💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › bob-black-the-libertarian-as-conservative.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:55:46. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Libertarian As Conservative
Author: Bob Black
Date: 1984
Language: en
Topics: neoliberalism
Source: Retrieved on October 1, 2009 from http://www.inspiracy.com/black/abolition/libertarian.html
Notes: (A shorter, different version of this article was delivered as an address at the fourth annual convocation of the Eris Society in Aspen, Colorado in August 1984.)

Bob Black

The Libertarian As Conservative

I agreed to come here today to speak on some such subject as “The

Libertarian as Conservative.” To me this is so obvious that I am hard

put to find something to say to people who still think libertarianism

has something to do with liberty. A libertarian is just a Republican who

takes drugs. I’d have preferred a more controversial topic like “The

Myth of the Penile Orgasm.” But since my attendance here is subsidized

by the esteemed distributor of a veritable reference library on mayhem

and dirty tricks, I can’t just take the conch and go rogue. I will

indeed mutilate the sacred cow which is libertarianism, as ordered, but

I’ll administer a few hard lefts to the right in my own way. And I don’t

mean the easy way. I could just point to the laissez-faire Trilateralism

of the Libertarian Party, then leave and go look for a party. It doesn’t

take long to say that if you fight fire with fire, you’ll get burned.

If that were all I came up with, somebody would up and say that the LP

has lapsed from the libertarian faith, just as Christians have insisted

that their behavior over the last 1900 years or so shouldn’t be held

against Christianity. There are libertarians who try to retrieve

libertarianism from the Libertarian Party just as there are Christians

who try to reclaim Christianity from Christendom and communists (I’ve

tried to myself) who try to save communism from the Communist parties

and states. They (and I) meant well but we lost. Libertarianism is

party-archist fringe-rightism just as socialism really is what Eastern

European dissidents call “real socialism,” i.e., the real-life

state-socialism of queues, quotas, corruption and coercion. But I choose

not to knock down this libertarian strawman-qua-man who’s blowing over

anyway. A wing of the Reaganist Right has obviously appropriated, with

suspect selectivity, such libertarian themes as deregulation and

voluntarism. Ideologues indignate that Reagan has travestied their

principles. Tough shit! I notice that it’s their principles, not mine,

that he found suitable to travesty. This kind of quarrel doesn’t

interest me. My reasons for regarding libertarianism as conservative run

deeper than that.

My target is what most libertarians have in common — with each other,

and with their ostensible enemies. Libertarians serve the state all the

better because they declaim against it. At bottom, they want what it

wants. But you can’t want what the state wants without wanting the

state, for what the state wants is the conditions in which it

flourishes. My (unfriendly) approach to modern society is to regard it

as an integrated totality. Silly doctrinaire theories which regard the

state as a parasitic excrescence on society cannot explain its

centuries-long persistence, its ongoing encroachment upon what was

previously market terrain, or its acceptance by the overwhelming

majority of people including its demonstrable victims.

A far more plausible theory is that the state and (at least) this form

of society have a symbiotic (however sordid) interdependence, that the

state and such institutions as the market and the nuclear family are, in

several ways, modes of hierarchy and control. Their articulation is not

always harmonious (herein of turf-fights) but they share a common

interest in consigning their conflicts to elite or expert resolution. To

demonize state authoritarianism while ignoring identical albeit

contract-consecrated subservient arrangements in the large-scale

corporations which control the world economy is fetishism at its worst.

And yet (to quote the most vociferous of radical libertarians, Professor

Murray Rothbard) there is nothing un-libertarian about “organization,

hierarchy, wage-work, granting of funds by libertarian millionaires, and

a libertarian party.” Indeed. That is why libertarianism is just

conservatism with a rationalist/positivist veneer.

Libertarians render a service to the state which only they can provide.

For all their complaints about its illicit extensions they concede, in

their lucid moments, that the state rules far more by consent than by

coercion — which is to say, on present-state “libertarian” terms the

state doesn’t rule at all, it merely carries out the tacit or explicit

terms of its contracts. If it seems contradictory to say that coercion

is consensual, the contradiction is in the world, not in the expression,

and can’t adequately be rendered except by dialectical discourse.

One-dimensional syllogistics can’t do justice to a world largely lacking

in the virtue. If your language lacks poetry and paradox, it’s unequal

to the task of accounting for actuality. Otherwise anything radically

new is literally unspeakable. The scholastic “A = A” logic created by

the Catholic Church which the libertarians inherited, unquestioned, from

the Randites is just as constrictively conservative as the Newspeak of

1984.

The state commands, for the most part, only because it commands popular

support. It is (and should be) an embarrassment to libertarians that the

state rules with mass support — including, for all practical purposes,

theirs.

Libertarians reinforce acquiescent attitudes by diverting discontents

which are generalized (or tending that way) and focusing them on

particular features and functions of the state which they are the first

to insist are expendable! Thus they turn potential revolutionaries into

repairmen. Constructive criticism is really the subtlest sort of praise.

If the libertarians succeed in relieving the state of its exiguous

activities, they just might be its salvation. No longer will reverence

for authority be eroded by the prevalent official ineptitude. The more

the state does, the more it does badly. Surely one reason for the common

man’s aversion to Communism is his reluctance to see the entire economy

run like the Post Office. The state tries to turn its soldiers and

policemen into objects of veneration and respect, but uniforms lose a

lot of their mystique when you see them on park rangers and garbage men.

The ideals and institutions of authority tend to cluster together, both

subjectively and objectively. You may recall Edward Gibbon’s remark

about the eternal alliance of Throne and Altar. Disaffection from

received dogmas has a tendency to spread. If there is any future for

freedom, it depends on this. Unless and until alienation recognizes

itself, all the guns the libertarians cherish will be useless against

the state.

You might object that what I’ve said may apply to the minarchist

majority of libertarians, but not to the self-styled anarchists among

them. Not so. To my mind a right-wing anarchist is just a minarchist

who’d abolish the state to his own satisfaction by calling it something

else. But this incestuous family squabble is no affair of mine. Both

camps call for partial or complete privatization of state functions but

neither questions the functions themselves. They don’t denounce what the

state does, they just object to who’s doing it. This is why the people

most victimized by the state display the least interest in

libertarianism. Those on the receiving end of coercion don’t quibble

over their coercers’ credentials. If you can’t pay or don’t want to, you

don’t much care if your deprivation is called larceny or taxation or

restitution or rent. If you like to control your own time, you

distinguish employment from enslavement only in degree and duration. An

ideology which outdoes all others (with the possible exception of

Marxism) in its exaltation of the work ethic can only be a brake on

anti-authoritarian orientations, even if it does make the trains run on

time.

My second argument, related to the first, is that the libertarian phobia

as to the state reflects and reproduces a profound misunderstanding of

the operative forces which make for social control in the modern world.

If — and this is a big “if,” especially where bourgeois libertarians are

concerned — what you want is to maximize individual autonomy, then it is

quite clear that the state is the least of the phenomena which stand in

your way.

Imagine that you are a Martian anthropologist specializing in Terran

studies and equipped with the finest in telescopes and video equipment.

You have not yet deciphered any Terran language and so you can only

record what Earthlings do, not their shared misconceptions as to what

they’re doing and why. However, you can gauge roughly when they’re doing

what they want and when they’re doing something else. Your first

important discovery is that Earthlings devote nearly all their time to

unwelcome activities. The only important exception is a dwindling set of

hunter-gatherer groups unperturbed by governments, churches and schools

who devote some four hours a day to subsistence activities which so

closely resemble the leisure activities of the privileged classes in

industrial capitalist countries that you are uncertain whether to

describe what they do as work or play. But the state and the market are

eradicating these holdouts and you very properly concentrate on the

almost all-inclusive world-system which, for all its evident internal

antagonisms as epitomized in war, is much the same everywhere. The

Terran young, you further observe, are almost wholly subject to the

impositions of the family and the school, sometimes seconded by the

church and occasionally the state. The adults often assemble in families

too, but the place where they pass the most time and submit to the

closest control is at work. Thus, without even entering into the

question of the world economy’s ultimate dictation within narrow limits

of everybody’s productive activity, it’s apparent that the source of the

greatest direct duress experienced by the ordinary adult is not the

state but rather the business that employs him. Your foreman or

supervisor gives you more or-else orders in a week than the police do in

a decade.

If one looks at the world without prejudice but with an eye to

maximizing freedom, the major coercive institution is not the state,

it’s work. Libertarians who with a straight face call for the abolition

of the state nonetheless look on anti-work attitudes with horror. The

idea of abolishing work is, of course, an affront to common sense. But

then so is the idea of abolishing the state. If a referendum were held

among libertarians which posed as options the abolition of work with

retention of the state, or abolition of the state with retention of

work, does anyone doubt the outcome?

Libertarians are into linear reasoning and quantitative analysis. If

they applied these methods to test their own prescriptions they’d be in

for a shock. That’s the point of my Martian thought experiment. This is

not to say that the state isn’t just as unsavory as the libertarians say

it is. But it does suggest that the state is important, not so much for

the direct duress it inflicts on convicts and conscripts, for instance,

as for its indirect back-up of employers who regiment employees,

shopkeepers who arrest shoplifters, and parents who paternalize

children. In these classrooms, the lesson of submission is learned. Of

course, there are always a few freaks like anarcho-capitalists or

Catholic anarchists, but they’re just exceptions to the rule of rule.

Unlike side issues like unemployment, unions, and minimum-wage laws, the

subject of work itself is almost entirely absent from libertarian

literature. Most of what little there is consists of Randite rantings

against parasites, barely distinguishable from the invective inflicted

on dissidents by the Soviet press, and Sunday-school platitudinizing

that there is no free lunch — this from fat cats who have usually

ingested a lot of them. In 1980 a rare exception appeared in a book

review published in the Libertarian Review by Professor John Hospers,

the Libertarian Party elder state’s-man who flunked out of the Electoral

College in 1972. Here was a spirited defense of work by a college

professor who didn’t have to do any. To demonstrate that his arguments

were thoroughly conservative, it is enough to show that they agreed in

all essentials with Marxism-Leninism.

Hospers thought he could justify wage-labor, factory discipline and

hierarchic management by noting that they’re imposed in Leninist regimes

as well as under capitalism. Would he accept the same argument for the

necessity of repressive sex and drug laws? Like other libertarians,

Hospers is uneasy — hence his gratuitous red-baiting — because

libertarianism and Leninism are as different as Coke and Pepsi when it

comes to consecrating class society and the source of its power, work.

Only upon the firm foundation of factory fascism and office oligarchy do

libertarians and Leninists dare to debate the trivial issues dividing

them. Toss in the mainstream conservatives who feel just the same and we

end up with a veritable trilateralism of pro-work ideology seasoned to

taste.

Hospers, who never has to, sees nothing demeaning in taking orders from

bosses, for “how else could a large scale factory be organized?” In

other words, “wanting to abolish authority in large-scale industry is

tantamount to wanting to abolish industry itself.” Hospers again? No,

Frederick Engels! Marx agreed: “Go and run one of the Barcelona

factories without direction, that is to say, without authority!” (Which

is just what the Catalan workers did in 1936, while their

anarcho-syndicalist leaders temporized and cut deals with the

government.) “Someone,” says Hospers, “has to make decisions and” —

here’s the kicker — “someone else has to implement them.” Why? His

precursor Lenin likewise endorsed “individual dictatorial powers” to

assure “absolute and strict unity of will.” “But how can strict unity of

will be ensured? By thousands subordinating their will to the will of

one.” What’s needed to make industrialism work is “iron discipline while

at work, with unquestioning obedience to the will of a single person,

the soviet leader, while at work.” Arbeit macht frei!

Some people giving orders and others obeying them: this is the essence

of servitude. Of course, as Hospers smugly observes, “one can at least

change jobs,” but you can’t avoid having a job — just as under statism

one can at least change nationalities but you can’t avoid subjection to

one nation-state or another. But freedom means more than the right to

change masters.

Hospers and other libertarians are wrong to assume, with Manchester

industrialist Engels, that technology imposes its division of labor

“independent of social organization.” Rather, the factory is an

instrument of social control, the most effective ever devised to enforce

the class chasm between the few who “make decisions” and the many who

“implement them.” Industrial technology is much more the product than

the source of workplace totalitarianism. Thus the revolt against work —

reflected in absenteeism, sabotage, turnover, embezzlement, wildcat

strikes, and goldbricking — has far more liberatory promise than the

machinations of “libertarian” politicos and propagandists.

Most work serves the predatory purposes of commerce and coercion and can

be abolished outright. The rest can be automated away and/or transformed

— by the experts, the workers who do it — into creative, playlike

pastimes whose variety and conviviality will make extrinsic inducements

like the capitalist carrot and the Communist stick equally obsolete. In

the hopefully impending meta-industrial revolution, libertarian

communists revolting against work will settle accounts with

“libertarians” and “Communists” working against revolt. And then we can

go for the gusto!

Even if you think everything I’ve said about work, such as the

possibility of its abolition, is visionary nonsense, the anti-liberty

implications of its prevalence would still hold good. The time of your

life is the one commodity you can sell but never buy back. Murray

Rothbard thinks egalitarianism is a revolt against nature, but his day

is 24 hours long, just like everybody else’s. If you spend most of your

waking life taking orders or kissing ass, if you get habituated to

hierarchy, you will become passive-aggressive, sado-masochistic, servile

and stupefied, and you will carry that load into every aspect of the

balance of your life. Incapable of living a life of liberty, you’ll

settle for one of its ideological representations, like libertarianism.

You can’t treat values like workers, hiring and firing them at will and

assigning each a place in an imposed division of labor. The taste for

freedom and pleasure can’t be compartmentalized.

Libertarians complain that the state is parasitic, an excrescence on

society. They think it’s like a tumor you could cut out, leaving the

patient just as he was, only healthier. They’ve been mystified by their

own metaphors. Like the market, the state is an activity, not an entity.

The only way to abolish the state is to change the way of life it forms

a part of. That way of life, if you call that living, revolves around

work and takes in bureaucracy, moralism, schooling, money, and more.

Libertarians are conservatives because they avowedly want to maintain

most of this mess and so unwittingly perpetuate the rest of the racket.

But they’re bad conservatives because they’ve forgotten the reality of

institutional and ideological interconnection which was the original

insight of the historical conservatives. Entirely out of touch with the

real currents of contemporary resistance, they denounce practical

opposition to the system as “nihilism,” “Luddism,” and other big words

they don’t understand. A glance at the world confirms that their utopian

capitalism just can’t compete with the state. With enemies like

libertarians, the state doesn’t need friends.