💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › anonymous-infidels-freethinkers-humanists-unbelievers.g… captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:08:45. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Infidels, Freethinkers, Humanists, and Unbelievers Author: Anonymous Date: Unknown Language: en Topics: Max Stirner, philosophy, hegel, Source: http://www.theinfidels.org/zunb-maxstirner.htm
"The truth wears longer than all the gods; for it is only in the truth's
service, and for love of it, that people have overthrown the gods and at
last God himself. "The truth" outlasts the downfall of the world of
gods, for it is the immortal soul of this transitory world of gods; it
is Deity itself."
-- Max Stirner
Johann Kaspar Schmidt, better known as Max Stirner (the nom de plume he
adopted from a schoolyard nickname he had acquired as a child because of
his high brow [Stirn]), German philosopher, who ranks as one of the
literary grandfathers of nihilism, existentialism and anarchism,
especially of individualist anarchism. Stirner himself explicitly denied
holding any absolute position in his philosophy, further stating that if
he must be identified with some "-ism" let it be egoism — the antithesis
of all ideologies and social causes, as he conceived of it.
Stirner's main work is The Ego and Its Own, also known as The Ego and
His Own (Der Einzige und sein Eigentum in German), which was first
published in Leipzig, 1844, and has since appeared in numerous editions
and translations.
Stirner was born in Bayreuth, Bavaria, on October 25, 1806. What little
is known of his life is mostly due to the Scottish born German writer
John Henry Mackay, who wrote a biography of Stirner (Max Stirner - sein
Leben und sein Werk), published in German in 1898. A 2005 English
translation has now appeared.
Stirner attended university in Berlin, where he attended the lectures of
Hegel, who was to become a vital source of inspiration for his thinking,
and on the structure of whose work Phenomenology of Spirit
(Phänomenologie des Geistes), he modelled his own book. (Hegel's
influence on Stirner's thinking is debatable, and is discussed in more
detail below.)
While in Berlin in 1841, Stirner sometimes participated in a discussion
group of young philosophers called "The Free" [Die Freien], and who
historians have subsequently categorized as so-called Young Hegelians.
Some of the best known names in 19th century literature were members of
this discussion group, including Bruno Bauer, Karl Marx, Friedrich
Engels, Ludwig Feuerbach, and Arnold Ruge.
While some of the Young Hegelians were eager subscribers to Hegel's
dialectical method, and attempted to apply dialectical approaches to
Hegel's conclusions, the "left wing" members of the Young Hegelians,
e.g. those named above, broke with Hegel. Feuerbach and Bauer led this
charge.
Frequently the debates would take place at Hippel's, a Weinstube (wine
bar) in Friedrichstrasse, attended by, amongst others, the young Karl
Marx and Friedrich Engels, at that time still adherents of Feuerbach.
The only portrait we have of Stirner consists of a cartoon by Engels,
drawn forty years later from memory on the request of Stirner's
biographer John Henry Mackay.
Stirner worked as a schoolteacher employed in an academy for young girls
when he wrote his major work The Ego and Its Own, which in part is a
polemic against both Hegel and some Young Hegelians (e.g. Ludwig
Feuerbach, Bruno Bauer), but also against communists as Wilhelm Weitling
and against the anarchist Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, not to mention
Feuerbach. He resigned his teaching position in anticipation of the
controversy arising from his major work's publication in October 1844.
Stirner married twice; his first wife was a household servant with whom
he fell in love at an early age. Soon after their marriage, she died due
to complications with pregnancy in 1838. In 1843 he married Marie
Dähnhardt, an intellectual associated with Die Freien. They divorced in
1846. The bitter ironic dedication of The Ego and Its Own - "to my
sweetheart Marie Dähnhardt" - may hint at the reasons for the shortness
of their liaison. Marie later converted to catholicism and died 1902 in
London.
One of the most curious events in those times was that Stirner planned
and financed (with his second wife's inheritance) an attempt by some
Young Hegelians to own and operate a milk-shop on co-operative
principles. This enterprise failed because the German dairy farmers
harboured suspicions of these well-dressed intellectuals with their
confusing talk about profit-sharing and other high-minded ideals.
Meanwhile, the milk shop itself appeared so ostentatiously decorated
that most of the customers felt too poorly dressed to buy their milk
there.
After The Ego and Its Own, Stirner published German translations of Adam
Smith's The Wealth of Nations and Jean-Baptiste Say's Traite d'Economie
Politique, and a set of his replies to his critics were collected in a
small work titled History of Reaction (1852).
In 1856, Stirner died in Berlin, Prussia from an infected insect bite.
As the story goes, Bruno Bauer was the only Young Hegelian present at
his funeral.
The status of the philosophy of Max Stirner has been largely determined
by his criticism of others, and his treatment by his critics. His
lengthy repudiation of Hegelian philosophy has reserved an historically
dubious niche for his name in the list of "Young Hegelians" offered in
standard histories of 19th century philosophy, and, perhaps more
importantly (so far as keeping his works in print), the perceived
importance of his philosophy in the intellectual development of the
young Karl Marx has earned him a footnote in many reading lists.
The number of pages Marx and Engels devote to attacking Stirner in (the
unexpurgated text of) The German Ideology exceeds the total of Stirner's
written works. Marx's incoherent (and frequently ad hominem) screed has
led a few of his followers in each generation to investiage the source
text that inspired so much vituperation. Leaving aside Stirner's
critical engagement with Feuerbachian Humanism, German Liberalism, and
other ideologies of his era, we may say that Stirner's purely negative
associations with Hegel and Marxism alone have been sufficient to assign
him a permanent place in the canon of Western philosophy --albeit a
place of infamy. Even those who value Stirner's contribution to the
Western tradition tend to focus on the negative arguments of The Ego and
its Own, viz., his condemnation of the social, moral, religious and
political conditions that surrounded him in 19th century Europe.
Although Stirner provides plenty of such "negative" material for our
consideration, it is disappointing to find that the "positive aspect"
(or "posited tenets") of his philosophy has been so rarely taken into
consideration in evaluating his significance. Although less overtly
prejudicial to Stirner's work, the small literature of comparative
essays that have attempted to relate Stirner in Nietzschean terms (e.g.,
R.W.K. Patterson, The Nihilistic Egoist, & John Carroll, 1974, Break Out
from the Crystal Palace) have also obscured the primary source text by
reducing Stirner's work into a set of points that can (or cannot be)
validated in the light of later philosophical developments.
The root of the problem is partly methodological: to describe Stirner
simply in contradistinction to Hegel (or Marx, or Feuerbach, etc.) must
inevitably fail to touch on the heart of his own philosophy, for the
plain reason that his own arguments stand independent of (and in radical
contradistinction to) the common assumptions of the 19th century German
tradition.
Stirner's main work is The Ego and Its Own (org. 'Der Einzige und sein
Eigentum'), which appeared in Leipzig in 1844. One can chart the
development of his philosophy through a series of articles that appeared
shortly before this central work (the articles The False Principle of
Our Education and Art and Religion furnishing particular interest).
In The Ego and Its Own Stirner launches a radical anti-authoritarian and
individualist critique of contemporary Prussian society, and modernity
and modern western society as such, and offers an approach to human
existence which depicts the self as a creative non-entity, beyond
language and reality, as generally conceived of in the western
philosophical tradition.
In short, the book proclaims that all religions and ideologies rest on
empty concepts, that, once undermined by individual self-interest, break
apart to reveal their emptiness. The same holds true for those of
society's institutions, that uphold these concepts, be it the state,
legislation, the church, the systems of education, or other institutions
that claim authority over the individual.
Stirner's argument explores and extends the limits of Hegelian
criticism, aiming his critique especially at those of his contemporaries
(particularly colleagues amongst the Young Hegelians, most importantly
Ludwig Feuerbach), embracing popular 'ideologies', explicitly including
nationalism, statism, liberalism, socialism, communism and humanism.
In the time of spirits thoughts grew till they overtopped my head, whose
offspring they yet were; they hovered about me and convulsed me like
fever-phantasies -- an awful power. The thoughts had become corporeal on
their own account, were ghosts, e. g. God, Emperor, Pope, Fatherland,
etc. If I destroy their corporeity, then I take them back into mine, and
say: "I alone am corporeal." And now I take the world as what it is to
me, as mine, as my property; I refer all to myself.
— Max Stirner, The Ego and Its Own, p 15.
Only when the false claims of authority by such concepts and
institutions as the above, are revealed, can real individual action,
power and identity take place. Individual self-realization rests on each
individual's desire to fulfill his egoism, be it by instinct,
unknowingly, unwillingly - or consciously, fully aware of his
self-interest
The primary difference between an unwilling and a willing egoist, is
that the first will be 'possessed' by an empty idea, or a 'spook', in
the hope that this idea will make him happy, and the last, in contrast,
will be able to freely choose the ways of his egoism, and enjoy himself
while doing it. The contrast is also expressed in terms of the
difference between the individual being the possessor of his concepts as
opposed to being possessed thereby. Only when one realizes that all
sacred truths such as law, right, morality, religion etc., are nothing
other than artificial concepts, and not holy authorities to be obeyed,
can one act freely. In Stirner's idiom, to be free is to be both one's
own "creature" (in the sense of 'creation') and one's own "creator"
(dislocating the traditional role assigned to the gods):
Sacred things exist only for the egoist who does not acknowledge
himself, the involuntary egoist ... in short, for the egoist who would
like not to be an egoist, and abases himself (combats his egoism), but
at the same time abases himself only for the sake of "being exalted",
and therefore of gratifying his egoism. Because he would like to cease
to be an egoist, he looks about in heaven and earth for higher beings to
serve and sacrifice himself to; but, however much he shakes and
disciplines himself, in the end he does all for his own sake... [on]
this account I call him the involuntary egoist. ...As you are each
instant, you are your own creature in this very 'creature' you do not
wish to lose yourself, the creator. You are yourself a higher being than
you are, and surpass yourself ... just this, as an involuntary egoist,
you fail to recognize; and therefore the 'higher essence' is to you --an
alien essence. ... Alienness is a criterion of the "sacred". [Ibidem,
Cambridge edition, p. 37-8]
Stirner has been broadly understood as a proponent of both psychological
egoism and ethical egoism, although the latter position can be disputed,
maintaining that there is no sense in Stirner's writing, in which one
'ought to' pursue one's own interest, and further claiming any such
category of 'ought' would be a new 'fixed idea'. The notion that one's
own interest (or one's own nature) is a calling to which one is beholden
(or "ought to follow" in any moral or imperative sense) is, strictly
speaking, contrary to Stirner's tenets. However, he may be understood as
a rational egoist in the sense that he apparently considered it
irrational not to act in one's self interest.
On the other hand, Stirner repeatedly refers to a fundamental state of
existence, which he seems to view as ideal, 'like the bird, who sings
because it is a singer'. He provokes his readers with references to
their christian-adopted fear of their own nudity, encouraging them to
throw away such fixed ideas, to see and become 'who they really are'. In
such terms, Stirner's egoism may be seen as 'ethical' and perhaps even
as idealistic.
The political ramifications of Stirner's work are sometimes described as
a form of individualist anarchism. Stirner however does not identify
himself as an anarchist, and includes anarchists among the parties
subject to his criticism. In particular, Stirner's political doctrine
repudiates revolution in the traditional sense, and ridicules social
movements aimed at overturning the state as tacitly statist (i.e., aimed
at the establishment of a new state thereafter), putting forth instead a
unique model of self-empowerment and social change through "union
activism" --although the definition and explanation of the latter is
unique to Stirner, and does not resemble a standard socialist doctrine
of trade unionism. Some people see Ernst JĂĽnger's revolutionary
conservative concept of the anarch as a more faithful rendition of
Stirner's thought.
Stirner's demolition of 'fixed ideas' and absolute concepts (derided as
'spooks' of contemporary philosophy) lead him to a nameless void,
without meaning and without existence; a so-called 'creative nothing'
from which mind and creativity will arise. The 'nothing' Stirner arrives
at, in the process of tearing down every absolute concept (every
absolute description) outside of himself, he later described as an
'end-point of language', meaning this is where all description comes to
an end; it cannot be described. But this is also the place where all
description begins, where the individual self can describe (and
therefore create) the world in its own meaning.
In order to understand this 'creative nothing', which Stirner strives so
hard to argue for and explain, to the extent that his work invokes
poetry and vivid imagery to give meaning to his words - but helplessly
cannot describe by words alone, it is worth bearing his Hegelian origins
in mind. The 'creative nothing' by its dialectical shortcomings creates
the need for a description, for meaning. You need the word 'nothing' to
describe nothing - therefore nothing is a paradox. You cannot say
'nothing' without someone saying it, at the very least. And you need the
concept of self to describe who is describing it. The nothing gives way
to individual meaning, existence and power.
Stirner elaborated on his attempt on describing the undescribable in the
essay "Stirner's Critics", written by Stirner in response to Feuerbach
and others (in custom with the time, he refers to himself in the third
person) :
Stirner speaks of the Unique and says immediately: Names name you not.
He articulates the word, so long as he calls it the Unique, but adds
nonetheless that the Unique is only a name. He thus means something
different from what he says, as perhaps someone who calls you Ludwig
does not mean a Ludwig in general, but means You, for which he has no
word. (...) It is the end point of our phrase world, of this world in
whose "beginning was the Word."
— Max Stirner, Stirner's Critics
One might describe this place (if describable) as the place where we
come into existence; where we are born (see reference to the modern
theorist Julia Kristeva below).
In a peculiar but formally acurate sense, we could summarize The Ego and
Its Own as "an ethic of owning the world". The book both opens and
closes with a quotation from Goethe that reads "I have taken up my cause
without foundation", with the (unstated) next line of the poem being
"…and all the world is mine". Contrary to the common gloss on the
Stirner, one of his central doctrines is that the self "is nothing"; and
in realizing this one is said to "own the world", because (as the book
states in its last line:) "all things are nothing to me" [Ibidem., p.
324].
This philosophical standpoint, and the type of imagery used to advance
it, remains shocking to the Western philosophical tradition that Stirner
emerged from, and still in our times, authors such as David Leopold (in
his introduction to the Cambridge Edition of _The Ego..._, 1995 &
reprinted in 2000) express stunned disbelief at most of what Stirner has
to say about the nature of mind, world, and "property" (as he defines
it). However, from other philosophical perspectives Stirner's conclusion
that "the I" (or "the ego) is nothing is less surprising; both this and
the related tenet that "the world is empty" have no similar Western
precedent, but recall to mind closely comparable sentiments from
canonical Theravada Buddhism:
By bringing the essence into prominence one degrades the hitherto
misapprehended appearance to a bare semblance, a deception. The essence
of the world, so attractive and splendid, is for him who looks to the
bottom of it -- emptiness; emptiness is --world's essence (world's
doings). [Ibidem, p. 40]
... [F]or 'being' is abstraction, as is even 'the I'. Only I am not
abstraction alone: I am all in all, consequently, even abstraction or
nothing: I am all and nothing; I am not a mere thought, but at the same
time I am full of thoughts, a thought-world. [Ibidem, p. 300]
I say: liberate yourself as far as you can, and you have done your part;
for it is not given to every one to break through all limits, or, more
expressively, not to everyone is that a limit which is a limit for the
rest. Consequently, do not tire yourself with toiling at the limits of
others; enough if you tear down yours. [...] He who overturns one of his
limits may have shown others the way and the means; the overturning of
their limits remains their affair.
Significantly, Stirner describes this world-view, in brief, as
"enjoyment", and he frequently glosses the "nothingness" of the non-self
as "unutterable" (p. 314) or "unnameable" (p. 132), "unspeakable" yet "a
mere word" (p. 164; cf. Stirner's comments on the Skeptic concepts
ataraxia and aphasia, p. 26). This ethic of self-liberation is a
striking contrast to the exhortations on duty, obedience, and public
morality common to Kant, Hegel, and even anti-establishment authors like
Marx who drew so much of their vocabulary from the former generation.
Contrary to the common gloss on Stirner, this combined teaching of
"egoism" and the illusory nature of the ego is not associated with a
life of rapacious self-interest, but rather, as the author states
repeatedly, is part of a life of "love" and "compassion" (for "every
feeling being"); but this "consciously egoistic" love comes with the
important caveat that these feelings are without the "alienness" of a
religion, and are no longer social "duties", nor "fixed notions", nor
even "passions":
<qoute> ...[Love] cuts no better figure than any other passion [if] I
obey [it] blindly. The ambitious man, who is carried away by ambition...
has let this passion grow up into a despot against whom he abandons all
power of dissolution; he has given up himself because he cannot dissolve
himself, and consequently cannot absolve himself from the passion: he is
possessed. I love men, too, not merely individuals, but every one. But I
love them with the consciousness of my egoism; I love them because love
makes me happy, I love because loving is natural to me, it pleases me. I
know no 'commandment of love'. I have a fellow-feeling with every
feeling being, and their torment torments, their refreshment refreshes
me too... [Ibidem, p. 258] </qoute>
Turning to the introduction to the Cambridge edition of _The Ego and its
Own_ provided by David Leopold (Ibidem, pg. xxxi), we find a badly
flawed sketch of this important aspect of Stirner's work:
... [W]hen Stirner talks of the egoist being 'owner' of the world it
seems simply to indicate the absence of obligations on the egoist --a
bleak and uncompromising vision that he captures in an appropriately
alimentary image:
"Where the world comes in my way -- and it comes in my way everywhere --
I consume it to the quiet hunger of my egoism. For me you are nothing
but -- my food, even as I too am fed upon and turned to use by you. We
have only one relation to each other, that of usableness, of utility, of
use. We owe each other nothing. (p. 263)"
The supposedly "bleak and uncompromising vision" that he alludes to on
page 263 is in fact a description of a bird singing in a tree for the
sheer joy of creating its own song; the image is not "bleak", but
positively ebullient. Stirner's words immediately preceding the
quotation that Leopold has taken out of context are as follows:
But not only not [sic.] for your sake, not even for the truth's sake
either do I speak out what I think. No:
I sing as the bird sings,
That on the bough alights;
The song that from me springs
Is pay that well requites.
I sing because -- I am a singer. But I use [gebrauche] you for it
because I -- need [brauche] ears. [Ibidem, 263]
Stirner's intended meaning for the word 'use' [gebrauche] in this
excerpt is established in the context of the metaphor of the singing
bird: the bird's song is reward enough for the act of singing, but yet
the performer has some 'use' for an audience. The very next statement
("where the world comes in my way..." etc.) broadens the meaning to
encompass all sorts of creative engagement with the world (i.e.,
Stirner's point is not limited to birds or vocalists), and the paragraph
ends with a re-affirmation of the central point of the metaphor, namely,
that the performer has no obligation to the audience, but sings out of
sheer joy for the act of performing. Thus, it seems, the audience is
encouraged to get the same 'use' out of the performance, viz., mutual
joy/enjoyment without any obligations binding the two parties. By taking
the quote out of context, Leopold effectively imposes an unintended
meaning upon the verb "use" [gebrauche] as somehow implying
"instrumental treatment" (p. xxxi), but the specific "use" that Stirner
here describes is the enjoyment of a listener for a song, or of a singer
for the very act of singing. This misuse of the source text is further
demonstrated when we consider Stirner's words immediately following the
quotation selected by Leopold:
We owe each other nothing, for what I seem to owe you I owe at most to
myself. If I show you a cheerful air in order to cheer you likewise,
then your cheerfulness is of consequence to me, and my air serves my
wish... [Ibidem]
Whereas Leopold abruptly ends his quotation with "We owe each other
nothing" (full stop, i.e., failing to provide an ellipsis to indicate
that he is breaking off Stirner in mid-sentence) the original text
reiterates that the subject being discussed is, in fact, the imparting
of cheerfulness (without any debt being owed between the parties cheered
up, i.e., because each cheers the other for his own delight, as per the
bird with its song).
There is a broad problem of interpretation in the assignation of
"pessimism" to Stirner's philosophy, despite its frequently ebullient
tone, and sometimes overtly optimistic imagery. This extends to the
important issue of Stirner's writing about writing, viz., the role of
the author (and "critic") in self-liberation and effecting social
change.
In the foregoing section, readers were encouraged to decide for
themselves if Stirner's thesis is truly "a bleak and uncompromising
vision" as Leopold characterizes it in his introduction (op. cit.
supra). In that instance, the source text actually presents a discussion
of how people can spread joy to one-another (with detachment, and no
sense of mutual obligation), explained by way of a rather impish and fey
simile. What Leopold glosses as an "alimentary image" is in fact a
bird's "hunger" for the sound of its own song in the act of cheering
itself (and others) up.
Leopold abuses the same passage again (p. xxxi) when he attempts, in
effect, to have Stirner condemn his own writing by taking a quotation
out of context:
As Stirner's own meiotic prediction has it: 'very few' of us will 'draw
joy' (p. 263) from this picture. [Ibidem, xxxi]
Is this a fair representation of Stirner's opinion of his own work as an
author on page 263? No, it is not; on that page, Stirner specifically
describes himself as comparable to a singing bird in imparting joy to
others (as shown above) without having any obligation toward his
audience. His separate statement that 'very few will draw joy from it'
is put forth in direct contrast to the Catholic Church's medieval policy
of 'withholding the Bible from the laity' so that the ignorant bliss of
the masses would not be troubled by its details. In the passage quoted
by Leopold, Stirner is asserting that his writing will trouble the bliss
of the ignorant, but (like the bird that is compelled to sing) he feels
he must "scatter" his thoughts even if they "deprive you of your rest
and sleep" (p. 263).
In the passage quoted, Stirner is definitely not conceding that his
vision is so "bleak" that few can enjoy it; he is rather making an
argument (sustained throughout the book, e.g., p. 127, 132, 309-12) that
the correct attitude of the intellectual (or "critic") is to proceed
with an open mind, and an open heart, not with the intention of
protecting his audience from truths too terrible to tell. Specifically,
in this passage, the emphasis is on writing without any preconceptions
(viz., including such vague assumptions as what "the public good" might
be), and without any sense of obligation to nationality, religion, or
broader abstractions such as humanity, truth and justice. All such
obligations, Stirner argues, entail prejudice, even when these
obligations are represented as a kind of enthusiasm, passion, or love
(e.g., censorship "out of love for the Church", "...for the Nation",
etc.).
Although any such obligation may be portrayed as a form of love,
Stirner's assertion is that "because preconceived, it is a prejudice"
(p. 262). In terms closely comparable to the classical Skepticism of
Sextus Empiricus, Stirner directs us to examine the criterion of truth
that underlies our arguments as an unexamined proposition; this "first
presupposition" perverts true philosophy (glossed as "discovery", and
elsewhere as "self-discovery") into mere dogmatism (p. 309). Stirner
maintains that love, too, can be subverted by "dogmatism", viz.,
sentiments that philosophers have so much praised, such as the love for
humanity in general, and the love for truth, Stirner criticizes as
"narrow" feelings compared to the open-minded impulse of one who loves
from the free play of the passions (here posed as parallel to the bird
singing from pure joy):
I do not limit myself to one feeling for men, but give free play to all
that I am capable of. [...] With this, I can keep myself open to every
impression without being torn away by one of them. I can love, love with
a full heart, and let the most consuming glow of passion burn in my
heart, without taking the beloved one for anything else than the
nourishment of my passion, on which it ever refreshes itself anew.
[Ibidem, p. 262]
In this quotation we find again that the "alimentary" imagery that
Leopold complains of is far from "bleak"; it simply posits the role of
the beloved as "fueling" the passion of lover (as akin to the audience
"fueling" the passion of the performer --Stirner describes both as
reciprocal relationships of "utility", and, thus, of "union").
It may be complained that Stirner is using needlessly cerebral (and
unfamiliar) terms in describing the singer's impulse to perform as "the
quiet hunger of egoism", or in speaking of the "nourishment" of passion.
Nevertheless, it is intellectually dishonest for Leopold to characterize
"the absence of obligations on the egoist" in negative terms by taking
Stirner's psychologically loaded vocabulary out of context, and
suggesting to the reader that the appearance of the word "use" means
that Stirner endorses the "instrumental treatment" (xxxi) of people, or
that Stirner is literally telling people they ought to regard
one-another as food (in the quote that Leopold has taken out of context
from page 263) when this is in fact an image employed in an argument
that people should spread joy to one-another without any feelings of
obligation, and moreover (in a separate but related argument) that
authors should write without dogmatic preconceptions.
Stirner's ethic is not revolutionary (he does not call for his reader to
rebel, as does Marx), nor is it one of enjoining a moral duty or
obligation upon the reader (as with Kant, Hegel, and so many others),
but he instead describes his own social and moral role as comparable to
a figure no more obscure to the Western tradition than Jesus Christ:
The time [in which Jesus lived] was politically so agitated that, as is
said in the gospels, people thought they could not accuse the founder of
Christianity more successfully than if they arraigned him for 'political
intrigue', and yet the same gospels report that he was precisely the one
who took the least part in these political doings. But why was he not a
revolutionary, not a demagogue, as the Jews would gladly have seen him?
[...] Because he expected no salvation from a change of conditions, and
this whole business was indifferent to him. He was not a revolutionary,
like Caesar, but an insurgent: not a state-overturner, but one who
straightened himself up. [...] [Jesus] was not carrying on any liberal
or political fight against the established authorities, but wanted to
walk his own way, untroubled about, and undisturbed by, these
authorities. [...] But, even though not a ringleader of popular mutiny,
not a demagogue or revolutionary, he (and every one of the ancient
Christians) was so much the more an insurgent who lifted himself above
everything that seemed so sublime to the government and its opponents,
and absolved himself from everything that they remained bound to [...];
precisely because he put from him the upsetting of the established, he
was its deadly enemy and real annihilator... [Ibidem p. 280-1]
As Stirner specifies in a footnote (p. 280), he here uses the word
insurgent "in its etymological sense"; thus, "to rise above" the
religion and government of one's own times by "straightening oneself up"
is contrasted to the method of the revolutionary who merely brings about
a "change of conditions" by displacing one government with another:
The revolution aimed at new arrangements; insurrection leads us no
longer to let ourselves be arranged, but to arrange ourselves, and sets
no glittering hopes on 'institutions'. It is not a fight against the
established [...] it is only a working forth of me out of the
established. [...] Now, as my object is not an overthrow of the
established order but my elevation above it, my purpose and deed are not
political or social but (as directed toward myself and my ownness alone)
an egoistic purpose indeed. [Ibidem, p. 280]
It is hardly necessary reiterate that Stirner is using the language of
ethical philosophy to direct the reader to pursue his or her own
"upliftment" --both that they might liberate themselves from their own
"limits" (elsewhere given a more detailed epistemological definition),
and also that they might "rise above" limiting social, political and
ideological conditions, and each walk their "own way". An attentive
reader can also gathered a working definition of Stirner's sense of the
term "egoistic" from the quotes provided above; the egoism that Stirner
endorses is quite simply setting aside any interest in the social order
to seek out one's own liberation --but, at the same time, serving to
benefit others by demonstrating "the way and the means". The passages
quoted above are clearly incompatable with Leopold's conclusion (in his
introduction to the Cambridge edition) that Stirner "...saw humankind as
'fretted in dark superstition' but denied that he sought their
enlightenment and welfare" (Ibidem, p. xxxii). Although it is
technically true that Stirner refuses to describe himself as directly
liberating others, his stated purpose these quotations is precisely to
achieve the "enlightenment and welfare" of others by way of
demonstration --and "insurrection" as he defines it.
The passages quoted above seem to exhaust the few points of contact
between Stirner's philosophy and early Christianity. It is merely Jesus
as an "annihilator" of the established biases and preconceptions of Rome
that Stirner can relate to --he has nothing but scorn for Christianity
as the basis of a new dogmatism that was to ossify soon thereafter. His
reason for "citing" the cultural change sparked by Jesus, is
(explicitly) that he wants the Christian ideologies of 19th century
Europe to collapse, much as the ideology of heathen Rome did before it
(e.g., "[the Christian era] will end with the casting off of the ideal,
with 'contempt for the spirit'", p. 320). As with the classical Skeptics
before him, Stirner's method of self-liberation is expressly opposed to
faith or belief in the broadest possible sense of the term; he envisions
a life free from "dogmatic presuppositions" (p. 135, 309) or any "fixed
standpoint" (p. 295). It is not merely Christian dogma that his
epistemology would repudiate, but also a wide variety of European
ideologies that are effectively condemned as crypto-Christian for
putting hypostatized ideas in an equivalent, injuntive role:
Among many transformations, the Holy Spirit became in time the 'absolute
idea' [in Hegelian philosophy], which again in manifold refractions
split into the different ideas of philanthropy, reasonableness, civic
virtue, and so on. [...] Antiquity, at its close, had gained its
ownership of the world only when it had broken the world's
overpoweringness and 'divinity', recognised the world's powerlessness
and 'vanity'. [...] [The philosophers of our time say] Concepts are to
decide everywhere, concepts to regulate life, concepts to rule. This is
the religious world [of our time], to which Hegel gave a systematic
expression, bringing method into the nonsense and completing the
conceptual precepts into a rounded, firmly-based dogmatic. Everything is
sung according to concepts and the real man, I, am compelled to live
according to these conceptual laws. [...] Liberalism simply brought
other concepts on the carpet; human instead of divine, political instead
of ecclesiastical, 'scientific' instead of doctrinal, or, more
generally, real concepts and eternal laws instead of 'crude dogmas' and
precepts. [Ibidem, p. 87-8]
The thinker is distinguished from the believer only by believing much
more than the latter, who, on his part, thinks of much less as signified
by his faith (creed). The thinker has a thousand tenets of faith where
the believer gets along with few; but the the former brings coherence
into his tenets, and take the coherence in turn for the scale to
estimate their worth by. p. 304
What Stirner proposes is a radical alternative to dispense with
dogmatism, root and branch; it is not that concepts should rule people,
but that people should rule concepts. The "nothingness" of all truth is
rooted in the "nothingness" of the self, because the ego is the
criterion of (dogmatic) truth. Again, Stirner seems closely comparable
to the Skeptics in that his radical epistemology directs us to emphasise
empirical experience (the "unmediated" relationship of mind as world,
and world as mind) but leaves only a very limited validity to the
category of "truth". When we regard the impressions of the senses with
detachment, simply for what they are (e.g., neither good nor evil), we
may still correctly assign truth to them, with the conscious awareness
that our own desire is (in effect) the criterion of truth:
Christianity took away from the things of this world only their
irresistibleness [...]. In like manner I raise myself above truths and
their power: as I am above the sensual, so I am above the truth. Before
me truths are as common and as indifferent as things; they do not carry
me away, and do not inspire me with enthusiasm. There exists not even
one truth, not right, not freedom, humanity, etc., that has stability
before me, and to which I subject myself. [...] In words and truths
[...] there is no salvation for me, as little as there is for the
Christian in things and vanities. As the riches of this world do not
make me happy, so neither do its truths. [...] Along with worldly goods,
all sacred goods too must be put away as no longer valuable. (p. 307)
Truths are material, like vegetables and weeds; as to whether vegetable
or weed, the decision lies in me. (p. 313)
In place of such systems of beliefs, Stirner presents a detached life of
non-dogmatic, open-minded engagement with the world "as it is"
(unmediated by such hypostatizations, unpolluted by "presupposed truth"
of any kind), coupled with the awareness that there is no soul, no
personal essence of any kind, but that the individual's unqiueness
consists precisely in its "creative nothingness" prior to all concepts.
'Power' is of central importance for Stirner, and can best be described
as a form of mental creativity, represented as the key to psychological
and social possibility of radical change. Stirner counterposes his
notion of "power" to the liberal discourse on social rights that was
ongoing in his contemporaneous Europe:
The polemic against privilege is a characteristic feature of liberalism,
which fumes against "privilege" because it [instead] appeals to "right".
But it cannot carry the matter any further than this fuming; privileges
do not fall before right, because they are merely forms of right. Right
falls apart into nothingness when it is entwined with might, e.g., when
one understands what is meant by "might goes before right" [i.e., that
"right" is established by force]. [_The Ego and its Own_, Cambrdige
Edition, p. 229, translation amended by E.M.]
In Stirner's sense power, also referred to as the acquisition of
'property', has a broad meaning, ranging from the smile of the child,
that acquires its mothers' love, over the sensual and material pleasures
and meanings of taking what one desires, to the wholesale attribution of
meaning, value and existence in language and life. Power in this sense
is synonymous with the dynamics of utter autonomy, and the ability of
change, of existence, of life itself.
Stirner's critique of Hegel shows a profound awareness of Hegel's work,
and, argued by scholars such as Karl Löwith and Lawrence Stepelevich,
suggests a vital influence of Hegel's thinking, in Stirner's
intellectual development and line of thinking -- even if Stirner's
mature philosophy may comprise a thorough repudiation of Hegelianism, in
form as well as content.
Stirner employs some of the most important elements of Hegelian
structure and many of Hegel's basic presuppositions to arrive at his
conclusions. Stepelevich argues, that while The Ego and his own
evidently has an "un-Hegelian structure and tone to the work as a
whole", as well as being fundamentally hostile to Hegel's conclusions
about the self and the world, this does not mean that Hegel and Stirner
are not related on the most intimate level.
The main juncture leading from Hegel to Stirner is found [in The
Phenomenology of the Spirit] at the termination of a phenomenological
passage to absolute knowledge. Stirner's work is most clearly understood
when it is taken to be the answer to the question, 'what role will
consciousness play after it has traversed the series of shapes known as
'untrue' knowledge and has attained to absolute knowledge?
— Lawrence Stepelevich, 'Max Stirner as Hegelian, Journal of the History
of Ideas, v.15, pp. 597-614 (1985).
In other words, to go beyond Hegel in true dialectical fashion is to
continue Hegel's project, and Stepelevich argues persuasively that this
effort of Stirner's is, in fact a completion of Hegel's project.
Stepelevich concludes his argument referring to Jean Hyppolite, who in
summing up the intention of the Phenomenology, stated : "The history of
the world is finished; all that is needed is for the specific individual
to rediscover it in himself."
Stirner as an Einziger took himself directly to be that 'specific
individual' and then went on as a Hegelian to propose the practical
consequence which would ultimately follow upon that theoretical
rediscovery, the free play of self-consciousness among the objects of
its own determination: "The idols exist through me; I need only refrain
from creating them anew, then they exist no longer: 'higher powers'
exist only through my exalting them and abasing myself.... My
intercourse with the world consists in my enjoying it, and so consuming
it for my self-enjoyment" (Ego, 319)
— Lawrence Stepelevich, 'Max Stirner as Hegelian'
Opinions among scholars have been strongly divided as to how the terms
"racism" and "racialism" apply to Stirner's oeuvre. Those who reject the
accusation that Stirner was a racist can point to Stirner's protacted
(and consistent) opposition to bigotry and nationalism of any kind, and
his many passages attacking the racism of Germans as narrow-minded
"tribalism" and "Teutonomania". However, for many modern readers,
Stirner's use of the (now odious) 19th century racial categories
"Mongoloid" and "Negro" constitute powerful prima facie evidence, and
may cause them to ignore his direct arguments against racist
nationalism.
Stirner's central argument (or "method") on the question of racial
identity hinges on his assertion that ethnicity is an illusory and
invidious notion (variously exploited by nationalism, liberalism, and
the Church in his contemporary Germany) and that can be broken by the
uniqeness (and "nothingness") of the ego. With the latter breaking of
the illusion a free intercourse between people of different ethnicities
is supposed to ensue; this seems to work from a cosmopolitan or
"multi-cultural" assumption wherein each distinct ethnicity or religion
should "assert [its] distinctness or peculiarity: you need not give way
or renounce yourself [viz., your ethnic identity]" (p. 185). This is a
striking contrast to the widespread presumption of the time that ethnic
minorities in Europe were obliged to assimilate or else depart. Stirner
excoriates the presumption that ethnic divisions can be "dissolved" by
the forced imposition of a nationalistic identity, and similarly rejects
the liberal claims that the issue will disappear if only state power
would provide "equal rights" to all:
The "equality of right" is a phantom ... people dream of "all citizens
of the state having to stand side by side, with equal rights". As
citizens of the state they are certainly all equal for the state. But it
will divide them, and advance them or put them in the rear, according to
its special ends, if on no other account... People conceive of the
significance of the opposition [between ethnicities] too formally and
weakly when they want only to 'dissolve' it in order to make room for a
third thing that shall 'unite'. The opposition deserves rather to be
sharpened. [...] Our weakness consists not in this, that we are in
opposition to others, but in this, that we are not completely so; that
we are not entirely severed from them, that we still seek a "Communion",
a "Bond", that in communion we have an ideal. One faith, one god, one
idea, one hat, for all! If all were brought under one hat, certainly no
one would need to take off his hat for another anymore. The last and
most decided opposition, that of unique against unique, is fundamentally
beyond what is called opposition, but without having sunk back into
"unity" and unison. As unique you no longer have anything in common with
the other, and therefore nothing divisive or hostile either; you are not
seeking to be in the right before a third party [viz., god, the state,
etc.], and are standing with [others] neither on "the basis of right"
nor on any other common ground. The opposition vanishes in complete
severance or singleness. This might be regarded as the new point in
common, or as a new parity, but here the parity consists precisely in
the disparity, an eqality of disparity, and [even] that [distinction
arises] only for him who poses the two in "comparison". [p. 184-186]
Unfortunately, David Leopold has badly misinterpreted one of the most
inflammatory passages (dealing with race) in his introduction to the
Cambridge edition (op. cit. supra). The passage appears as a
non-sequitor ("episodically", in Leopold's terms) from pg. 62-65, and
certainly does employ offensive racial terms, but, significantly, these
terms are employed to ridicule the (then mainstream) European
conceptions of their own history and ethnic heritage.
The passage in question begins [p. 62-3] by claiming that the period
Western scholars commonly refer to as "European antiquity" (viz.,
classical Greece and Rome) should instead be termed "the Negroid age",
viz., the period in which "Egypt and... northern Afica in general" are
culturally predominant over Europe. Leopold's assessment seems to ignore
the fact that this passage is not intended to insult black people, but
is rather a pointed attempt to upset the (historically false, but still
prevalent) European assumptions that paint modern racial prejudices onto
ancient history, e.g., claiming that the Athenians, or even the
Egyptians, were in some sense "Europeans" or ethnically "Caucasian",
whereas the Hittites, and adjacent peoples of Asia Minor, etc., are
presumed to be "non-white" enemies in this apocryphal racialization of
bronze age history. Against this miasma of racial prejudices, Stirner
brashly asserts that these ancient peoples were all "Negro", including
the (much mythified) Athenian Greeks and Romans. He briefly expands on
this to say that all of classical "Euroepan" philosophy is in fact
African in character, a clear attempt to lampoon the historicist
racialism of authors such as Hegel. His next assertion is that currently
(viz., in the 19th century) Europeans are ethnically Mongoloid, not
Caucasian: they follow a Mongolian religion, are worshipping a Mongolian
god, and have the same social ideals as those of dynastic China. Thus,
while European Christians imagine themselves to be superior to Asian
idolators, Stirner asserts that Europeans have merely "wrestled for
thousands of years with [the same] spiritual beings" as the Chinese, and
still dream of going to "the Mongolian heaven, Tien", after they die.
[p. 64] As with the first phase of the argument, it is clear that
Stirner is not using these terms to insult Asians, but is throwing the
established (Eurocentric) preconceptions of history back upon Europeans,
and juding them to be (in their own racist terms) merely "Mongoloid" in
their beliefs. [p. 63-5]
Although the passage is likely to be offensive to members of any
religion (or almost any ethnicity) it is also noteworthy that Stirner
here asserts that the dynastic empire of Confucian China is a more
advanced civilization than that of Europe, but, from his perspective,
this advancement is in precisely the wrong direction, viz., toward
hierarchy, patriarchy, and the repression of the individual by
obligation and law. For those who have studied Hegel's Philosophy of
History, Stirner seems to have included a direct inversion of the
Hegelian conception of freedom (based as it was upon a racist historical
dialectic, and the glorification of law and obligation as the
precondition of "freedom of the spirit"):
To want to win freedom for the spirit is Mongolism; freedom of the
spirit is Mongolian freedom, freedom of feeling, moral freedom, and so
forth.
Effectively, Stirner is here saying that what Germans imagine to be the
"new" philosophy of freedom (according to Hegel, a philosophy exclusive
to their race, and to their time) is really just a throwback to an
ancient and repressive notion that was already prevalent in classical
China (or "Mongoldom" as Stirner styles it).
Certainly, it is no accident that the passage in question is extremely
offensive; most modern readers will likely feel insulted by it, or by
the (now antiquated) terms it employs. Stirner clearly lacked any
detailed understanding of classical Chinese civilization, and simply
employs a limited sketch of its repressive, hierarchical elements as
part of a reproach against European civilization in his own times. The
primary purpose of the passage seems to be to upset the long-standing
conceits of European pre-eminence, and it does not establish a racialist
historiography of its own. What Leopold and other critics seem to have
failed to understand is that what Stirner dubbs climbing "the ladder of
culture, or civilization" [p. 64] is not a process that he seeks to
glorify (as Hegel and so many others did), but rather to repudiate;
thus, it is not inconsistent that Stirner identifies the culture of
Confucian China with greater advancement and yet, at the same time,
considers it abhorrent. In this passage "Civilization" is glossed as the
subordination of the individual and the world to the rule of "the
hierarchy of the spirit", viz., the inculcation of "habit, or second
nature", and the proliferation of "principles" and "laws" on the basis
of the enjoined obligations of man to "heaven". [p. 64] Thus, only at
the conclusion of the passage does Stirner define what he means by the
term "Mongolism", viz., "[the] utter absence of any rights of the
sensuous, [it] represents non-sensuousness and unnature...". [p. 65] In
some respects, this critique of civilization and culture (as such) seems
to anticipate much later thinkers such as John Zerzan.
Stirner's work did not go unnoticed among his colleagues, the Young
Hegelians. Stirner's attacks on ideology, in particular Feuerbach's
humanism, forced Feuerbach into print. Moses Hess (at that time close to
Marx) and Szeliga (an adherent of Bruno Bauer) also replied to Stirner.
Stirner answered the criticism in a German periodical, in the article
Stirner's Critics (org. Recensenten Stirners, Sept 1845), which
clarifies several points of interest to readers of the book - especially
in relation to Feuerbach.
To begin with, Engels was spontaneously enthusiastic about the book, and
expressed his opinions freely in a letter to Marx. Later, Marx wrote a
histrionic indictment of Stirner, co-authored with Engels, spanning
several hundred pages (in the original, unexpurgated text) of his book
The German Ideology (org. Die deutsche Ideologie). The book was written
in 1845 - 1846, but not published until 1932. Marx's lengthy, ferocious
polemic against Stirner has since been considered an important turning
point in Marx's intellectual development from "idealism" to
"materialism".
While The German Ideology so assured The Ego and Its Own a place of
curious interest among Marxist readers, Marx's ridicule of Stirner has
played a significant role in the subsequent marginalization of Stirner's
work, in popular and academic discourse.
Over the course of the last hundred and fifty years, Stirner's thinking
has proved an intellectual challenge, reminiscent of the challenge
Cartesian criticism brought to western philosophy. His philosophy has
been characterized as disturbing, sometimes even considered a direct
threat to civilization; something that ought not even be mentioned in
polite company, and that should be, if encountered by some unfortunate
happenstance, examined as briefly as possible and then best forgotten.
Stirner's relentlessness in the service of scuttling the most
tenaciously held tenets of the Western mindset yields a terrain which
bears testimony to the radical threat he posed; most writers who read
and were influenced by Stirner failed to make any references to him or
The Ego and Its Own at all in their writing. As the renowned art critic
Herbert Read has observed, Stirner's book has remained 'stuck in the
gizzard' of Western culture since it first appeared.
It has been argued that Nietzsche did read Stirner's book, yet even he
did not mention Stirner anywhere in his work, his letters, or his
papers. Nietzsche's thinking sometimes resembles Stirner's to such a
degree that Eduard von Hartmann called him a plagiarist. This seems too
simple an explanation of what Nietzsche might have done with Stirner's
ideas. Stirner's book had been in oblivion for half a century, and only
after Nietzsche became well-known in the 1890s did Stirner become more
well-known, although only as an awkward predecessor of Nietzsche. Thus
Nietzsche - as with Marx's concept of historical materialism in
1845/46 - did not really plagiarize Stirner but instead "superseded" him
by creating a philosophy.
Several other authors, philosophers and artists have cited, quoted or
otherwise referred to Max Stirner. They include Albert Camus (In The
Rebel), Benjamin Tucker, Dora Marsden, Georg Brandes, Rudolf Steiner,
Robert Anton Wilson, Italian individualist anarchist Frank Brand, the
notorious antiartist Marcel Duchamp, several writers of the situationist
movement, and Max Ernst, who titled a 1925 painting L'unique et sa
propriété. The Italian dictator Benito Mussolini read and was inspired
by Stirner, and made several references to him in his newspaper
articles, prior to rising to power. His later writings would uphold a
view opposed to Stirner, a trajectory mirrored by the composer Richard
Wagner.
Since its appearance in 1844, The Ego and Its Own has seen periodic
revivals of popular, political and academic interest, based around
widely divergent translations and interpretations -- some psychological,
others political in their emphasis. Today, many ideas associated with
post-left anarchy criticism of ideology and uncompromising
individualism - are clearly related to Stirner's. He has also been
regarded as pioneering individualist feminism, since his objection to
any absolute concept also clearly counts gender roles as 'spooks'. His
ideas were also adopted by post-anarchism, with Saul Newman largely in
agreement with many of Stirner's criticisms of classical anarchism,
including his rejection of revolution and essentialism.
Stirner's demolition of absolute concepts disturbs traditional concepts
of attribution of meaning to language and human existence, and can be
seen as pioneering a modern media theory which focuses on dynamic
conceptions of language and reality, in contrast to reality as subject
to any absolute definition. Jean Baudrillard's critique of Marxism and
development of a dynamic theory of media, simulation and 'the real'
employs some of the same elements Stirner used in his Hegelian critique
without, however, making recourse to very much that lies at the heart of
the plumb-line libertarian core of Stirner's philosophy. Though many in
the poststructuralist camp have championed Stirner's thought, the core
tenets of these two entities are wholly incompatible; Stirner would
never agree, for example, with that fundamental poststructuralist idea,
that as a product of systems, the self is undermined. For Stirner, the
self cannot be a mere product of systems. There remains, in the
Stirnerian schema, as described in the above, a place deep within the
self which language and social systems cannot destroy. This idea finds
expression, perhaps, in a concept put forward by the contemporary
philosopher Julia Kristeva; the 'semiotic chora', as she calls it,
represents a state of mind which predates the inculcation of the social
apparatus in the mind of the young child.
Twenty years after the appearance of Stirner's book, the author
Friedrich Albert Lange wrote the following:
Stirner went so far in his notorious work, 'Der Einzige und Sein
Eigenthum' (1845), as to reject all moral ideas. Everything that in any
way, whether it be external force, belief, or mere idea, places itself
above the individual and his caprice, Stirner rejects as a hateful
limitation of himself. What a pity that to this book -- the extremest
that we know anywhere -- a second positive part was not added. It would
have been easier than in the case of Schelling's philosophy; for out of
the unlimited Ego I can again beget every kind of Idealism as my will
and my idea. Stirner lays so much stress upon the will, in fact, that it
appears as the root force of human nature. It may remind us of
Schopenhauer
— History of Materialism, ii. 256
"The great are great only because we are on our knees. Let us rise!"
"The truth wears longer than all the gods; for it is only in the truth's
service, and for love of it, that people have overthrown the gods and at
last God himself. "The truth" outlasts the downfall of the world of
gods, for it is the immortal soul of this transitory world of gods; it
is Deity itself."
"Before what is sacred, people lose all sense of power and all
confidence; they occupy a powerless and humble attitude toward it. And
yet no thing is sacred of itself, but by my declaring it sacred, by my
declaration, my judgment, my bending the knee; in short, by my
conscience."
"The State calls its own violence law, but that of the individual
crime."