💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › janet-biehl-bookchin-breaks-with-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:04:16. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Bookchin Breaks with Anarchism
Author: Janet Biehl
Date: 2007
Language: en
Topics: Murray Bookchin
Source: Retrieved on 20 January 2011 from http://www.communalism.net/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=189:bookchin-breaks-with-anarchism&catid=84:movement&Itemid=2][www.communalism.net]].  Proofread online source [[http://www.revoltlib.com/?id=4142, retrieved on November 20, 2020.
Notes: From Communalism

Janet Biehl

Bookchin Breaks with Anarchism

For much of his adult life Murray Bookchin was known as a major

anarchist theorist, perhaps the most wide-ranging and innovative of the

twentieth century. When he died in July 2006, the Times (London) Online

called him “the most important anarchist thinker in North America for

more than a quarter of a century.”[1] But the fact is that by the time

of his death Murray no longer identified himself as an anarchist.

As early as 1995 he was telling the people closest to him that he no

longer considered himself part of that movement. At a conference in 1999

in Plainfield Vermont he made the rupture public; and he put it in

writing in 2002, in an article published online.

The break, however, was fairly easy to miss. After he died, I noticed

that many of his admirers did not realize that he had parted ways with

anarchism, or if they did, they did not understand the reasons for it.

The story therefore needs telling. As his companion and collaborator for

almost two decades (our relationship began in March 1987 and continued

to his death), I had a front-row seat to watch the events unfold. I am

writing this article to tell what I know and saw about Murray Bookchin’s

break with anarchism.

Ecology

Murray always said that to understand a thing, you have to know its

history. So to understand what happened with him and anarchism, we must

first go back to the 1950s, when he was undergoing his transition from

Marxism to anarchism.

In 1948, as a member of the United Auto Workers and a shop steward,

Murray participated in a large United Auto Workers strike against

General Motors that resulted in the workers winning quarterly

cost-of-living increases, company-paid health insurance and pension

funds, and extended paid vacations — in exchange for abjuring walkouts

for two years. That outcome convinced him that the working class, as

such, was not going to be the primary revolutionary agent. Contrary to

Marxist predictions, capitalism was not going to so “immiserate” the

working class that it rose up in rebellion against it. Rather, workers

were going to try to make improvements in their working conditions

within capitalism.

This realization must have been highly distressing to Murray. He was,

after all, a committed anticapitalist revolutionary. If workers were not

going to overthrow capitalism, then who would, and under what

circumstances? What, if any, were the limits to capitalism? In those

years he was developing an interest in environmental issues such as

chemicals — pesticides and herbicides — commonly used in and agriculture

and in food preservation; he thought they might have deleterious health

effects, even causing cancer. He wrote about the subject in 1952 in a

long essay called “The Problem of Chemicals in Food.”[2] Perhaps the

limits of capitalism, he thought, were environmental or ecological in

nature. But those problems affected everyone, regardless of class. The

revolutionary agent, in an ecological rebellion against capitalism,

would then be not the working class but the community as a whole.

Opposition to capitalism could become a general, transclass interest.

This assumption — that citizens, not workers, were the revolutionary

agent of greatest significance — remained foundational for the rest of

his life.

Where had Murray’s ideas about ecology come from? Surprisingly,

considering some of his later writings, they came from Marxism itself.

“I wrote my earliest, almost book-length work on the ecological

dislocations produced by capitalism, ‘The Problems of Chemicals in

Food,’ in 1952,” he recalled forty years later, “while I was a

neo-Marxist and had in no way been influenced by anarchist thinkers.”[3]

He would in later years bitterly criticize Marxism for its

anti-ecological premises (in, for example, the 1979 “Marxism as

Bourgeois Sociology”). But in the early 1950s, while he was still a

Marxist, he had come upon passages in Engels that got him thinking about

nonhuman nature and about ecology as a social phenomenon. “My basic

ideas on an ecological society really came from my decades-long studies

of the Athenian polis, Hegel, and even Marx. Specifically, my thinking

on ecology was instigated not by the works of any anarchist thinker but

by Marx and Engels’s remarks on the need to reconcile town and

country.”[4] A passage in Friedrich Engels’s Anti-Dühring was

particularly fascinating:

Abolition of the antithesis between town and country is not merely

possible. It has become a direct necessity. ... the present poisoning of

the air, water and land can be put to an end only by the fusion of town

and country.”[5]

Another passage from Engels was also thought provoking, this one from

the 1872 The Housing Question:

The housing question can be solved only when society has been

sufficiently transformed for a start to be made towards abolishing the

contrast between town and country, which has been brought to its extreme

point by present-day society. Far from being able to abolish this

antithesis, capitalist society on the contrary is compelled to intensify

it day by day.[6]

Such passages led Murray to the insight that our present social order is

on a collision course with the natural world (“town and country”) and

that we must have an anticapitalist revolution in favor of an ecological

society. That being the case, he realized, he had to define the nature

of the postrevolutionary society. What would an ecological society look

like? An observation from Engels was striking: because it required a

“uniform distribution of the population over the whole country” it would

necessitate “the physical decentralization of the cities.”[7]

Accordingly, Murray wrote in 1962 that decentralization was essential

for an ecological society:

Some kind of decentralization will be necessary to achieve a lasting

equilibrium between society and nature. Urban decentralization underlies

any hope of achieving ecological control of pest infestations in

agriculture. Only a community well integrated with the resources of the

surrounding region can promote agricultural and biological diversity.

... a decentralized community holds the greatest promise for conserving

natural resources, particularly as it would promote the use of local

sources of energy [and use] wind power, solar energy, and hydroelectric

power.[8]

Anarchism

Given he importance of decentralization, Marxism (despite Engels’s

remark) was not the most congenial ideological home for Murray’s new

ecological ideas. In the late 1950s he had been attending meetings of

the Libertarian League in New York and learning about anarchism. As he

later recalled, what led him to turn from Marxism to that alternative

revolutionary tradition was “not any extensive readings into the works

of early anarchists” like Proudhon, Bakunin, and Kropotkin. Rather it

was “my reaction against Marx and Engels’s critiques of anarchism, my

readings into the Athenian polis, George Woodcock’s informative history

of anarchism, my own avocation as a biologist, and my studies in

technology that gave rise to the views in my early essays.”[9] The first

anarchist work that Murray read was Herbert Read’s brief essay “The

Philosophy of Anarchism,” Read being “one of the few anarchists whose

writings I could find” in the late 1950s and early 1960s. [10]

An anarchist society, existing without the state, would by definition be

a decentralized society. “An anarchist society,” Murray wrote, ”should

be a decentralized society, not only to establish a lasting basis for

the harmonization of man and nature, but also to add new dimensions to

the harmonization of man and man.”[11] Other anarchist principles as

well seemed to converge with his ecological ideas, so much so that in

his eyes anarchism and ecology seemed tailor made for each other. One

example is the principle of differentiation (which Read mentions in his

essay). To Murray (whose lifelong philosophical grounding was in the

Hegelian dialectic), differentiation — a Hegelian concept — seemed to

have an affinity to the organic, the organismic, and the ecological:

“Progress is measured by the degree of differentiation within a society.

... Both the ecologist and the anarchist view differentiation as a

measure of progress. ... to both the ecologist and the anarchist, an

ever-increasing unity is achieved by growing differentiations.”[12]

Another key concept in the convergence was diversity, considering “the

ecological principle of wholeness and balance as a product of

diversity.” “An expanding whole is created by the diversification and

enrichment of its parts,” he wrote; and “I submit that an anarchist

community would approximate a clearly definable ecosystem: it would be

diversified, balanced and harmonious.” And: “To sum up the

reconstructive message of ecology: if we wish to advance the unity and

stability of the natural world, if we wish to harmonize it, we must

conserve and promote variety.”[13]

Murray articulated these points of convergence between anarchism and

ecology in his path-breaking 1964 article “Ecology and Revolutionary

Thought.” As he put them all together, they led him to affirm that “an

anarchist society, far from being a remote ideal, has become a

precondition for the practice of ecological principles.”[14] Anarchism

had further appeal for him, in what he saw as its rich revolutionary

antecedents: in the German Peasant Wars of the 1500s; in the Diggers of

1640s England; in the Enragés of French Revolution; in the Paris

Communards of 1871; and above all in the Spanish Revolution.

Perhaps in retrospect it seems opportunistic to try to marry one’s

preexisting ideas to an existing ideology. But in the early 1960s

anarchism seemed like a historical relic, more or less up for grabs. Few

people in Europe and North America were interested in it as an ideology.

In 1962 (the year Murray published Our Synthetic Environment, with the

passages about decentralization) the historian George Woodcock

pronounced anarchism all but dead, after its last flowering in Spain in

1936–39.

Today there are still thousands of anarchists scattered thinly over many

countries of the world. There are still anarchist groups and anarchist

periodicals, anarchist schools and anarchist communities. But they form

only the ghost of the historical anarchist movement, a ghost that

inspired neither fear among governments nor hope among peoples nor even

interest among newspapermen. Cleary, as a movement, anarchism has

failed. ... During the past forty years the influence it once

established has dwindled, by defeat after defeat and by the slow

draining of hope, almost to nothing.[15]

Just as Murray was engaging with anarchism, then, anarchism was on life

support. By infusing it with parallel concepts from what he would call

“social ecology,” he did more than anyone else in the 1960s to

resuscitate anarchism. And indeed by promoting this refurbished

anarchism, by indefatigably writing and lecturing about it to the

counterculture and the New Left in the United States and Europe, he gave

rise to a revival of interest in anarchism itself.

As Murray would later point out, anarchism seems to have always been

most functional when merged with another ideology or set of ideas. For

example, synthesized with syndicalism, or trade unionism, it became

anarcho-syndicalism, one of its more significant tendencies and the

banner under which the greatest anarchist experiment of all was

conducted, the Spanish Revolution. Synthesized with communism, the idea

of the abolition of private property and distribution according to need,

it became anarcho-communism, a libertarian form of communism. In some

sense anarchism functions best as part of a duality.

The marriage of ecology and anarchism appeared to be no exception, and

Murray dedicated himself passionately to advancing the ideas. He felt

confident and even militant about his choice: his 1969 essay “Listen,

Marxist!” represented, not simply a warning to the SDS to avoid a

takeover by Maoists of the Progressive Labor Party, but also his

definitive personal break with Marxism as the ideology by which he

defined himself. He took pride when, a few years later, Victor Ferkiss

identified him with a tendency that he called “eco-anarchist.”[16]

Post-scarcity, hierarchy, and spontaneity

In the following decade Murray went on to elaborate his anarchist ideas,

developing them into a social theory of great richness and depth.

Anarchist history and ideas seemed to stir his extraordinarily fecund

theoretical imagination. One idea after another struck him as relevant

to the ecology-anarchist project, and he enthusiastically incorporated

into it a number of innovative ideas.

One was post-scarcity, the idea that the leisure time potentially

afforded to all in present-day Western societies need not necessarily

lead to complacency or embourgeoisement but could provide the freedom to

create a cooperative society. A high level of technological achievement

promised to eliminate the toil and drudgery and thereby to open the

doors to political participation to people of all classes. The working

class itself could even be its way out demographically: thanks to

automation technologies, jobs performed by people were increasingly

performed by machines. Murray saw this development as potentially

positive, as it could give people the free time to function as political

beings in their communities. Having worked as a foundryman and

autoworker as a young man, he personally experienced the drudgery of

factory work and understood well the difficulty of political activity

while forced to work under such circumstances. Post-scarcity, he

concluded, was potentially liberatory.

Another major innovation that he brought to anarchism was the critique

of hierarchy and domination, which he came to consider the authentic

“social question.”[17] Social hierarchies, he came to believe, were more

fundamental than economic classes, existing as they did long before

capitalism. It was through hierarchies that social strata dominated one

another. Indeed, social hierarchies gave rise to the idea of dominating

nature. The concept of hierarchy was thus of great relevance to Murray’s

still-developing “social ecology.”[18]

Murray may not have been the first libertarian social theorist to write

about hierarchy, but he towered above all others in elaborating it as a

significant social-political concept. In his elaborate dialectical

exposition of hierarchy, The Ecology of Freedom, he tried to do what

Marx had done with capital: show its emergence, its inner tensions, its

limits, its downfall. He turned to anthropology to trace its origins; to

history to trace its development; and to ethics and philosophy to

foresee possibilities for its downfall.[19] Published in 1982, The

Ecology of Freedom became an anarchist classic and a cornerstone of

social ecology, while the critique of hierarchy has become conventional

in anarchist thinking. [20]

Still another point of convergence between anarchism and ecology was the

emphasis on spontaneity: “Every development must be free to find its own

equilibrium. Spontaneity, far from inviting chaos, involves releasing

the inner forces of a development to find their authentic order and

stability. ... Spontaneity in social life converges with spontaneity in

nature to provide the basis for an ecological society.”[21] The concept

had its social parallel not only in previous anarchist writing but in

revolutionary history and theory itself. Historically, Murray observed,

the initial stage of revolutions tended to be spontaneous; revolutionary

peoples created revolutionary institutions spontaneously, as the

Parisians of 1793 did with their sectional assemblies, and the Russians

of St. Petersburg and Moscow in 1905 with their soviets, and as the

Spanish anarchists did in 1936 with their collectives. Its convergence

with the ecological concept of spontaneity made it newly relevant.

Murray went on in the 1970s to make further contributions to both

eco-anarchism and to anarchism as such. He pioneered exploration of

alternative energy sources and eco-technics in his 1965 essay “Towards a

Liberatory Technology.” In the 1970s he developed a distinction between

ecology (inherently radical) and environmentalism (reformist). He

explored the history of Spanish anarchism in The Spanish Anarchists

(1977). He nuanced his ideas by finding intellectual affinities with the

libertarian socialism of Western Marxism (the Frankfurt School). He

often wrote under the rubric of social ecology but sometimes seemed to

consider social ecology and anarchism to be more or less the same thing.

He once summarized his own contribution to anarchism this way:

Social ecology is a fairly integrated and coherent view point that

encompasses a philosophy of natural evolution and of humanity’ s place

in that evolutionary process; a reformulation of dialectics along

ecological lines; an account of the emergence of hierarchy; a historical

examination of the dialectic between legacies and epistemologies of

domination and freedom; an evaluation of technology from an historical ,

ethical, and philosophical standpoint; a wide-ranging critique of

Marxism, the Frankfurt School, justice, rationalism, scientism, and

instrumentalism; and finally an education of a vision of a utopian,

decentralized, confederal, and aesthetically grounded future society

based on an objective ethics of complementarity. ... Whether adequately

or not, this holistic body of ideas endeavors to place “eco-anarchism”

on a theoretical and intellectual par with the best systematic works in

radical social theory. [22]

Face-to-face Democracy

Dating back to the days of his 1930s disillusionment with Stalinism,

Murray had a lifelong fascination with revolutionary institutions — the

various committees, councils, assemblies, soviets, and so on that were

historically created during the revolutionary process. There must be no

more Robespierres, he resolved, no more Stalins, no more Maos. There

must be no more guillotines or gulags. Revolutionaries must learn the

lessons if history. If a new revolution were to succeed in creating a

liberatory, ecological society, and not devolve into just another brutal

power grab, revolutionary institutions would have to be in place that

would control and the selfish desires of some individuals for

domination. The only kind of institutions that could both liberate

people and at the same time keep the power-hungry in check, he believed,

were democratic ones that could hold revolutionary leaders accountable.

Indeed the sine qua non of any revolutionary institution must be its

ability to facilitate democracy. And by “democracy” Murray did not mean

the system practiced by nation-states today, with representatives and

legislatures and parliaments, which he considered to be republicanism, a

form of statism. He meant, rather, face-to-face democracy.

In his musings about the origins of his interest in anarchism, as we

have seen, Murray mentioned, among other things, “my readings into the

Athenian polis” — that is, Athenian democracy. In “Ecology and

Revolutionary Thought” Murray had referred to “the anarchist concept of

... a face-to-face democracy,” calling it a “rich libertarian concept,”

as if democracy had a long lineage in anarchist history and theory.[23]

Face-to-face democracy seemed to him to be not only the ideal

revolutionary institution but the perfect political institution for a

decentralized, differentiated, diverse, eco-anarchist society.

To my knowledge Murray’s first discussion of democracy appeared in the

remarkable essay “Forms of Freedom,” an inquiry into revolutionary

institutions written in the annus mirabilis 1968. “Let us turn to the

popular assembly for an insight into unmediated forms of social

relations,” he urges — that is, unmediated by legislators and

parliamentarians. In ancient Athens, he says, “the trend toward popular

democracy ... achieved a form that has never quite been equaled

elsewhere. By Periclean times the Athenians had perfected their polis to

a point where it represented a triumph of rationality within the

material limitations of the ancient world.” Not that Athenian society

itself was ideal, far from it, marred as it was by slavery, social

classes, and the exclusion of women. But “Athens, despite the slave,

patriarchal and class features it shared with classical society, as a

whole developed into a working democracy in the literal sense of the

term.” As a political institution, he noted, the popular assembly later

“reappeared in the medieval and Renaissance towns of Europe.”[24]

Among the most extraordinary of popular assemblies were the sectional

assemblies of 1793, Murray wrote, which “emerged as the insurgent bodies

in Paris during the Great Revolution.” The sectional assemblies “by

degrees ... turned into neighborhood assemblies of all ‘active’

citizens, varying in form, scope and power form one district to

another.” Here was an ultra-democratic institution right in the heart of

revolutionary Europe: the sections “represented genuine forms of

self-management.” Some might argue that a city like Paris was too large

to handle face-to-face democracy, but “the sections provide us with a

rough model of assembly organization in a large city and during a period

of revolutionary transition from a centralized political state to a

potentially decentralized society.” Just so, the Athenian “ecclesia

provides us with a rough model of assembly organization in a

decentralized society.”[25]

Murray’s intention, then, was to place face-to-face democracy on the

eco-anarchist program.

“Spring Offensives, Summer Vacations”

In 1969 Students for a Democratic Society (SDS), the primary political

organization of the American New Left, collapsed, its leadership having

been taken over by ultraleft guerrilla groups like Weatherman. The

Maoist guerrilla campaigns that had seemed to be the path ahead ended up

destroying the organization. The student movement had always suffered

from the endemic problem of fast turnover — no sooner do students

organize a demonstration than summer vacation begins; no sooner do

students develop political experience than they graduate. In April 1970

National Guards killed four student demonstrators at Kent State in Ohio.

Among the New Left’s rank and file the National Mobilization Committee

to End the War in Vietnam continued to pull together intermittent

demonstrations in Washington. The 1972 presidential campaign of George

McGovern channeled the energy of many antiwar activists. Amid the

once-vibrant American radical movement confusion reigned.

In these years Murray was involved with the East Side Anarchists in New

York as well as a libertarian collective that published the periodical

Anarchos. What the American radical movement needed, he realized, in

order to function as a real social and political alternative, was a set

of institutions that would have at least some permanence. But no such

institutions remained from the detritus of SDS or emerged from the

antiwar demonstrations. Marches were “ephemeral spectacles,” he wrote in

“Spring Offensives and Summer Vacations,” published in Anarchos in June

1972. “After each demonstration, street action, or confrontation, this

hollow cone [of organizational leadership] all but collapsed, only to be

recreated again with varying degrees of success for another

demonstration, street action, or confrontation.”[26]

Something more lasting had to be built: “The hollow cone that we call a

movement must acquire a more solid geometry. It must be filled in by an

authentic popular movement based on the self-activity of the American

people, not the theatrical eruptions of a dedicated minority.” Antiwar

activists, he urged, should build stable institutions — somewhat like

the ones he had written about four years earlier, in “Forms of Freedom”:

Our effort must now be directed throughout the entire year to catalyzing

popular antiwar groups: popular assemblies and local action committees,

if you like, each rooted in a community, campus, school, professional

arena, ... factory, office, and research establishment. A real movement

must be built out of these formations for the immediate purpose of

antiwar activity and perhaps in the long run as popular modes of

self-activity to achieve a society based on self-management. ... each

popular institution is free to make its own local decisions, free to act

or not act as it feels necessary.

Those popular assemblies and local action committees, he wrote, should

themselves form confederations over larger regions:

We propose a qualitatively different level of political activity: the

confederal or, if you like, the “communard” concept of institutional

organization that also found expression in the Paris communes of 1793–94

and 1871. This “communard” approach ... essentially called for a

confederation of the municipalities as opposed to the development of a

centralized state ... For American radicals to raise this approach today

and restore its revolutionary content based on a post-scarcity

technology would mark a decisive, indeed a historical advance in the

development of an authentic left in the United States.

The article was signed by the Anarchos Group but was clearly written by

Murray, containing many of his idiosyncratic phrasings. It has not been

republished (to my knowledge) and so its key parts are worth

transcribing here at some length, especially its list of proposals:

1. The formation of local coalitions of non-party groups — the best of

the urban and rural communes, independent student groups, radical

professional, working class, and women’s groups ... independent antiwar

groups — to act concertedly in choosing and presenting candidates for

city councils in the municipalities of this country. These coalitions,

we believe, must be free and non-hierarchical; they must try to be

rooted in their local communities and act openly with each other in a

consistently democratic manner, eschewing any form of bureaucratic or

manipulatory behavior ...

Anarchos, that is, was calling upon anarchists to elect candidates to

city councils. On what platform? The answer: they could write programs

on many topics but

could also demand a radical restructuring of municipal institutions

along directly democratic lines, involving above all the right by

popular constituencies and assemblies to recall representatives who do

not reflect their will, the replacement of the police by a popular guard

organized on a roster basis from neighborhoods and factories, and open

defiance against the central government’s parasitization of the

municipality’s fiscal and economic resources.

That is, the anarchist programs would call for a democratization of city

government, abolishing city councils and replacing them with popular

assemblies. They would thus use the power of the municipality — the

level of the state closest to the people — to create popular and

potentially antistatist institutions, “unmediated” by representatives.

Thus the next proposal was:

2. The dissolution of the gigantic megalopolitan “city” governments into

local town halls and city councils with direct neighborhood control over

civic life.

And the next:

3. Lastly, a demand for a confederation of the city councils to resist

the encroachment by State governments and by the Federal government on

local and municipal autonomy.

The group issued a caveat against the use of these proposals for statist

purposes:

If the proposals we advance are to be more than mere liberal or Social

Democratic pap, if they are to acquire a truly radical thrust, the

coalitions which advance them must themselves be alliances of authentic

popular groups such as the grass-roots antiwar movement we have

proposed, not cadre organizations ... Should the local coalitions and

municipal confederal movement we propose go beyond a municipal and

confederal level, should it grasp for institutional control or influence

on the State and Federal level, it would become nothing more than

another treacherous Social Democracy — another betrayal of the popular

movement and the principles of freedom and revolution.

The group emphasized the confrontational nature of the approach:

The issue of local control versus the centralized state is being joined

today whether we like it or not. A long-range historical dialectic

toward state capitalism pits the neighborhood against the megalopolis,

the village, town, and small city against the State governments and

Federal government, the municipality against the national state.

Anarchist objections

The essay “Spring Offensives and Summer Vacations” did not go

unchallenged — not even at its very moment of publication. Some members

of the Anarchos collective strongly disagreed with its calls for

participation in municipal electoral campaigns. As these members were in

charge of printing the periodical, they were able enclose an insert in

that June 1972 issue, expressing their objections. Judith Malina (yes,

she of the Living Theater) wrote the dissenting article:

What is voting? Voting is an agreement by all that the will of the most

shall be carried out. When there is unanimous agreement the decision of

the people is self-evident. But when there is no unanimity the vote

becomes the tyranny of the many over the reluctant few. This tyranny is

the expression of a principle inherent in the democratic ethic: a tacit

understanding that the few will not fight the many because the many

would win by virtue of their superior numbers. ... The myth is that

justice consists of a few “bowing down to the ill of the majority”;

whereas, the tyranny of the majority is injustice like any other form of

tyranny.[27]

That is, democracy, even face-to-face democracy, based as it is on the

will of the majority, is inherently tyrannical. Malina offered an

anarchist alternative:

Yes, the people should take over local control at the community level —

but not through the municipal governments which, through party lines,

are always closely bound to state and federal governmental structures.

Instead, the people should take over control by creating community

structures from below. Such structures will not exist parallel to the

governmental municipal structures — but will in fact — wrest the power

from them. ... The criticism here is not of the forms of local

organization that the Anarchos group proposes, but only of the

submission to the jurisdiction of the local constitutional

government.[28]

Murray surely responded in some way to Malina, but to my knowledge no

written record of it survives. He did recall the incident in 1985:

Someone wrote a reply to me stating that anarchists should never

participate in any elections of any kind ... I’m saying that city

government, as you call it, has to be restructured at the grassroots

level. ... what anarchists should be doing is not hesitating to get

involved in local politics to create forms of organization in which they

may run once they’ve established these forms or, alternatively, running

on a platform to establish these forms.[29]

Malina’s objection would recur frequently in the following decades, but

few expressed it as clearly and thoroughly as she did, at the outset.

Murray, in turn, would frequently respond to Malina’s type of argument

about parallel institutions. Alternative community groups that exist

parallel to the municipality have no real power, he argued. Citizens

might be motivated to attend one or two meetings, out of concern over a

specific issue, but they would have no real reason to continue to

participate in them over time, or to maintain their existence for its

own sake. For a group of people to actively work to keep an institution

alive, it must have some form of structural power.

Murray would later conclude that anarchists misunderstand the nature of

power and were therefore unprepared to address it.

Anarchists conceive of power as an essentially malignant evil that must

be destroyed. Proudhon, for example, once stated that he would divide

and subdivide power until it, in effect, ceased to exist ... a notion as

absurd as the idea that gravity can be abolished ... The truly pertinent

issue ... is not whether power will exist but whether it will rest in

the hands of an elite or in the hands of the people ... Social

revolutionaries ... must address the problem of how to give power a

concrete institutional emancipatory form.[30]

Still, Malina’s objection exemplified an important point: anarchism had

not historically been particularly friendly to democracy. George

Woodcock had pointed this out back in 1962:

The extreme concern for the sovereignty of the individual ... explains

the anarchist rejection of democracy as well as autocracy. No conception

of anarchism is farther from the truth than that which regards it as an

extreme form of democracy. Democracy advocates the sovereignty of the

people. Anarchism advocates the sovereignty of the person. This means

that automatically the anarchists deny many of the forms and viewpoints

of democracy.[31]

Murray had read Woodcock’s book, but if he noticed this caveat, he must

have responded with skepticism. After all, anarchism in the past had not

been ecological, either, or concerned with post-scarcity or hierarchy.

Yet he had injected those concepts into anarchism. Why not democracy

too? It must have seemed obvious to him: if he called anarchists’

attention to face-to-face democracy, surely they would agree that it was

the best model of self-management for a decentralized and ecological

society.

Anarchism is after all potentially dynamic:

Anarchism could be the most creative and innovative movement in

radicalism today ... [With] our ideals of self-management,

decentralization, confederalism, and mutual aid ... we have long been

the progenitors of an organic, naturalist, and mutualistic sensibility

that the ecology movement has appropriated with few references to their

source — the naturalism of Kropotkin.[32]

Libertarian municipalism

In the early 1980s Murray developed his ideas about face-to-face

democracy into a specific approach that, for purposes of easy

identification, he gave a name. Libertarian municipalism was his

strategy for achieving democratic revolutionary institutions, as well as

the political infrastructure of a rational ecological society. He had

sketched the rudiments of this approach in “Spring Offensives,” but did

not write much about it after 1972. Then in 1983 he returned to the

subject, developing it in a mature and detailed form. I will summarize

it very briefly here. [33]

We need a “new politics,” Murray argued, one based, not in a national

capital, but at the community level. “Here, in the most immediate

environment of the individual — the community, the neighborhood, the

town, or the village — where private life slowly begins to phase into

public life, the authentic locus for functioning on a base level exists

insofar as urbanization has not totally destroyed it.”[34] Here a “new

politics” of citizenship may be instituted, one in which people take

charge of their own political life, through participation in popular

assemblies. Murray distinguished between politics (which is practiced by

citizens in assemblies) and statecraft (which is practiced by

officeholders in the institutions of the nation-state). He believed that

politics must be “a school for genuine citizenship.

Ultimately there is no civic “curriculum,” as it were, that can be a

substitute for a living and creative political realm. But what we must

clearly do in an era of commodification, rivalry, anomie, and egoism is

formulate and consciously inculcate the values of humanism, cooperation,

community, and public service in the everyday practice of civic life.

... Grass-roots citizenship must go hand in hand with grass-roots

politics.[35]

Libertarian municipalist activists would therefore create groups to run

candidates in municipal elections, on platforms calling for the creation

of face-to-face democracy in popular assemblies. When the citizenry

elected enough such candidates to office, the new city councilors would

fulfill the one purpose for which they had been elected: they would

alter city and town charters to create popular assemblies. Thus the

assemblies would come about as a result of a conscious devolution of

power from existing statist municipal institutions: The assemblies, so

empowered, would take over the functions of municipal governments. They

would municipalize the economy, taking over the ownership and management

of local economic life, allowing the people of community to make

decisions about economic activity in their area.

The township should have control over the land; it should have control

over the industries. Collectivization itself can lead many different

directions .... Municipalization means the municipality controls it

through neighborhood organizations or through town meetings.[36]

Over larger regions the democratized municipalities would interlink by

confederating with one another:

What, then, is confederalism? It is above all a network of

administrative councils whose members or delegates are elected from

popular face-to-face democratic assemblies, ... The members of these

confederal councils are strictly mandated, recallable, and responsible

to the assemblies that chose them for the purpose of coordinating and

administering the policies formed by the assemblies themselves. Their

function is thus a purely administrative and practical one, not a

policy-making one like the function of representatives in republican

systems of government.[37]

The confederated municipalities, in which power flowed from the bottom

up, would form a dual power, a counterpower, against the nation-state.

I’m concerned with developing local institutions — neighborhood

assemblies, neighborhood councils that will be thrown into dynamic

opposition to the centralized state. My most important concern is to

stop the centralization of economic and political power ... to see that

the municipal level acts as a brake upon the centralization of the state

and ultimately leads to the abolition of the centralized state in a free

municipal confederation of town and cities and villages structured in a

libertarian form.[38]

Libertarian municipalism is that it is grounded in historical reality

and local traditions “to legitimate its claims,

traditions which, however fragmentary and tattered, still offer the

potentiality for a participatory politics of challenging dimensions to

the State. The Commune still lies buried in the city council; the

sections still lie buried in the neighborhood; the town meeting still

lies buried in the township; confederal forms of municipal association

still lie buried in regional networks of towns and cities.[39]

This approach also had roots in revolutionary history. Many radical

workers’ movements, Murray wrote,

were largely civic phenomena, grounded in specific neighborhoods in

Paris, Petrograd, and Barcelona, and in small towns and villages that

formed the arenas not only of class unrest but of civic or communal

unrest. In such milieus oppressed and discontented people acted in

response to the problems they faced not only as economic beings but as

communal beings.[40]

Through these democratic institutions a revolutionary people would be

enabled to replace the nation-state and exercise its power through

popular self-government.

Nineteenth-century anarchist communalism

Starting in the early 1980s Murray mounted a veritable campaign to try

to persuade anarchists to adopt libertarian municipalism. He delved into

anarchist history to find support for it there, for organic,

community-level politics, and for confederated municipalities. In fact

the nineteenth-century originators of anarchist thought, he found, had

had a lot to say about such ideas.

Proudhon, for one, had written favorably about federalism (also known as

confederalism or confederation) as a libertarian alternative to the

nation-state. In The Federal Principle (1863), written toward the end of

his life, he advocated a decentralized theory of federal (confederal)

government. Public administration, he argued, should be organized most

basically at the local level, with communes and associations. These

communes would group together regionally, and a confederation of regions

would replace the nation-state. Power would rise from below. Delegates

would be recallable, ensuring the implementation of the popular will.

Proudhon’s was the first exposition of the idea that a confederation

could be an alternative to the nation-state.[41]

“Due honor should certainly be given to Proudhon,” Murray argued, ”for

developing federalistic notions of social organization against the

nation-state and defending the rights of crafts people and peasants who

were under the assault of industrial capitalism.”[42] Indeed,

What I find most worth emphasizing in Proudhon is his highly communal

notion of confederalism. He was at his best, allowing for certain

reservations, when he declared that “the federal system is the contrary

of hierarchy or administrative and governmental centralization”; that

the “essence” of federal contracts is ”always to reserve more powers of

the citizen than for the state, and for municipal and provincial

authorities than for the central power”; that “the central power” must

be ‘imperceptibly subordinated it... to the representatives of

departments or provinces, provincial authority to the delegates of

townships, and municipal authority to its inhabitants.”[43]

Very popular among nineteenth-century libertarians was the idea of what

in French and other European languages was called the commune — the unit

of local government closest to the people; that is, the municipality.

The word “commune” also had overtones of the revolutionary Paris Commune

of 1793–94. “The importance of the commune in traditional anarchist

thought,” wrote Murray, “has not received the full attention it

deserves.”[44] Libertarian thinkers, in the wake of Proudhon, commonly

thought of the confederation to replace the nation-state as constituting

a network of communes. Wrote Murray: “The anarchic ideal of

decentralized, stateless, collectively managed, and directly democratic

communities — of confederated municipalities or ‘communes’ — speaks

almost intuitively ... to the transforming role of libertarian

municipalism into the framework of a liberatory society.”[45]

The commune was also an important idea to Bakunin. In his “Revolutionary

Catechism” of 1865–66 the Russian saw the commune as a revolutionary

institution, close to the people and responsive to their needs, and

functioning in a confederation:

Immediately after government has been overthrown, communes will have to

reorganize themselves along revolutionary lines ... No commune can

defend itself in isolation. So it will be necessary for each of them to

radiate revolution outward, to raise all of its neighboring communes in

revolt to the extent that they will rise up, and to federate with them

for common defense. Between themselves they will of necessity enter into

a federal pact founded simultaneously upon solidarity of all and

autonomy of each. ... The same revolutionary requirements induce the

autonomous provinces to federate into regions, regions into national

federations, nations into international federations.[46]

Later in the same document he wrote:

First: all organizations must proceed by way of federation from the base

to the summit, from the commune to the coordinating association of the

country or nation. Second: there must be at least one autonomous

intermediate body between the commune and the country, the department,

the region, or the province ... The basic unit of all political

organization in each country must be the completely autonomous commune,

constituted by the majority vote of all adults of both sexes ... the

province must be nothing but a free federation of autonomous

communes.[47]

In 1871 the Paris Commune, despite its brief existence, excited many

libertarians. Murray once noted that it “provided Marxism and anarchism

with its earliest models of a liberated society” and “was precisely a

revolutionary municipal movement whose goal of a ‘social republic’ had

been developed within a confederalist framework of free municipalities

or ‘communes.’”[48] It gave the already-interesting concept of the

“commune” even more electricity.

The commune loomed large on the horizon of Peter Kropotkin, the

anarchist theorist closely identified with anarcho-communism.[49] In

1879 Kropotkin wrote:

Once expropriation has been carried through, and the capitalists’ power

to resist been smashed, the ... there will necessarily arise a new

system of organizing production and exchange ... the foundations of the

new organization will be the free federation of producers’ groups and

the free federation of Communes and groups of independent Communes.[50]

And a year later: “The communes of the next revolution will proclaim and

establish their independence by direct socialist revolutionary action,

abolishing private property. When the revolutionary movement happens ...

the people themselves will abolish property by a violent

expropriation.”[51]

The communes of the next revolution will not only break down the state

and substitute free federation for parliamentary rule; they will part

with parliamentary rule within the commune itself. They will trust the

free organization of food supply and production to free groups of

workers — which will federate with like groups in other cities and

villages not through the medium of a communal parliament but directly,

to accomplish their aim.[52]

And Kropotkin wrote in 1913 that “the form that the social revolution

must take [is] the independent commune.”[53]

We notice in these countries the evident tendency to form into groups of

entirely independent communes, towns, and villages, which would combine

by means of free federation, in order to satisfy innumerable needs and

attain certain immediate ends ... The future revolutions in France and

Spain will be communalist — not centralist.[54]

In sum, the commune in confederation (“the Commune of communes”) was

crucial to these major nineteenth-century anarchists as well as others.

Together their writings, said Murray in the 1980s, constituted a

“communalist” tendency within anarchism, a tendency that had been

largely overlooked amid the more conspicuous tendencies of

anarcho-individualism and anarcho syndicalism. He now campaigned to call

attention to it: “It would be well to remember that there has always

been a communalist tendency in anarchism, not only a syndicalist and an

individualist one. Moreover, this communalist tendency has always had a

strong municipalist orientation.”[55] He told Kick It Over in 1985:

Long before syndicalism emerged in the anarchist tradition, there was a

communalist tradition which dates back to Proudhon and which appears in

Kropotkin and I don’t know why that’s been so completely neglected. So

if I’m to take that seriously and update it up into our own time and

explore its logic completely, then I have to ask myself: what can I do

to recover the neighborhood and the community? How can I empower the

citizens to take control of their community at the base grassroots

level, ... and not to develop the bad habits of parliamentarism, but to

try to create neighborhood assemblies such as we have in Burlington —

town meeting type forms — councils in neighborhoods — confederate them,

and confederate the communities into a dual power against the

centralized state on the basis of a libertarian tradition.[56]

To be sure, in Murray’s hands the communalist tendency underwent

transformation. The nineteenth-century theorists had seen the communes

as mainly administrative in function, providing “public services,” and

had given actual decision-making power over to workers’ associations

that comprised the communal federations. The communes themselves would

be kind of mini-confederations at the municipal level, made up of

smaller components like producers’ groups, collectives, cooperatives,

and the like. Murray instead envisioned the commune as a direct

democracy, made up of popular assemblies, that controls the economy.

But then, how would the forebears’ workers’ associations and communes

make decisions? As bodies for policymaking as well as administration,

they would have to make decisions. Perhaps they would comprise councils,

or committees. These councils or committees might consist of councilors

who were delegates — recallable delegates, empowered to carry out the

will of the people. As Bakunin wrote in 1868: ”As regards organization

of the Commune, there will be a federation of standing barricades and a

Revolutionary Communal Council will operate on the basis of one or two

delegates from each barricade, one per street or per district, these

deputies being invested with binding mandates and accountable and

revocable at all times.”[57]

But how would the deputies be chosen? Bakunin does not say; nor does

Kropotkin or any of the other forebears. Perhaps the deputies would be

hand-picked by revolutionary leaders, but that does not seem

particularly enlightened. Or perhaps the delegates would be elected

democratically. By the people. Perhaps by the people in assemblies. The

forebears do not say.

The fact is that, if I may generalize wildly, the European Left of the

nineteenth century tended not to think of democracy as a desideratum in

its own right. Even democratic grassroots self-government held little

appeal. Democracy, as a concept, seemed the politics of compromise,

requiring tolerance and moderation, unsuited for violent revolutionary

goals of expropriation. Statist democracy (what Murray would call

republicanism) was a means for the acquisition power by the working

class rather than a goal in its own right. For European leftists the

revolutionary institutions par excellence were factory committees and

workers’ councils, institutions whose origins lay in economic thought.

Perhaps it required an American radical to insist that democracy was

exciting in its own right, to give it priority, to make it a goal worth

fighting for.

And it became his job to try to persuade anarchists that democracy was

worth fighting for, to be valued in its own right. Libertarian

municipalism, he believed, as a translation and update of

anarchist-communalism, could become the basis for a new anarchism

dedicated to face-to-face democracy.

“The revolutionary era is over”

Before I go on, I would like to look at another notable fact about the

“commune” formations described by the nineteenth-century forebears:

these communes were intended to come into existence after the workers’

revolution. That is, once the workers had expropriated private property

and forced the collapse of the state, they would spontaneously form

communes. Note that one of the Bakunin quotes above begins “Immediately

after government has been overthrown ... ” And that one of the Kropotkin

quotes begins “Once expropriation has been carried through ...” For both

thinkers, the workers’ revolution would come first.

As we have seen, Murray had argued that revolutionary institutions are

formed spontaneously by the people during the course of a revolution.

(Spontaneity was one of his principles of convergence between anarchism

and ecology.) But in the early 1980s something happened that permanently

changed his thinking: he came to the realization that he was not going

to see a revolution would happen in his lifetime. The way he put it to

me was: he realized that the revolutionary era is over.

He had been working with the Clamshell Alliance, the group that

prevented the Seabrook nuclear reactor from going on line. Was it

something about that experience that led to this realization? He was

frustrated by the decision-making processes used in that group:

consensus, he found, was a process very prone to manipulation. Or was it

the changes happening in North America and Europe in the 1970s?

Certainly the United States was entering a period of right-wing backlash

against the 1960s (a backlash that continues to this day). Onetime

radicals were now pursuing careers, getting “a piece of the pie” for

themselves. The new social movements were emerging, which offered hope

but also fragmentation of any broad movement; they moved radical

thinking increasingly toward identity politics. Ecology was emerging as

an issue of general concern, but as Washington adopted a few

environment-friendly laws, radical ecologists were becoming reformist

environmentalists. Finally the alternative (non-Western and noncredal)

spiritualities that made up the New Age were ever more popular, luring

former political activists into private life and promising to replace

extroverted demands to change society with inner quests for serenity and

enlightenment.

The revolutionary era, Murray realized in the early 1980s, was over. The

era of proletarian revolutions had begun on the barricades of June 1848

and had continued through the Paris Commune, the Russian Revolution, and

beyond. But it had come to an end in May 1937, on the barricades of

Barcelona. That was the last time workers had risen up in pursuit of a

new, utopian society.[58] He said in a 1985 speech: “I believe that the

revolutionary era in the classical sense is over. ... I lived through

the era of the barricades. The glamour of them has always enchanted me,

but I’ve learned when an epic has come to an end.”[59] He later told me

that he came to that realization after Clamshell. “Hardly any authentic

revolutionary opposition exists in North American and Europe,” he wrote

in 1979.[60]

This realization must have been wrenching, as much so as his 1948

realization that the workers would not be revolutionary agents. After

all, capitalism and the nation-state still had to be overthrown, even

more urgently now with the ecological crisis, and Murray himself, as

well as other revolutionaries, had no intention of giving up their

fight. He could have settled back and adjusted his views to the tenor of

the times, but it was not in his personality to do so — he had always

been a revolutionary, and would remain one. But now that revolution was

no longer on the horizon, how was he to continue? How should any

revolutionaries function, given that history was no longer on their

side?

His thinking shifted, and one hallmark of the shift, in my view, was his

virtual abandonment of the concept of spontaneity. Revolutionaries had

to stop supposing that revolutionary institutions would be formed after

the revolution, or even during the course of an uprising. Instead,

revolutionaries had to start creating revolutionary institutions now.

That way the institutions would not simply be a product of revolution;

they could help foment a revolution. Revolutionaries had to create these

institutions consciously and deliberately. Certainly events might erupt

that would fuel social change; a growing awareness of the ecological

crisis could lead to a broad social movement; global warming, wreaking

havoc, could threaten survival and lead to a major social and political

upheaval. But for now, in the absence of such broad popular unrest,

revolution had to be worked for consciously. And to perform that

conscious work, an organized, coherent, and purposive libertarian

movement was needed.

The strategy of that movement, of course, was libertarian municipalism.

The institutions of face-to-face democracy were the ones that could be

created before the revolution and that would be in place if and when the

revolution finally came. After all, in the wake of the collapse of the

Soviet Union in 1991, the rest of the world seemed to be embracing

democracy, in the form of the republican nation-state. Municipalist

revolutionaries could do no less, but in their case the democracy they

embraced would be direct and face-to-face.

The anarchist response

As we have seen, Murray mounted a campaign to convince his fellow

anarchists that this was the path they should take. He passionately

advocated libertarian municipalism at a major international anarchist

conference held in Venice in 1984. He wrote The Rise of Urbanization and

the Decline of Citizenship (a cumbersome and academic-sounding title for

a brilliant book shot through with political engagement), published in

1985, tracing the democratic tradition and exploring the age-old

conflict between the municipality and the state. From 1983 to the early

1990s he produced a series of articles on various aspects of libertarian

municipalism, many of them published in Green Perspectives (later

renamed Left Green Perspectives). He formed a libertarian municipalist

political group in Burlington, Vermont. (By this time I was in his life

and became a member of that group, the Burlington Greens; I coedited

Green Perspectives with him.)

How did anarchists respond to this campaign? For the most part, the

response I heard, both in my presence and in writings that crossed our

desks, it was univocal: anarchists will never participate in elections.

Municipalism is statism, it is parliamentarism, they said, just as

Judith Malina had in 1972.

But at the local level, Murray replied, politics is not statism; it is

something qualitatively different. The state, in his definition, was the

institution that involves a surrender of sovereignty to legislators;

politics, by contrast, takes place at the community level, where

communal self-management is possible; it involves people actively

managing their own communities, not surrendering power to legislators

but exercising it themselves. That fact made all the difference. “Civic

politics is not intrinsically parliamentary politics,” he wrote in

1984.[61] And: “If this kind of assembly brings anarchists into city

councils, there is no reason why such a politics should be construed as

parliamentary, particularly if it is confined to the civic level and is

consciously posed against the state.”[62]

He frequently quoted Bakunin on the qualitative difference between local

politics and the national state. In 1870 Bakunin had drawn an implicit

distinction between them:

Due to their economic hardships the people are ignorant and indifferent

and are aware only of things closely affecting them. They understand and

know how to conduct their daily affairs. Away from their familiar

concerns they become confused, uncertain, and politically baffled. They

[the people] have a healthy practical common sense when it comes to

communal affairs. They are fairly well informed and know how to select

from their midst the most capable officials. Under such circumstances,

effective control is quite possible, because the public business is

conducted under the watchful eyes of the citizens and vitally and

directly concerns their daily lives. This is why municipal elections

always best reflect the real attitude and will of the people. Provincial

and county governments, even when the latter are directly elected, are

already less representative of the people.[63]

“I would want to restate his formulation to mean that municipal

elections can more accurately reflect the popular will than

parliamentary ones,” Murray wrote.[64]

Moreover, the municipality and the state have long been in tension if

not conflict.

The state, until comparatively recent times, has never been able to

fully claim the municipality as its own ... Almost every major

revolution has involved — indeed, has often been — a conflict between

the local community and the centralized state ... The municipality may

well be the one arena in which traditional institutional forms can be

reworked to replace the nation-state itself ... The municipality’s

capacity to play a historic role in changing society depends on the

extent to which it can shake off the state institutions that have

infiltrated it: its mayoralty structure, civic bureaucracy, and its own

professionalized monopoly on violence. Rescued from these institutions,

however, it retains the historical materials and political culture that

can pit it against the nation-state and the cancerous corporate

world.[65]

But still the objections continued. In 1996 the periodical Organise!

suggested that Murray was advocating a process wherein “’libertarians’

capture the local state and end up captured by it.”[66] His response:

My views on libertarian municipalism are entirely oriented toward

creating a dual power composed of directly democratic assemblies of the

people in revolutionary opposition to the state. The idea that

libertarian municipalism should try to capture the local state and

operate within a statist framework is alien to my views. My hope is that

a movement can be created that seeks to enlarge whatever local democracy

still remains in a community — particularly a direct face-to-face

democracy — in the hope that it can be thrown against the state on all

levels, from the municipality to the central government.[67]

But already in 1992 he was becoming discouraged. “The extreme resistance

I have encountered from anarchist traditionalists and ‘purists’ on this

issue has virtually foreclosed any possibility of developing a

libertarian, participatory, municipalist, and confederal politics today

as part of the anarchist tradition.”[68]

Most discouragingly, many anarchists objected to the basic principle of

democratic decision-making, majority rule. “Majority rule is still

rule,” he was told. As he described the difficulty:

Libertarians commonly consider democracy, even in this [face-to-face]

sense, as a form of “rule” — since in making decisions, a majority view

prevails and thus “rules” over a minority. As such, democracy is said to

be inconsistent with a truly libertarian ideal. Even so knowledgeable a

historian of anarchism as Peter Marshall observes that, for anarchists,

“the majority has no more right to dictate to the minority, even a

minority of one, than the minority to the majority.”[69]

Such thinking dates back to Kropotkin, who asserted that “majority rule

is as defective as any other kind of rule.”[70]

As an alternative to majority rule, some anarchists argued that

consensus was preferable; by seeking unanimous or near-unanimous

consent, it seemed to eliminate the problem of overruled minorities.

But Murray did not agree. Consensus decision-making, he thought, was

suitable for small groups of people who know each other but was entirely

impracticable for large assemblies of strangers. Moreover, it tended to

turn citizens into manipulators, working behind the scenes to get full

support for their proposal, rather than openly articulating valid

disagreements. And by insisting on unanimous or near-unanimous support

for a decision, consensus tended to suppress dissent, subtly coercing

those who disagreed with the majority to “step aside” — that is, to

negate themselves as citizens and participants. As a fourteen-year-old

member of the Young Communist League, Murray had defied the Stalinists’

ban on talking — even talking! — to Trotskyists. He had never been one

to agree to the suppression of dissent — on the contrary, he would

always champion dissent, not simply for allowing it but for encouraging

it, because “dissensus” brought creativity. A democracy did indeed

insist that the outvoted minority had to abide by the decisions of the

majority, but it always left open the possibility that a dissenting

minority could express its views freely and thereby hope one day to

reverse the noxious decision.[71]

Yes, anarchists are rightly concerned about statism, Murray said, and

their “concern over parliamentarism and statism” has been “amply

justified by history.” But “it can also lead to a siege mentality that

is no less dogmatic in theory than an electoral radicalism is corrupt in

practice.”[72] Murray felt passionately that anarchists should not let

their justified opposition to parliamentarism lead them to oppose

elections and face-to-face democracy.

Today, so great is the fear of a localist politics of any sort — of

crossing the mystical line between nonvoting and voting — that the

rejection of electoral activity, even if base don the locality in which

one lives, has become a paralyzing dogma.[73]

Anarchism, Murray insisted over and over again, has to be able to move

forward; it shouldn’t allow itself to be ossified.

We can certainly build on views advanced by the great anarchist thinkers

of the past. But must we ignore the need for more sophisticated notions

of confederalism, anti-statism, decentralism, definitions of freedom, a

sensitivity to the natural world than those that they advance? ... If

anarchist theory and practice cannot keep pace with — let alone go

beyond — historic changes that have altered the entire social, cultural,

and moral landscape ... the entire movement will indeed become what

Adorno called it — a “ghost.”[74]

“You know,” he said to me and to others several times in these years,

“the Spanish anarchists back in the 1890s wanted to drop the name

‘anarchist’ in favor of ‘libertarian communism.’ Maybe I’ll do the same

thing.”

Individualism and lifestyle anarchism

As it turned out, anarchism was indeed changing with the times — but not

in the way that Murray had been urging. On the contrary, during all

those years when he had been trying to revive anarcho-communalism, much

of anarchist thinking had actually been going in the opposite direction,

toward individualism. Murray became alarmed by this tendency in the

early 1990s. Anarchism, he warned, was moving away from a “collectivist

commitment to socialist freedom” and toward “a personalistic commitment

to individual autonomy.” These tendencies had once “simply coexisted

within anarchism as a minimalist credo of opposition to the State.” But

during the 1980s and 1990s,

as the entire social and political spectrum has shifted ideologically to

the right, “anarchism” itself has not been immune to redefinition. In

the Anglo-American sphere, anarchism is being divested of its social

ideal by an emphasis on personal autonomy, an emphasis that is draining

it of its historic vitality. A Stirnerite individualism ... has become

increasingly prominent. This personalistic “lifestyle anarchism” is

steadily eroding the socialistic core of anarchist concepts of

freedom.[75]

Such individualism lay at the root of a complex that Bookchin called

“lifestyle anarchism,” which he criticized in the essay “Social

Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism: An Unbridgeable Chasm.”[76] As Murray

described lifestyle anarchism:

Invertebrate protests, directionless escapades, self-assertions, and a

very personal “recolonization” of everyday life parallel the

psychotherapeutic, New Age, self-oriented lifestyles of bored baby

boomers and members of Generation X. Today what passes for anarchism in

America and increasingly in Europe is little more than an introspective

personalism that denigrates responsible social commitment; an encounter

group variously renamed a collective or an affinity group; a state of

mind that arrogantly derides structure, organization, and public

involvement; and a playground for juvenile antics.[77]

Personalistic or lifestyle anarchism was preoccupied with the ego,

Murray thought, typified by a narcissistic inwardness and seeking

self-enchantment. Its very forms of rebellion were petulant and

egoistic, episodes of “ad hoc adventurism” marked by personal bravura.

Lifestyle anarchists were stridently antipolitical and

anti-organizational.

Perhaps most grievously, lifestyle anarchism rejected the core values of

the Enlightenment, to which Murray had always been committed and that he

had always presupposed, never imagining that they would one day be

challenged. Attracted to mysticism, desire, ecstasy, imagination,

paganism, and the New Age, lifestyle anarchism was hostile to reason as

such and harbored an aversion to theory, even celebrating theoretical

incoherence; and when it was not engaged in bravura, it receded into

Taoist quietism and Buddhist self-effacement. It condemned modern

technology as well as science, even though Kropotkin, for one,

significantly emphasized “the progress of modern technics, which

wonderfully simplifies the production of all the necessaries of

life.”[78]

Lifestyle anarchism furthermore was anti-civilizational, offering “a

glorification of prehistory and the desire to somehow return to its

putative innocence,” Lifestyle anarchists “draw their inspiration from

aboriginal peoples and myths of an edenic prehistory.” They believe that

“life before domestication/agriculture was in fact largely one of a

leisure, intimacy with nature, sensual wisdom, sexual equality, and

health.” Primitive peoples “refused technology” because “with their

animistic beliefs [they] were saturated by a ‘love’ of animal life and

wilderness.’” People in prehistory consciously decided to refuse not

only tools but even language. Theirs was “a dancing society, a singing

society, a celebrating society, a dreaming society.” Lifestyle

anarchists seemed to imagine that complex societies could one day return

to the simple forms of social organization of tribal or even band

societies.

Lifestyle anarchists categorically rejected libertarian municipalism and

anything resembling democracy

By denying institutions and democracy, lifestyle anarchism insulates

itself from social reality, so that it can fume all the more with futile

rage, thereby remaining a subcultural caper for gullible youth and bored

consumers of black garments and ecstasy posters. To argue that democracy

and anarchism are incompatible because any impediment to the swishes of

even a minority of one constitutes a violation of personal autonomy is

to advocate not a free society but a herd. No longer would “imagination”

come to power. Power, which always exists, will belong either to the

collective in a face-to-face and clearly institutionalized democracy, or

to the egos of a few oligarchs who will produce a “tyranny of

structurelessness.[79]

And above all they rejected socialism. Kropotkin had once said that

anarchism was the left wing of socialism. “The rise of modern

secularism, scientific knowledge, universalism, reason and

technologies,” wrote Murray, “potentially offer the hope of a rational

and emancipatory dispensation of social affairs.” But “in a very real

sense [lifestyle anarchists] are no longer socialists — the advocates of

a communally oriented libertarian society-and they eschew any serious

commitment to an organized, programmatically coherent social

confrontation with the existing order.”[80]

Nor did they seem to grasp, Murray wrote, that true individuality (as

opposed to individualism) depends on a social context. “Left to his or

her own self, the individual loses the indispensable social moorings

that make for what an anarchist might be expected to prize in

individuality: reflective powers, which derive in great part from

discourse; the emotional equipment that nourishes rage against

unfreedom; the sociality that motivates the desire for radical change;

and the sense of responsibility that engenders social action.”[81]

Against this cultural tide, Murray warned, anarchism must retain its

social and political core.

There must be a place on the political spectrum where a body of

anti-authoritarian thought that advances humanity’s bitter struggle to

arrive at the realization of its authentic social life — the famous

“Commune of communes” — can be clearly articulated institutionally as

well as ideologically. There must be a means by which socially concerned

anti-authoritarians can develop a program and a practice for attempting

to change the world, not merely their psyches. There must be an arena of

struggle that can mobilize people, help them to educate themselves and

develop an anti-authoritarian politics ... that pits a new public sphere

against the state and capitalism. In short, we must recover not only the

socialist dimension of anarchism but its political dimension, democracy.

’”[82]

For the name of this “place on the political spectrum,” Murray used his

old word “communalism,” now explicitly defining it as “the democratic

dimension of anarchism”: “ I wish to propose that the democratic and

potentially practicable dimension of the libertarian goal be expressed

as Communalism, a term that has not been historically sullied by

abuse.”[83]

Lifestyle anarchists respond

Lifestyle anarchists responded to “Social Anarchism or Lifestyle

Anarchism,” often in ad hominem ways. Kingsley Widmer, for one, accused

Murray of engaging in an “inquisitional burning which allows only one

tradition and style of anarchism” — an absurd accusation, given even the

title of Murray’s essay. Another tactic was to diagnose Murray as

suffering from a mental disturbance: Jason McQuinn asserted that the

article revealed his “paranoid side”: “Murray “aims to pin the blame for

his lifetime of frustration [in contesting the powers-that-be] , . . on

an evil anti-socialist conspiracy which has subverted his drams at every

turn.” Far from seeing a conspiracy, Murray clearly identified lifestyle

anarchism as a symptom of a larger social malaise, of social reaction

and capitalist commodification. Others diagnosed Bookchin as power

hungry, or as intent on making a power play. Laure Akai, a reviewer for

Anarchy, asserted that Murray was “fighting for his seat as leading

theoretician.” She nonsensically dismissed him (along with Hakim Bey) as

“old men hungry for affection who want to leave their mark on radical

theory before they croak.” Bob Black also portrayed Murray as wealthy

and privileged, motivated by a lust for power.[84]

The most popular tactic was to caricature Murray as an authoritarian —

especially of the Marxist or Stalinist variety. Murray’s defense of the

libertarian social-revolutionary left was distorted into a devious,

indirect defense of the authoritarian, Stalinist left. David Watson,

untroubled by the fact that Murray had broken with Marxism in the 1950s,

designated him as both “General Secretary” and “Chairman,” suffering

from megalomania to boot. Steve Ash wrote that Murray “retains a kind of

Marxoid determinism that undermines his claim to be a libertarian.” John

Clark accused Bookchin of a pernicious “Bakuninist (or

anarcho-Leninism).” Taking issue with none of Murray’s arguments, he

went on to write a “Confession to Comrade Murray Bookchin,” casting

Bookchin metaphorically as Stalin, staging a Moscow show trial — and

self-servingly casting himself (Clark) as a Bukharin — type victim.

On the issues of substance, David Watson wrote an entire book, Beyond

Bookchin, in which he militantly defended primitivism and mysticism.

[85] People, he wrote, should “humble themselves ... before the smallest

ant, realizing their own nothingness.” Murray wrote a long article

entitled “Whither Anarchism?” in which he defended himself against

Watson’s, Clark’s, and other criticisms.[86] Astonishingly, scarcely a

year after the publication of Beyond Bookchin, in the pages of Fifth

Estate, Watson proceeded to reverse himself and rejected “pretenses to

an anarcho-primitive perspective or movement,” calling primitivism “a

fool’s paradise” and “self-proclaimed primitivists” as “deluded.”[87]

Murray couldn’t have said it better.

Conclusions about capitalism

In the wake of the lifestyle anarchism fight, Murray was exhausted. In

1996 he was seventy-five years old. The intractable and unwavering

anarchist rejection of libertarian municipalism demoralized him, and the

attacks by the lifestyle anarchists were personally discouraging. No one

seemed to stand up for him, to take his part. He felt alone and

misunderstood, a man out of his time, even a relic from another era.

The whole experience, he believed, said a great deal about the world he

was living in. The primitivists “are telling us to look inside ourselves

and discover our own ‘real’ selves,” he noted. Apparently we are “to

shed the psychic layers that civilization has imposed on us for

thousands of years — civilization being responsible for our problems —

and peel away our various civilized attributes, much like an onion,

until we get to the innermost core.” But “if we do so, we are likely to

find very little in the core, if anything, but our barest physical

attributes, instincts, and emotions.”

The fact is that “human beings are social beings.” As such we ”have no

natural inner self that exists apart from ... the civilization in which

we live, whether we accept its values and lifeways or are in revolt

against them. This is true for even the most militant individualist.

What we do have is the ability to develop intellectually, to absorb

knowledge, to become emotionally, mature, and above all to innovate and

create. For that we require the presence of other people.”

Oriented as he was toward the future, he looked fondly back to some

aspects of precapitalist society, especially insofar as people were

“tied to one another by their feelings, communities, and a generous

capacity for empathy.” Under capitalism, by contrast, “commodification

severs all the ties created by feeling and community, decomposing them

... capitalism turns the organic into the inorganic, so to speak ... It

fetishizes commodities as substitutes for genuine social ties.

Thus people come to relate to one another through things. If we’re

unhappy, we are advised to buy a new outfit or household device, and

then we’ll feel better. The family mutates into a unit of consumption.

Acquiring an education is reduced to training for earning an income;

gaining one’s livelihood often involves the exploitation of other people

and plundering the natural world. Friendships are reduced to

relationships designed to advance one’s career. Commodification, in

short, replaces genuine social ties to such an extent that things seem

to preside over human relationships, as Marx observed, instead of human

beings administering the disposition of things.

People today have become interested in mysticism and religion out of

emptiness and despair. “In the Western industrialized countries, the

mystical revival is primarily a substitute for the creation of a

politics that would otherwise genuinely empower people. Thus, rather

than entering into a political sphere, trying to change the society

around them, to destroy the disease — capitalism — and replace it with a

new social order, people today are more likely to turn inward, in their

despair, and to belief in a god.” But even the god becomes commodified.

“Capitalism commercializes emotions by placing a dollar sign on

everything people believe or feel.” It not only creates desperation but

then “tries to profit from the aspirations that surge within and yearn

for meaning and significance.”

Murray believed that “today capitalism and commodification are

trivializing people to a remarkable extent,” and that “the egoism, the

narcissism, and the psychotherapeutic mentality that are all so typical

of our society today” are symptoms of that trivialization. “One of our

most important first tasks, as revolutionaries, is to de-trivialize

ourselves and others, ... to recover the great revolutionary traditions

that once existed when people devoted their lives to creating a better

society.”[88]

The chasm widens

As the debate wore on, the “unbridgeable chasm” between social and

lifestyle anarchism became ever more evidently unbridgeable. Murray had

treated lifestyle anarchism and social anarchism as two strains of the

same movement, in the hopes of bolstering the social strain, but many of

his critics seemed intent on consigning social anarchism to the

unrecoverable past. The great divide, according to anarchist Kingsley

Widmer, was not simply the one between social and lifestyle anarchism

but the one between anarchism past and anarchism present. Murray, in

this view, was an anachronism, standing “in lonely splendor ... on the

ghostly shoulders of Bakunin, Kropotkin, and their descendants in such

as the Spanish anarchists of more than two generations ago.” Social

anarchism, Widmer wrote, is historically over: “What Bookchin propounds

overall seems a sometimes admirable but now narrow and thin

libertarianism of a different time and place and conditions. To put it

kindly, much of Bookchinism steams with quaintness.”[89]

Such critics seemed intent on defining social anarchism as

anarchism-of-the-past, and lifestyle anarchism as anarchism-of-today.

Steve Ash, writing in Freedom, went even further, asserting that

individualistic anarchism was anarchism-of-always: “Anarchism as a whole

... has always emphasized self determinism” — that is, autonomy. If

Murray thought anarchism ever had some collectivist or communal

dimension, he was apparently mistaken; indeed, Ash asserted, Bookchin

had joined the “anarchist movement mistaking it for a radical form of

anti-hierarchical communism.” To which Murray replied: “Can it be that

Mr. Ash has never heard of comunismo libertario or the tens of thousands

of Spanish anarchists who raised the cry for it in the streets of

Zaragoza, Barcelona, and Alcoy, among other Spanish cities and towns, as

well as on the battlefronts of Aragon? If it is a mistake to believe

that ‘anti-hierarchical communism’ belongs to ‘genuine [!] anarchist

idea,’ then we have chosen to ignore a major chapter of anarchist

history.” Ash’s critique not only consigned social anarchism to the past

but lost all historical memory of it.

Those of us who knew Murray personally understood that he had privately

rejected anarchism as such in 1995, around the time he wrote “Social

Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism.” In that booklet he essentially was

saying, If anarchism continues in this vein, I’ll have to leave the

movement. But in reality he had already left, emotionally and

intellectually. Still, for four years he hesitated to make a public

break. He had forty years of history with the movement and many

anarchist friends. He had anarchist publishers and a major reputation.

Was he going to jettison that? But Murray, to his credit, never made the

intellectual mistake of caring about reputation. He cared only about

doing what he thought was right.

Why, then, did he procrastinate with the break? In my view, an important

reason was his age. He had just been through a vicious fight with the

lifestyle anarchists. He might now write an article called “Communalism

vs. Anarchism,” but if he did so he would open up another fight. At

seventy-five, he felt himself to be too fragile, and his health too

poor, to withstand the counterattack. He knew that he would need my help

to write the replies, but I was already hard at work editing and

research-assisting the final two volumes of The Third Revolution.

Another reason was the libertarian municipalism conference series of

1997–99. In 1997 I wrote a small book summarizing his political ideas,

called The Politics of Social Ecology: Libertarian Municipalism, which

was almost immediately translated into several languages. Some of his

friends wanted to use the book to try to interest whatever social

anarchists remained in face-to-face democracy. The publisher proposed

that we organize a series of two international conferences, to pitch

democracy to anarchists one last time. Since Murray was too crippled by

arthritis to travel, I agreed to participate in his stead. He was

impatient with the whole project but, perhaps out of deference to me,

kept his misgivings to himself. The first conference took place in 1998

in Lisbon, Portugal; the second, in 1999, in Plainfield, Vermont. As

Murray had predicted, the conference series failed to produce a movement

or even a set of initiatives. On the contrary, the anarchists that the

conferences reached continued to make the same objections: Democracy is

rule. Libertarian municipalism is statism.

By then his friends understood as well as Murray did that no progress

could be made. He had given it his best shot. “I’m tired of defending

anarchism against the anarchists,” he used to say. Writing to the

English periodical Organise! he admitted that his attempt to transform

anarchism had been a failure:

I do not fault myself for trying to expand the horizon of anarchism in

the sixties along cultural lines. I regret only that I failed, not that

I saw the wrong possibilities for profoundly changing our society.

Tragically, many self-professed American anarchists didn’t even try to

do much back then and have since abandoned their convictions for private

life and academic careers. Surely failure doesn’t mean that one

shouldn’t try?[90]

Over the decades Murray had indeed transformed anarchism — much to its

benefit, he had infused it with ecology and the critique of hierarchy

and other ideas.[91] But George Woodcock turned out to be right —

anarchists had no taste for democracy. At least Murray had the

satisfaction of knowing he had tried. In the end, his loyalty to

democracy as a concept and a praxis was stronger than his loyalty to

anarchism. So when he had to choose between them, he chose democracy.

In the meantime a group of talented Scandinavian communalists had come

into his life. They met with us in 1996–97 and, upon returning home,

proceeded to create a solid organization, Democratic Alternative. They

formed study groups. They held meetings and public forums. They wrote

platforms and programs. They held internal congresses and external

conferences. They translated Murray’s and my works into Norwegian and

published them. They wrote their own articles. They edited and published

periodicals. They de-trivialized themselves. They were astonishing.

In Norwegian, as in other European languages, the word municipalism is

translated as an equivalent of “communalism.” Our Norwegian comrades

therefore easily called themselves “communalists.” In 1994 Murray had

referred to communalism as “the democratic dimension of anarchism”; his

next, inevitable step was to separate communalism from anarchism. The

Norwegians gave him the political and psychological support he needed in

order to make the break with the ideology that had been his home for

forty years.

At the second conference of the libertarian municipalism series, in

Vermont in 1999, Murray broke with anarchism. Then three years later, he

wrote it down in his final theoretical article, the brilliant summation

of his late-life views that he called “The Communalist Project.”[92]

In the late 1950s, when anarchism in the United States was a barely

discernible presence, it seemed like a sufficiently clear field in which

I could develop social ecology, as well as the ... political ideas that

would eventually become ... libertarian municipalism. I well knew that

these views were not consistent with traditional anarchist ideas ...

Today I find that anarchism remains the very simplistic individualistic

and antirationalist society it has always been. My attempt to retain

anarchism under the name of “social anarchism” has largely been a

failure, and I now find that the term I have used to denote my views

must be replaced with Communalism, which coherently integrate and goes

beyond the most viable features of the anarchist and Marxist traditions.

The article is notable for its sobriety — although critical of

anarchism, it does not polemicize against it but rather calmly

explicates a transformation:

I myself once used this political label [anarchism], but further thought

has obliged me to conclude that, its often-refreshing aphorisms and

insights notwithstanding, it simply is not a social theory ...

Regrettably, the use of socialistic terms has often prevented anarchists

from telling us or even understanding clearly what they are:

individualists whose concepts of autonomy originate in a strong

commitment to personal liberty rather than to social freedom, or

socialists committed to a structured, institutionalized, and responsible

form of social organization ... The history of his ideology is peppered

with idiosyncratic acts of defiance that verge on the eccentric, which

not surprisingly have attracted many young people and aesthetes. In

fact, anarchism represents the most extreme formulation of liberalism’s

ideology of unfettered autonomy, culminating in a celebration of heroic

acts of defiance of the state.

He did not lash out at anarchism, his former ideological home.

Several years ago, while I still identified myself as an anarchist, I

attempted to formulate a distinction between “social” and “lifestyle”

anarchism, and I wrote an article that identified Communalism as “the

democratic dimension of anarchism.” ... I no longer believe that

Communalism is a mere ”dimension” of anarchism, democratic or otherwise;

rather, it is a distinct ideology with a revolutionary tradition that

has yet to be explored.

As for the communalism that he now affirmed, Murray saw it as a

transcendence of both anarchism and Marxism, and he attributed to it all

the political and philosophical and social ideas that he had been

advocating for decades.

It is my contention that Communalism is the overarching political

category most suitable to encompass the fully thought out and systematic

views of social ecology, including libertarian municipalism and

dialectical naturalism. As an ideology, Communalism draws on the best of

the older Left ideologies — Marxism and anarchism, more properly the

libertarian socialist tradition — while offering a wider and more

relevant scope for our time.

My own view is that Murray had no alternative but to do what he did.

Anarchists had repeatedly and consistently rejected his approach. “The

Communalist Project” is a fitting capstone to a life of immense

intellectual integrity. Here he hoped that, having blazed a new trail,

he would give libertarian social revolutionaries a new path forward. The

task of further developing communalism and working to build a

communalist movement therefore now falls to the next generation of

social ecologists.

September 28, 2007

This article will appear in Anarchism for the 21^(st) Century, ed. Larry

Gambone and Pat Murtagh (Edinburgh and Oakland: A.K. Press,

forthcoming).

 

[1] Times Online, August 10, 2006.

[2] Bookchin, The Problem of Chemicals in Food. This article, like many

others cited in these notes, may be found online at the Anarchy Archive,

dwardmac.pitzer.edu

.

[3] Bookchin, “Deep Ecology, Anarchosyndicalism, and the Future of

Anarchist Thought,” in Bookchin, Graham Purchase, Brian Morris, and

Rodney Aitchtey, contributors, Deep Ecology and Anarchism (London:

Freedom Press, 1993), p. 54.

[4] Emphasis added. Bookchin, Anarchism, Marxism, and the Future of the

Left: Interviews and Essays, 1993–1998 (Edinburgh and San Francisco:

A.K. Press, 1999), p. 57.

[5] Frederick Engels, Herr Eugen Dühring’s Revolution in Science

(Anti-Dühring) (New York: International Publishers, 1939), p. 323,

quoted in Bookchin, “Listen, Marxist!” in Post-Scarcity Anarchism

(Berkeley, Calif.: Ramparts Press, 1971), p. 209.

[6] Friedrich Engels, The Housing Question (Moscow: Progressive

Publishers, 1970), p. 49. Murray quotes this passage in The Limits of

the City (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1986), p. 138n.

[7] Bookchin, “Listen, Marxist!” p. 209. In this essay Murray thought of

decentralism as a common goal of both anarchism and Marxism: “Both

Marxism and anarchism have always agreed that a liberated, communist

society entails sweeping decentralization, the dissolution of

bureaucracy, the abolition of the state, and the breakup of the large

cities”(p. 209).

[8] Bookchin, Our Synthetic Environment (1962; reprinted by New York:

Harper, & Row, 1974), pp. 242–43.

[9] Bookchin, “Deep Ecology, Anarchosyndicalism,” pp. 53–54.

[10] Bookchin, Anarchism, Marxism, p. 57.

[11] Bookchin, “Ecology and Revolutionary Thought,” in Post Scarcity

Anarchism, p. 79.

[12] Ibid., pp. 77, 78.

[13] Ibid., pp. 78, 80, 76.

[14] Ibid., p. 76.

[15] George Woodcock, Anarchism: A history of Libertarian Ideas and

Movements. (Cleveland: World, 1962), p. 468.

[16] Victor Ferkiss, The Future of Technological Civilization (New York:

George Braziller, 1974), p. 75. Murray wrote in 1999, “I regard

Kropotkin as the real pioneer in the eco-anarchist tradition, as well as

anarchist communism.” Anarchism, Marxism, p. 58. In 2002 he rejected

eco-anarchism as primitivistic. See Bookchin, “The Communalist Project,”

in Communalism: Journal for a Rational Society (2002), originally

published online at www.communalism.net; republished in Bookchin, Social

Ecology and Communalism (Oakland and Edinburgh: A.K. Press, 2007).

[17] Bookchin, introduction to Towards an Ecological Society (Montreal:

Black Rose Books, 1980), p. 29.

[18] Murray first mentioned the phrase “social ecology” in “Ecology and

Revolutionary Thought.” He co-founded the Institute for Social Ecology

in 1974. He did not write his first article defining social ecology,

“What Is Radical Social Ecology?”, until 1983.

[19] In the essay “Post Scarcity Anarchism” Murray quoted Raoul

Vaneigem’s “Totality for Kids.” See Post-Scarcity Anarchism (Berkeley,

Calif.: Ramparts Press, 1971), p. 39. Vaneigem, in this two-part essay

(published in 1962 and 1963), referred several times to “hierarchical

power.” Originally titled “Banalités de base,” the essay has more

recently been retranslated as “Basic Banalities” and published (parts 1

and 2) in Ken Knabb, ed., Situationist International Anthology, rev. and

updated ed. (Berkeley: Bureau of Public Secrets, 2006). To my knowledge,

Murray first wrote about “hierarchical society” in the 1967 essay

“Desire and Need,” then at greater length in the 1969 “Listen, Marxist!”

and finally in his magisterial 1982 The Ecology of Freedom. “Ecology and

Revolutionary Thought,” as reprinted in Post-Scarcity Anarchism,

contains a discussion of hierarchy, but it was a revision added to the

1971 book and did not appear in the original article.

[20] The Ecology of Freedom (Palo Alto, Calif.: Cheshire Books, 1982)

opens with an epigraph from Kropotkin’s Ethics. Murray’s

acknowledgements say: “Peter Kropotkin’s writings on mutual aid and

anarchism remain an abiding tradition to which I am committed.”

[21] Bookchin, introduction, Post-Scarcity Anarchism, p. 21.

[22] Bookchin, “Deep Ecology, Anarcho-syndicalism,” pp. 52–53.

[23] Bookchin, “Ecology and Revolutionary Thought,” p. 69.

[24] Quotes in this paragraph are from Bookchin, “Forms of Freedom,” in

Post-Scarcity Anarchism, pp. 155–58.

[25] “Forms of Freedom,” pp. 155–65. In his preface to the 1985 Black

Rose edition of Post-Scarcity Murray wrote: “’The Forms of Freedom,’

written seventeen years ago, still constitutes the basis for my views on

libertarian municipalism: the assembly as the authentic basis for

democracy and my criticism of syndicalism.”

[26] The article was signed “The Anarchos Group.” In many respects this

remarkable article foreshadows the 1994 polemic “Social Anarchism vs.

Lifestyle Anarchism.” Murray’s 1972 complaints about the transience and

theatricality of the antiwar movement anticipate his later criticisms of

lifestyle “ad hoc adventurists.” This article was also his first

exposition of ideas that, ten years later, he would call “libertarian

municipalism.”

[27] Judith Malina, “Anarchists and the Pro-Hierarchical Left,” Anarchos

(June 1972), insert.

[28] Ibid.

[29] “Democratizing the Republic and Radicalizing the Democracy: An

Interview with Murray Bookchin” (part 2), Kick It Over (Winter 1985–86),

p. 9.

[30] Bookchin, “Communalist Project.”

[31] Woodcock, Anarchism, pp. 28, 30.

[32] Bookchin, “Anarchism: 1984 and Beyond,” address to the

international anarchist gathering, Venice, Sept. 24–30, 1984

(unpublished).

[33] Murray’s major book on libertarian municipalism is The Rise of

Urbanization and Decline of Citizenship (Sierra Club, 1987), republished

as Urbanization Against Cities (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1992) and as

From Urbanization to Cities (London: Cassell, 1995). From the early

1980s he wrote numerous articles on the subject as well. For a list of

those works, as well as a brief summary of the ideas, see my The

Politics of Social Ecology: Libertarian Municipalism (Montreal: Black

Rose Books, 1998).

[34] Bookchin, “Theses on Libertarian Municipalism” (1984), in The

Limits of the City, rev. ed. (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1986), p. 172.

[35] Bookchin, Rise of Urbanization, p. 258.

[36] “Democratizing the Republic,” p. 9.

[37] Bookchin, “The Meaning of Confederalism,” in From Urbanization to

Cities, pp. 252–53.

[38] “Democratizing the Republic,” p. 9.

[39] Bookchin, “Theses,” p. 178.

[40] Bookchin, “The Ghost of Anarcho-syndicalism,” Anarchist Studies 1

(1993), p. 7.

[41] Murray had some major disagreements with Proudhon, such as his

“commitment to a contractual form of economic relationships, as

distinguished from the communistic maxim of ‘from each according to his

or her abilities, to each according to his or her needs,’ a commitment

that ... can scarcely be distinguished from bourgeois conceptions of

‘right.’“ See Bookchin, “Deep Ecology, Anarcho-syndicalism.” He also

objected to “the proprietarian mentality that appears in so many of

Proudhon’s writings,” which he says is “dispensable.” See Bookchin,

“Ghost,” p. 7.

[42] Bookchin, “Deep Ecology, Anarcho-syndicalism,” p. 54.

[43] Bookchin, “Ghost,” p. 6; he is citing Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, The

Principle of Federation (1863), trans. Richard Vernon (Toronto:

University of Toronto Press, 1969), pp. 41, 45, 48.

[44] Bookchin, “Ghost,” p. 6.

[45] Bookchin, “Theses on Libertarian Municipalism,” p. 166.

[46] Michael Bakunin, “Revolutionary Catechism of the International

Revolutionary Society or Brotherhood” (1865), in Daniel Guerin, ed., No

Gods No Masters: An Anthology of Anarchism, trans. Paul Sharkey

(Edinburgh and San Francisco: A. K. Press, 1998), book 1, p. 142.

[47] Michael Bakunin, “Revolutionary Catechism” (1866) in Bakunin on

Anarchy, ed. Sam Dolgoff (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1972), pp. 82–83;

quoted in Bookchin, “Ghost,” p. 7.

[48] Bookchin, “Toward a Vision of the Urban Future,” in Towards an

Ecological Society, p. 183.

[49] Murray was careful to define his differences with Kropotkin’s

thought, objecting to Kropotkin’s notion of a “social instinct” to

validate his mutualism. That idea was “troubling, not only because it is

based on a highly selective study of animals, but because it tends to

ignore a host of solitary animals, including highly advanced mammals.

Even more troubling is that he tends to confuse animal troops, herds,

packs, and transient communities with societies — that is, with highly

mutable institutions, alterable as they are by virtue of the distinctly

human ability to form, develop, subvert, and overthrow them according to

their interests and will.” See Bookchin, “Deep Ecology,

Anarcho-syndicalism.”

[50] Peter Kropotkin, “The Anarchist Idea,” November 1, 1879; reprinted

in Daniel Guerin, No Gods No Masters, book 1, p. 232.

[51] Kropotkin, “The Commune of Paris,” March 20, 1880; reprinted in P.

A. Kropotkin, Selected Writings on Anarchism and Revolution, ed. Martin

A. Miller (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1970), pp. 128–29.

[52] Ibid., p. 132.

[53] Kropotkin, “Modern Science and Anarchism” (1913), in Kropotkin’s

Revolutionary Pamphlets, ed. Roger Baldwin (1927; reprinted New York:

Dover, 1970), p. 163; quoted in Bookchin, “Ghost,” p. 8.

[54] Ibid.

[55] Bookchin, “Theses,” p. 177.

[56] “Democratizing the Republic,” p. 9, emphasis added.

[57] Michael Bakunin, “Program and Object of the Secret Revolutionary

Organization of the International Brethren,” in Guerin, No Gods No

Masters, book 1, p. 155.

[58] Murray considered the revolutions in China and Cuba and Vietnam to

be nationalist in nature, not authentically socialist. See, for example,

Bookchin, Modern Crisis, p. 129.

[59] Bookchin, Keynote Address to Waterloo-PIRG, Waterloo, Ontario,

1985, videotape, Bookchin Papers, Tamiment Institute Library, New York.

[60] Bookchin, introduction to Towards an Ecological Society, p. 11.

[61] Bookchin, “Theses,” p. 178.

[62] Ibid., p. 179.

[63] Michael Bakunin, “Representative Government and Universal Suffrage”

(1870), in Dolgoff, ed., Bakunin on Anarchy, pp. 218–24; quoted, e.g.,

in “Ghost,” pp. 7–8.

[64] Bookchin, “Deep Ecology, Anarcho-syndicalism,” p. 55.

[65] Quotations in this paragraph are from Modern Crisis, pp. 39–41.

[66] Organise, no. 43 (Summer 1996).

[67] Organise, no. 44 (Autumn 1996).

[68] Bookchin, “Deep Ecology, Anarcho-syndicalism,” p. 55.

[69] Bookchin, “What Is Communalism? The Democratic Dimension of

Anarchism,” Green Perspectives no. 31 (October 1994), p. 3, quoting

Peter Marshall, Demanding the Impossible: A History of Anarchism

(London: HarperCollins, 1992), p. 22.

[70] Peter Kropotkin, “Anarchist Communism: Its Basis and Principles,”

in Kropotkin’s Revolutionary Pamphlets, ed. Roger Baldwin (1927;

reprinted by New York: Dover, 1970), p. 68.

[71] For Murray’s objections to consensus decision-making, see “What Is

Communalism?”

[72] Bookchin, “Theses,” p. 178.

[73] Bookchin, letter to the editor, A: Rivista Anarchica [Milan] 185

(Sept.-Oct. 1991), pp. 40–41; written Aug. 14, 1991.

[74] Bookchin, “Deep Ecology, Anarcho-syndicalism,” pp. 57–58.

[75] Bookchin, “What Is Communalism?” p. 1.

[76] Bookchin, “Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism: An Unbridgeable

Chasm,” in Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism: An Unbridgeable

Chasm (Edinburgh and San Francisco: A.K. Press, 1995).

[77] Ibid., p. 10.

[78] Ibid., p. 35.

[79] Ibid., p. 58. On “the tyranny of structurelessness,” see Jo

Freeman’s classic 1970 article by that name online at

flag.blackened.net

).

[80] Kropotkin, “Anarchism” (1910), in Kropotkin’s Revolutionary

Pamphlets; Bookchin, “Social Anarchism,” pp. 35, 1–2.

[81] Bookchin, “Social Anarchism,” p. 16.

[82] Bookchin, “What Is Communalism?” p. 4.

[83] Ibid., p. 5.

[84] Kingsley Widmer, “How Broad and Deep Is Anarchism?” Social

Anarchism, no. 24 (1997); Jason McQuinn, review of Social Anarchism or

Lifestyle Anarchism, in Alternative Press Review (Spring — Summer 1987);

Laure Akai, “Social Anarchism Revisited,” in Anarchy: Journal of Desire

Armed, no. 44 (Fall-Winter 1997–98); Bob Black, Anarchy After Leftism

(Columbia, Mo.: C.A.L. Press, 1997).

[85] David Watson, Beyond Bookchin: Preface for a Future Social Ecology

(Brooklyn: Autonomedia, 1996).

[86] Bookchin, “Whither Anarchism?” in Anarchism, Marxism.

[87] David Watson, “Swamp Fever, Primitivism, and the ‘Ideological

Vortex’: Farewell to All That,” Fifth Estate (Fall 1997).

[88] Quotations in this section are from Murray Bookchin, Anarchism,

Marxism, pp. 122–24.

[89] Widmer, “How Broad and Deep?”

[90] Bookchin, letter to Organise!, p. 18. Sadly, Iain Mackay, a writer

associated with Organise!, is currently circulating a rumor that late in

life Murray suffered from Alzheimer’s disease. As his primary caregiver,

I can state categorically that this rumor is entirely false. Murray

remained lucid almost to the end of his life.

[91] Space has not permitted me to discuss Murray’s philosophical ideas,

which he called dialectical naturalism. See his The Philosophy of Social

Ecology, rev. ed. (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1984).

[92] Bookchin, “Communalist Project.”