast of himself, therefore he is given credit.

He does not brag; therefore he can endure for long.

It is precisely because he does not compete that the world cannot

compete with him. (Chan, 22)

In describing such a non-aggressive, non-dominating personality, the Lao

Tzu continually resorts to images of the female and the child. Roger

Ames correctly notes that the Taoist advocates a form of androgyny in

which “the masculine and feminine gender traits are integrated in some

harmonious and balanced relationship.” [16] This is the clear

implication of the statement that:

“He who knows the male (active force) and keeps to the female (the

passive force or receptive element)

“Becomes the ravine of the world.” (Chan, 28)

The concept of rigidly defined sex roles is totally alien to the Taoist

sensibility, since this implies subordinating the unique person to

social convention, and denying the diversity of human nature. It is

another example of cutting the “Uncarved Block,” or interfering brutally

with Tao.

But there is a good reason why, in spite of its androgynism, the Lao Tzu

should stress heavily the importance of the female. For it is launching

a direct (if non-aggressive!) attack on one of history’s most entrenched

and enduring systems of domination: patriarchy. Under a patriarchal

system there is little need to emphasize the value of “masculine”

qualities. What is required is a vehement defense of the “feminine.”

Furthermore, while it is true-that “masculine” qualities are recognized

in the Lao Tzu to be of value, those usually stereotyped by most

societies as “feminine” seem in fact to be the more essential ones to

the Taoist perspective. In a revealing passage, creativity and love (in

the non-possessive “maternal” sense) are identified as “feminine”:

“Can you understand all and penetrate all without taking any action?

“To produce things and to rear them,

“To produce, but not to take possession of them,

“To act, but not to rely on one’s own ability,

“To lead them, but not to master them–

“This is called profound and secret virtue (hsuan-te).” (Chan, 10)

In a Taoist community, people are permitted to develop according to

their own Tao, so that to the extent that “masculinity” and “femininity���

exist (as contrasting, but not opposed qualities), they are spontaneous

and natural. An infinite variety in combinations of qualities might

occur. Without imposed sex roles, an anarchistic, non-prescriptive

androgyny is the ideal. However, if we limit our consideration to the

strictly opposed sex roles of patriarchal society, no reconciliation of

the antagonistic roles is possible, and the “feminine” must be selected

as being closer to the ideal.

For similar reasons Taoism often presents the child as the model of

virtue. This is also heretical from the perspective of patriarchal

societies. Since virtuousness is conventionally identified with the

power and status of the adult male, the recommendation that adults

emulate infants appears ludicrous at best. Yet for anti-patriarchal

Taoism, the child has two essential qualities in abundance:

non-aggressiveness and spontaneity. While in a society based on

hierarchical power, strength is valued greatly as a personal

characteristic, in the Taoist society founded on “natural order” and

unity-in-difference one should seek “the highest degree of weakness like

an infant.” (Chan, 10) The infant is not ruled by inordinate desires,

such as the longing for power, wealth, status, or luxury. Instead, all

actions are natural and spontaneous. As the Lao Tzu states in an

irrefutable argument:

He may cry all day without becoming hoarse,

This means that his (natural) harmony is perfect. (Chan, 55)

Just as in nature the softest and weakest thing, water, can overcome the

hardest obstacle, so softness and weakness are the most effective

qualities in personal development. Softness characterizes the organic,

while hardness is typical of the inorganic and mechanistic. Rigidity,

both mental and physical, is an attribute of the authoritarian. Rigid

muscles and rigid categories are two closely related armaments in the

futile battle to stop the flow of reality. As Wilhelm Reich explains,

“character armor” is the means by which the authoritarian personality

seeks to avoid the threat of feeling and experiencing too much. [17] The

Lao Tzu states the same point:

When a man is born, he is tender and weak.

At death he is stiff and hard.

All things, the grass as well as trees, are tender and supple while

alive.

When dead, they are withered and dried.

Therefore the stiff and the hard are companions of death.

The tender and weak are companions of life. (Chan, 76)

What then can be said of a society obsessed with economic and political

power, a society riddled with bureaucratic and technocratic

organization, a society convinced that “security” comes from military

strength (in short, of civilization in its most advanced state)? From

the Taoist viewpoint such a society is striving to reduce people to a

condition of living death. Our society, even more than the one existing

in the era of the ‘Lao Tzu, possesses all the qualities that are the

target of the work’s devastating attack. It illustrates well how a

holistic, organicist philosophy implies an anarchist critique of both

the institutions of an inorganic society based on power relations and of

the character structures that prevail in such a society.

In view of this critique, it is true, as Roger Ames argues, that Taoism

should not be judged “quietistic,” as it often is when its discussion of

the feminine, the childlike, weakness, and softness are not analyzed

carefully. [18] When power is combated by means of its own methods

(“strength”), power inevitably prevails, no matter which side is

victorious. But despite its rejection of aggressiveness, Taoism does not

propose a quietistic withdrawal from the world. Rather, it contends that

the foundations of power can be undermined by “rivers and streams

flowing to the sea.” (Chan, 32) By this is meant the liberation of other

powers-the powers of self-realization–of both humanity and nature.

In spite of all its anti-authoritarianism, one might conclude that what

the Lao Tzu advocates is at best quasi-anarchistic, in view of the fact

that the work is explicitly addressed to the ruler, and because the

existence of the state is accepted. While Roger Ames argues for the

coherence of the idea of Taoist anarchism, he contends that the Lao Tzu

does not fully adopt this position, since it “sees the state as a

natural institution, analogous perhaps to the family. [19] Frederic

Bender goes even further, concluding that the work is “hardly

anarchistic in the Western sense, since it retains, albeit in improved

form, ruler, rule, and the means of rule (the state).” [20]

But in fact the Lao Tzu dispenses with all of these, if they are taken

in their political sense. Its major divergence from classical Western

anarchism is that, given its more thorough rejection of patriarchy,

technological domination, and domination of nature, and given the

greater coherence of its metaphysical foundations, the Lao Tzu is more

consistently anarchistic. In fact the Lao Tzu expresses an entirely

negative view of government. It is true that occasionally it sounds as

if only the excesses of political control are condemned:

The people starve because the ruler eats too much tax grain….

They are difficult to rule because their ruler does too many things.

(Chan, 75)

Such a passage might be taken to mean that good rulers would tax less

and control people less. But in the context of the work’s overall

perspective “good rule” can only mean “no rule,” that is, ruling without

such measures as taxation and control. The idea of governmental “abuse”

is absurd from the standpoint of the Lao Tzu, in view of the fundamental

and absolute nature of its critique of government. As the ego is to the

organic self, so is political society to the organic community. In both

cases the Lao Tzu uses the image of the carving of the block:

Without law or compulsion, men would dwell in harmony.

Once the block is carved, there will be names. (Waley)

“Naming” refers to reifying dynamic processes, destroying natural unity,

and reducing the organic to the inorganic. And this is indeed the

transformation that took place with the rise of the state. The organic,

holistic community was divided or “cut up” into a society of classes, of

rulers and ruled, of rich and poor, of elites and masses, and, finally,

of individuals contending for power, or, at worst, mere “survival.” The

Lao Tzu shows an acute awareness of the contrast between previous

organic society and existing political society, an awareness that must

have been heightened by the intense degree of strife prevailing in its

time. Yet the central objection to government is metaphysical: it is a

distortion of reality, a destruction of the natural order of society,

the replacement of Taoist “non-action” by control and domination.

Government, ruling, and domination are the sources of disorder. This is

the political message of the Lao Tzu:

The people are difficult to keep in order because those above them

interfere.

This is the only reason why they are so difficult to keep in order.

(Waley)

What is strange is not this seemingly paradoxical statement, but rather

the fact that after over two thousand years of evidence to support it,

it still seems paradoxical.

If the Lao Tzu is correct, then the more laws there are, the more

disorganized society will be; the more prisons are built, the more crime

will increase; the more bureaucracy proliferates and experts are

trained, the more social problems are aggravated; the more military

power expands, the more conflicts occur and the more the threat of

destruction looms larger. (Consequences such as these are predicted in

Chapters 57 and 58 of the Lao Tzu.) And these have in fact been

precisely the results of the political organization of society. Every

expansion of political domination for the sake of maintaining order has

only further destroyed the organic structure of society, thus advancing

social disintegration and producing more deeply rooted disorder.

But can the proposed alternative to political society, a

non-authoritarian, cooperative society, possibly exist? Frederic Bender

thinks that it cannot, although it is not entirely clear what it is that

he considers impossible (a non-coercive social system, a society

“lacking entirely in institutionalized authority,” a “social organism”

without “someone exercising authority,” or a society practicing

“unanimous direct democracy”). [21] He argues that the fact that such

societies never existed is evidence that they are not possible. However,

there have indeed been societies without “institutional authority” in

the sense of a separate, permanent stratum of officials holding coercive

power. Bender cites the existence of the authority of “elders, chiefs,

shamans, and the like” as evidence for “systems of authority” in all

societies. [22] But to really understand the relevance of these

phenomena to anarchism, it is necessary to analyze carefully the meaning

of “authority” in each case and the sense in which it constitutes a

“system.”

Anthropology presents us with abundant evidence that “authority” in

tribal society differs radically from that of political society. To give

just one example, while the “chief’ is often assumed by the European

mind to be a political ruler, in fact, he (or sometimes she) has often

been primarily a ritual figure, or one with carefully delineated,

non-coercive functions dealing with specific areas of group life.

Discussions of societies without states or authoritarian political

structures have been discussed at length in works such as

Evans-Pritchard’s The Nuer, Levi-Strauss’ Tristes Tropiques, Tait and

Middleton’s Tribes Without Rulers, Dorothy Lee’s Freedom and Culture,

and, above all, Pierre Clastres’ Society Against the State. [23].

Clastres’ conclusions based on the study of many Amerindian tribes are

especially striking:

“One is confronted, then, by a vast constellation of societies in which

the holders of what elsewhere would be called power are actually without

power; where the political is determined as a domain beyond coercion and

violence, beyond hierarchical subordination; where, in a word, no

relation of command-obedience is in force.” [24]

To say that such societies have existed is certainly not to say that

they fully embody the anti-authoritarian ideal of anarchism. Yet an

exploration of the nature of organic societies of the past serves to

show what was lost with the rise of civilization, and what might be

regained in a more self-conscious form in the future. It also helps us

understand that there are many kinds of authority, and that some imply

neither membership in a special office-holding group possessing coercive

power, nor even “authoritarianism” in any sense. The Taoist ruler-sage

is an example of one who exercises such non-dominating authority. This

authority is, however, much closer to the anarchist ideal than is that

of the tribal chief or elder. For whereas these figures often have no

personal power at all, they may serve as vehicles through whom the

restrictive force of tradition is transmitted. The Taoist ruler, on the

other hand, imposes nothing on others, and refuses to legitimate his or

her authority through the external supports of either law or tradition.

The Lao Tzu teaches that people should not (and, in fact, cannot) be

coerced into doing “the right thing.” This follows from the

internal-development, immanent-good teleology of Taoism (which is

opposed to the hierarchical-good teleology of Aristotle, the

external-good teleology of utilitarianism, and the transcendent-good

teleology of many Western religious views, for example). The sage does

not attempt to legislate or require the good:

I take no action and the people of themselves are transformed.

I love tranquility and the people of themselves become correct.

I engage in no activity and the people of themselves become prosperous.

I have no desires and the people of themselves become simple. (Chan, 57)

In view of this conception of the true ruler as one who does not

interfere with the development of others, there is no reason to think

that the sage is what is called in political terminology a “ruler.” As

Lau notes, “the sage is first and foremost a man who understands the

Tao, and if he happens also to be a ruler he can apply his understanding

of the Tao to government.” [25] To this it must be added, first, that

the anti-patriarchal Lao Tzu never implies that only men can be sages,

and, secondly, that its application of “understanding of Tao” to

government means not governing. Attempts to interpret the Lao Tzu as a

manual of strategy in the “art of governing” inevitably fail. They

require a rather extreme literal-mindedness, in which “ruling” must

always mean holding political office, and “weapons” must always mean

military, rather than spiritual arms. [26] The meaning attributed to

rulership in the Lao Tzu is clear: it is the “nobility” that comes from

identification with Tao, and with successfully following one’s path of

self-realization:

To know the eternal is called enlightenment.

Not to know the eternal is to act blindly and to result in disaster.

He who knows the eternal is all–embracing.

Being all-embracing, he is impartial.

Being impartial, he is kingly (universal). (Chan, 16)

The power of the ruler is thus not political; it comes from the force of

example alone. It is for this reason that the Lao Tzu can assert that

“the best (rulers) are those whose existence is (merely) known by the

people.” (Chan, 17)

In fact, in several versions of the text the best rulers are “not” known

by the people. [27] Presumably, they are not known as rulers or leaders

in the ordinary sense, although they are known as models of personal

development. In either case a subtle, non-coercive authority is

attributed to the ruler. There is nothing in this kind of authority that

is contrary to anarchism. It is neither imposed on anyone nor used to

manipulate.

On the contrary, it is the result of the most non-aggressive activity,

and can only exist if “the people,” seeing the sage following the Oath

of non-dominating self-realization, freely choose to do likewise.

Thus, the Lao Tzu does not propose the continuation of traditional

political authority, but instead replacement by natural authority. The

“empire” that is ruled by the sage is not the political state, but

rather the natural order that is attained by the affirmation of one’s

own Tao and that of all other beings.

The Lao Tzu proclaims implicitly what is stated explicitly in the Huai

Nan Tzu: “Possessing the empire” means “self-realization.” [28]

[1] The Lao Tzu or Tao to Ching is one of the great philosophical

classics of world literature. Taoism, which takes much of its

Inspiration from the work, is (with Confucianism and Buddhism) one of

the three great traditions of thought and practice spanning much of the

history of Chinese civilization. The Lao Tzu has over the ages appealed

to diverse groups of readers. Some have found in it philosophical

enlightenment: others, a path to mystical experience; and still others,

knowledge of the means for personal growth. In recent years, many

Western readers have given it more careful attention, as the growth of

ecological consciousness has uncovered fatal limitations in Western

views of nature, and the Taoist philosophy of nature has been looked to

as a more adequate alternative.

[2] By “classical” anarchism I mean the tradition associated closely

with the international workers’ movement. This tradition began in the

mutualism of the French labor movement of the 1840s, spread across much

of Europe and Latin America by the early 20^(th) century in the form of

anarcho-communism and, especially, anarcho-syndicalism, and ended with

the precipitous decline of anarcho-syndicalism after the defeat of the

Spanish Revolution in the late 1930s.

[3] “Plato and the Defense of the Primitive” in In Search of the

Primitive: A Critique of Civilization (New Brunswick: Transaction Books,

1974), pp. 176–202.

[4] References to the Lao Tzu in the text will cite the translator and

the number of the chapter cited. The following translations and

commentaries are cited in the text: Wing-Tsit Chan, “The Lao Tzu” in A

Source Book in Chinese Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University

Press, 1963), which will be the primary source cited; R.B. Blakney, The

Way of Life (New York: New American Library, 1955); Rhett Y.W. Young and

Roger T. Ames, Lao Tzu: Text, Notes, and Comments (by Ch’en Ku-ying)

(Taiwan: Chinese Materials Center, 1981); D.C. Lau, Lao Tzu: Tao te

Ching (Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books, 1963); and Arthur Waley,

The Way and Its Power. A Study of the Tao te Ching and Its Place in

Chinese Thought (New York: Grove Press, 1958).

[5] Cf. John Findlay, “The Logic of Mysticism” in Religious Studies

(1972).

[6] David Hall, “The Metaphysics of Anarchism,” Journal of Chinese

Philosophy (1983) 10 (1983): 58–59.

[7] Roger Ames, “Is Political Taoism Anarchism?” in Ibid., p. 34.

[8] Lau, p. 36.

[9] Ames, pp. 31, 30.

[10] Lau, p. 24.

[11] Chan, p. 142.

[12] See Holmes Welch’s excellent discussion of this passage in Taoism:

The Parting of the Way (Boston: Beacon Press, 1957), pp. 4445.

[13] See Lau, p. 40, and Waley, pp. 157–158.

[14] I say “inequity” in an effort to stress that Taoism does not

advocate ‘equality,” but rather a system of values in which equality and

inequality have no meaning.

[15] A reductive simplification is often the result of the growth of

complex, inorganic social institutions. The social self has the kind of

rich complexity that is the goal of Taoist “simplicity.”

[16] Roger Ames, “Taoism and the Androgynous Idea,” in Historical

Reflections/Reflexions Historiques 8 (1981): 43.

[17] See Wilhelm Reich, The Mass Psychology of Fascism (New York: Simon

and Schuster, 1970).

[18] This is the case with Murray Bookchin’s “anarchist” and “social

ecological” attacks on Taoism. With a condescending assurance of

Taoism’s theoretical incoherence and political ineffectuality, this

champion of Western rationality parodies its philosophical content,

recklessly quotes passages out of context, and rewrites history

selectively.

[19] Ames, “Political Taoism,” p. 35.

[20] Frederic Bender, “Taoism and Western Anarchism: A Comparative

Study,” in Journal of Chinese Philosophy 10 (1983): 12.

[21] Ibid., p. 22.

[22] Ibid.

[23] E.E. Evans-Pritchard, The Nuer (London: Oxford University Press,

1940); Claude Levi-Strauss, Tristes Tropiques (New York: Pocket Books,

1977); David Tait and John Middleton, Tribes Without Rulers (London:

Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1958); Dorothy Lee, Freedom and Culture

(Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1959); Pierre Clastres, Society

Against the State: The Leader as Servant and the Humane Uses of Power

Among the Indians of the Americas (New York: Urizen Books, 1977).

[24] Clastres, p. 5.

[25] Lau, p. 32.

[26] For some of the Lao Tzu‘s fascinating insights on the nature of war

and self-defense, see chapters 31, 36 and 69.

[27] Chan, p. 148.

[28] Cited in Ames, “Political Taoism,” p. 36.