đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș anarqxista-goldman-anarchism-for-free-spirits.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:02:38. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Anarchism for Free Spirits Author: Anarqxista Goldman Date: 2022 Language: en Topics: egoism, Renzo Novatore, Friedrich Nietzsche Source: Retrieved on 11th July 2022 from https://archive.org/details/anarchism-for-free-spirits Notes: This is chapter 7 of the authorâs larger text Nothing to Stick to: Anarchism for Free Spirits.
The history of anarchism is strewn with labels and with denominations of
âwhat kindâ of anarchist somebody is or was. If one studies the history
of anarchism as, in writing my various books on the subject, has been
necessitated, you find that this labelling didnât really take very long
to become apparent and, furthermore, to become problematic, a source of
internal anarchist division. So problematic was it, in fact, that
anarchists started appearing who refused to be denominated at all â and
so, of course, they came to form a separate grouping, the âanarchists
without adjectivesâ.
Perhaps this was a product of the times. Whatever its cause, I find it
facile and banal. At least a couple of these groupings, the communist
anarchists [Bakunin, Kropotkin, Malatesta] and the individualist
anarchists of America [Benjamin Tucker, James L. Walker], were groupings
based on an economic theory of organisation [as were the Marxists and
Socialists more generally, of course]. But why should one need an
economic theory to be an anarchist [not an original question] and why
would economic theories be what decided which group you were in and
become that about you which made you an identifiable kind of anarchist?
We can only assume that the reason is a historically contingent one. In
the 19^(th) century the Western World become a place absolutely driven
by capitalism and this economic cancer was the be all and end all of the
new ability to pursue industrial activity. No wonder, then, that the
reaction was economically-based too. [Voltairine de Cleyre, an anarchist
without adjectives, also raises this point.]
Yet I have always taken a wider view on things than this and refused to
be sucked into an entirely economic view of the world or to concede that
economics, as the world presented it to me in capitalist terms, was the
really important thing about the world. I frankly do not care about
money or property or capital and this probably contributes a lot to why
I find Proudhon boring [as well as the American offshoot of anarchism
that is identified with Tuckerâs individualistic âcapitalism for
everyoneâ which, in the modern day, empties out into the nonsense of
Murray Rothbard and the idiocy of âanarcho-capitalismâ, a place where
NFTs and crypto-currencies are meant to be the height of anarchistic
endeavour] and Karl Marx the most irrelevant man who ever lived. This,
of course, has its own consequences for me as I try to make sense of the
world â for a world without these things, or with their importance
vastly reduced, presents challenges where they are veritable gods for
most other people. Yet this is also where, for me, anarchism becomes
exactly a relevant matter. But it must be said that even the word
âanarchismâ has lately become a questionable term for me for, in its
lengthening history, it has itself become a misunderstood and,
sometimes, largely worthless term.
What then is âan anarchistâ? Why its a person who hates the government
and posts memes to that effect on Twitter or Reddit â perhaps even
Mastodon â isnât it? No, in the olden days it was someone who bombed
things and tried to kill presidents, tsars, prime ministers or cops,
someone like that. No, youâre wrong again, Iâm afraid. Today an
anarchist is someone who messes with computers â like Anonymous â in
order to embarrass the rich by exposing their dirty secrets. Then again,
perhaps an anarchist is someone who waves a black flag at a
demonstration or spray paints large âAâ symbols inside circles on
buildings? Nope, not quite right. An anarchist is someone who likes punk
music and is covered in piercings and tattoos and who likes wearing
black leather. You see what I mean? There is no simple way to describe
what an anarchist is or, rather, what I would mean if I used the term
âanarchistâ of myself. It is one of those words which has been bent
completely out of shape by public usage [and often, it must be admitted,
by its enemies] until even using the word becomes an exercise in having
to explain what you think it means and where it comes from. And language
starts to fall apart when it works like this because language shouldnât
be about having to explain what words mean by the additional provision
of descriptions and histories and examples; it should be about their
common and useful understanding.
This is exampled in a historical fiction that was popular among
anarchists at the turn of the 20^(th) century. It was written by the
German anarchist, John Henry Mackay, a disciple of Benjamin Tucker and
the primary propagandist for Max Stirnerâs The Unique and Its Property
who also wrote poetry as well [some of which is included in Emma
Goldmanâs Anarchism and Other Essays]. The fiction was called The
Anarchists: A Picture of Civilization at the Close of the Nineteenth
Century and it was only semi-fictional since the plot, to the extent
that the book has one, isnât much of a plot at all. The book is set
among the anarchists and what today would be called âleftistsâ of
poverty-stricken London in the mid to late 1880s and is historically
based on Mackayâs own time there. The book functions as a way for
various figures, but mainly two â Carrard Auban and Otto Trupp â to
discuss their anarchist differences against the background of a squalid
London where disfigured women offer their teenage daughters for sex
favours in order to earn a few shillings and most other people will do
pretty much anything and everything to survive. This background acts to
necessitate the arguments of the anarchists in the book to provide
meaningful solutions to such social realities.
As I say, the two main players in the book are Auban [likely a stand in
for the author Mackay himself since this is the most fleshed out and
vivid character] and Trupp [who a number of commentators have said is
meant to be a fictional version of Johann Most who was for a time in
London before he went to New York, became the leader of the Freiheit
community there and became the mentor of Emma Goldman as well]. Auban
and Trupp are sharply distinguished in the text, the former offering a
post-Proudhonian economic individualism of the kind then being proposed
by Benjamin Tucker with Trupp being presented as a communist anarchist.
This, for instance, is an example of Aubanâs internal monologue from the
book:
âHe now saw what it was that Proudhon had meant by property: not the
product of labor, which he had always defended against Communism, but
the legal privileges of that product as they weigh upon labor in the
forms of usury, principally as interest and rent, and obstruct its free
circulation; that with Proudhon equality was nothing but equality of
rights, and fraternity not self-sacrifice, but prudent recognition of
oneâs own interests in the light of mutualism; that he championed
voluntary association for a definite purpose in opposition to the
compulsory association of the State, âto maintain equality in the means
of production and equivalence in exchangeâ as âthe only possible, the
only just, the only true form of society.â
Auban now saw the distinction Proudhon made between possession and
property. âPossession is a right; property is against right.â Your labor
is your rightful possession, its product your capital; but the power of
increase of this capital, the monopoly of its power of increase, is
against right. âLa propriĂ©tĂ©, câest le vol!â [âproperty is theftâ]. Thus
he recognized the true causes of the terrible differences in the
distribution of weapons of which nature knows nothing when it places us
on the battleground of life; how it happens that some are condemned to
pass a life of trouble and toil and hopelessness within the limits
unalterably fixed by the âiron law of wages,â while the others, removed
from competition, throw out playfully, as it were, the magnet of their
capital, to attract whatever of foreign labor products fall within its
field, and so steadily add to their wealth, â all that he now saw
clearly under the light of this examination. He saw that the minority of
the latter were in a position, by the aid of anciently received
opinions, to coerce the majority into a recognition of their privileges.
He saw that it was the nature of the State which enabled that minority
to keep a portion of the people in ignorance concerning their interests,
and to prevent by force the others who had recognized them from pursuing
them.
He saw consequently â and this was the most important and incisive
perception of his life, which revolutionized the entire world of his
opinions â that the one thing needful was, not to champion the creed of
self-sacrifice and duty, but rather egoism, the perception of oneâs own
interests! If there was a âsolution of the social question,â it lay
here. All else was Utopia or slavery in some form.â
A distinctive about Auban in the book, perhaps inspired by the
historical Marx/Bakunin split in the First International in 1872 and
perhaps not, is that communists cannot be anarchists for him. An
interlocutor tells him that all the anarchists he has ever heard of are
communists to which Auban replies that they are communists who call
themselves anarchists yet, so the reader understands, without, in his
mind, really being so. Auban takes the view that âevery consistent
individualistâ [by which he means the Proudhonian, Tuckerite, edging
towards Stirnerite figure just described] is an anarchist. When further
asked what he âunderstands by Anarchyâ, Auban replies with the
following:
âYou know that the word An-archy, is derived from the Greek language,
and means, in literal rendering, âno authority.â Now the condition of no
authority is identical with the condition of liberty: if I have no
master, I am free. Anarchy is consequently liberty. It is now necessary
to define the conception âliberty,â and I must say that it is impossible
for me to find a better definition than this one: liberty is the absence
of aggressive force or coercionâŠ
Now, the State is organized force. As force constitutes its essential
nature, robbery is its privilege; so the robbery of some for the benefit
of others is the means of its support. The Anarchist sees therefore in
the State his greatest, yes, his only, enemy. It is the fundamental
condition of liberty that no one shall be deprived of the opportunity of
securing the full product of his labor. Economic independence is
consequently the first demand of Anarchism: the abolition of the
exploitation of man by man. That exploitation is made impossible: by the
freedom of banking, i.e. liberty in the matter of furnishing a medium of
exchange free from the legal burden of interest; by the freedom of
credit, i.e. the organization of credit on the basis of the principle of
mutualism, of economic solidarity; by the freedom of home and foreign
trade, i.e. liberty of unhindered exchange of values from hand to hand
as from land to land; the freedom of land, i.e. liberty in the
occupation of land for the purpose of personal use, if it is not already
occupied by others for the same purpose; or, to epitomize all these
demands: the exploitation of man by man is made impossible by the
freedom of laborâŠâ
Here Auban makes the, in modern context, startling claim that his sort
of anarchist wants âto make it possible for everyone to become a
capitalist, by making it accessible to all by means of the freedom of
credit and by forcing it to enter competition, like all other products.â
The basis for this is Aubanâs belief that âthe social question cannot be
solved in any other way than by the initiative of the individual who
finally resolves to assume the administration of his affairs himself
instead of placing it in the hands of others.â Pushed further, Auban
says, âI claim the right of free control over my person⊠I neither
demand nor expect of the community a bestowal of rights, and I consider
myself under no obligations to it. Put in place of the word âcommunityâ
whatever you wish: âState,â âsociety,â âfatherland,â âcommonwealth,â
âmankind,â â it is all the same.â He continues: âI deny all human
institutions which are founded on the right of force. I am of greater
importance to myself than they are to me!â in a way that sounds like
echoes of Max Stirner and adds even further that he does not believe in
âthe progress of mankind towards liberty.â Later on, when a formal
discussion under the heading âWhat is Anarchism?â has commenced at
Aubanâs place with Trupp and some others, Auban adds that âthe question
of Anarchism is not the concern of a single class, consequently also not
of the laboring class, but it is the concern of every individual who
values his personal liberty.â Aubanâs anarchism is then of a form which
has definitely separated itself from any vestiges of Socialism [which
the text makes clear in that âthe best that Socialism might achieve
would⊠constitute only a change of rulersâ].
In response to such ideas, Trupp attempts to defend his communist corner
[although, I must say, given the author is the Proudhonian Stirnerite
John Henry Mackay, this isnât really presented as a fair fight]. Truppâs
rhetoric is about âthe workingmanâ and âthe real proletariatâ. He
disdains that âa few middle-class liberals have invented a new
Anarchismâ which matters not a jot either to working men or to that
proletariat at all. He then adds:
âIf the comrades wish to know what this Anarchism wants, which has risen
in opposition to the State Communists, I will gladly tell them in a few
words. Above all, we do not see in the individual a being separate from
society, but we regard him as the product of this very society from
which he derives all he is and has. Consequently, he can only return,
even if in a different form, what in the first place he received from
it. For this reason, too, he cannot say: this and that belong to me
alone. There can be no private property, but everything that has been
and is being produced is social property, to which one has just as much
right as another, since each oneâs share in the production of wealth can
in no manner be determined. For this reason we proclaim the liberty to
consume, i.e. the right of each to satisfy his wants free and
unhindered. Consequently we are Communists.
But, on the other hand, we are also Anarchists. For we want a system of
society where each member can fully realize his own âself,â i.e. his
individual talents and abilities, wishes, and needs. Therefore we say:
Down with all government! Down with it even in the form of
administration. For administration always becomes government. We
likewise oppose the whole swindle of the suffrage and declare the
leaders who have presumed to place themselves at the head of the
workingmen as humbugs.
As Communists we say; â To each according to his needs! And as
Anarchists: â From each according to his powers. If Auban says such an
ideal is impossible, I answer him that he does not yet know the
workingmen, although he might know them, for he has associated with them
long enough. The workingmen are not such sordid egoists as the bourgeois
â after they have had their day of reckoning with them, after the last
revolution has been fought, they will very well know how to arrange
things. I believe that after the expropriation of the exploiters and the
confiscation of the bank, they will place everything at the disposal of
all. The deserted palaces will quickly enough find occupants, and the
well-stocked warehouses soon enough customers. We need not cudgel our
brains about that!
Then when each one shall be sufficiently supplied with food, clothing,
and shelter, when the hungry shall be fed and the naked clothed, â for
there is enough for all for the present, â they will form groups; will,
impelled by the instinct of activity, produce in common and consume
according to needs. The individual will at best receive more, never
less, from society than he has given it. For what should the stronger
who produces more than he can consume do with the excess of his labor
except give it to the weaker? And that is not liberty? They will not ask
how much or how little each produces and each consumes; no, each will
carry his finished work to the warehouses and take therefore in return
what he needs for his support. According to the principle of fraternity
ââ
Auban is not prepared to accept that this is âanarchismâ however and, in
a way that is detrimental to the story, in my view, Auban proceeds with
a speech which attempts to force Trupp to concede that communism is not
anarchism. To be sure, there are points here to be taken into
consideration but, from a literary point of view, the argument is a fake
one from the start and could have been better presented as either a
genuine debate [which this isnât because Mackay puts words in the mouths
of both sides] or as an analytical presentation of the various positions
with the authorâs cards on the table. Nevertheless, here is Aubanâs
argument against Truppâs anarchist communist position:
âYou want the autonomy of the individual, his sovereignty, and the right
of self-determination. You want the free development of his natural
stature. You want his liberty. We agree in this demand. But you have
formed an ideal of a future of happiness which corresponds most nearly
to your own inclinations, wishes, habits. By naming it âthe ideal of
humanityâ you are convinced that every âreal and true manâ must be just
as happy under it as you. You would fain make your ideal the ideal of
all.
I, on the contrary, want the liberty which will enable each to live
according to his ideal. I want to be let alone, I want to be spared from
any demands that may be made in the name of âthe ideal of humanity.â I
think that is a great difference. I deny only. You build anew. I am
purely defensive. But you are aggressive. I battle exclusively for my
liberty. You battle for what you call the liberty of others. Every other
word you speak is abolition. That means forcible destruction. It is also
my word. Only I mean by it: dissolution. You talk about the abolition of
religion. You want to banish its priests, extirpate its teachings,
persecute its followers. I trust to the steadily increasing perception
which puts knowledge in the place of faith. It is economic dependence
that forces most people nowadays into recognizing one of the many still
existing churches, and prevents them from leaving them. After the chains
of labor have fallen, the churches will of themselves become deserted,
the teachers of a delusive faith and folly will no longer find
listeners, and their priests will be forsaken.â
In the end, the difference here is, as Auban himself says, that he wants
the end of the State in order to facilitate the existence of property
[which the State suppresses] whilst Trupp wants the abolition of the
State in order to abolish property â a fundamentally opposed idea about
property and its place within an anarchist understanding and so a
quibble fundamentally about political economy. Auban wants everyone to
become âproprietorsâ whereas Trupp wants no one to be able to become
them. Auban believes in taking up, and fighting for, oneâs right,
whereas Trupp believes that âin the coming society each will perform his
share of labor voluntarilyâ and that:
âIn the future society, where everything will be at the free disposal of
all, where there can be no trade consequently in the present sense,
every member, I am deeply convinced, will voluntarily abandon all claim
to sole and exclusive occupation of land.â
The end of this argument is when Auban finally forces Trupp to say that
âIn Anarchy any number of men must have the right of forming a voluntary
association, and so realizing their ideas in practice. Nor can I
understand how any one could justly be driven from the land and house
which he uses and occupiesâ, a concession Auban imagines means an
ultimate giving up of Truppâs communist future vision and his conceding
that, ultimately, Auban himself has the right of it. But I must admit
that the whole argument, as Mackay presents it, leaves a bitter taste
and I recognise in neither Auban nor Trupp an anarchist FREE SPIRIT of
the type I am shortly to describe. In fact, discussing âANARCHISMâ in
such strictly politico-economic terms seems really boring to me â
although I concede others do so and it may be entirely historically
accurate to depict past anarchist discussions this way. Yet, from my
perspective, what we need is a strong sirocco wind to blow such cobwebs
away. We need FREE SPIRIT and we need it now.
The herald of FREE SPIRITS is Friedrich Nietzsche and this phrase first
gets an airing in his books in one of his Untimely Meditations â
âSchopenhauer as Educatorâ â where he refers to âthe free spirits and
those who suffer profoundly from our ageâ. This is also related to those
who have ârecognized the unreason in the nature of this ageâ. Yet it is
with his third book Human, All Too Human: A Book for Free Spirits [this
book was originally to be titled simply âThe Free Spiritâ] that
Nietzsche begins to properly make something out of this terminology and
give it meaning. So it is with this text that I will start in the
Nietzschean canon, working through his books to exegete what Nietzsche
means by a âfree spiritâ in order to later make the term of use in my
anarchist context.
A first clue is found in the preface, added in the spring of 1886, in
which Nietzsche now deigns to add a word or two about free spirits.
[Originally, there had been a short quotation from Descartes instead.]
Nietzsche tells us here that he invented âfree spiritsâ as companions to
keep him in good spirits âas brave companions and familiarsâ through
trying personal times. [Nietzsche had recently split from a close
friendship with Richard Wagner, spiritual, artistic and intellectual â
so close that Nietzsche had his own room in the Wagner house â and had
had to leave his academic post due to debilitating bouts of illness
which would eventually end his career.] These free spirits take on a
life of their own, however, and he begins to see them as âactive and
audacious fellowsâ among the sons of Europeâs tomorrow, fellows he
wishes to further speed into existence in his telling of them. First of
all, then, a free spirit is one who experiences a âgreat liberationâ
from previously experienced fetters of reverence to duties or traditions
that previously held them fast and from obligations that were thus
imagined. Here:
âThe great liberation comes for those who are thus fettered suddenly,
like the shock of an earthquake: the youthful soul is all at once
convulsed, torn loose, torn away â it itself does not know what is
happening. A drive and impulse rules and masters it like a command; a
will and desire awakens to go off, anywhere, at any cost; a vehement
dangerous curiosity for an undiscovered world flames and flickers in all
its senses. âBetter to die than to go on living hereâ â thus responds
the imperious voice and temptation: and this âhereâ, this âat homeâ is
everything it had hitherto loved! A sudden terror and suspicion of what
it loved, a lightning-bolt of contempt for what it called âdutyâ, a
rebellious, arbitrary, volcanically erupting desire for travel, strange
places, estrangements, coldness, soberness, frost, a hatred of love,
perhaps a desecrating blow and glance backwards to where it formerly
loved and worshipped, perhaps a hot blush of shame at what it has just
done and at the same time an exultation that it has done it, a drunken,
inwardly exultant shudder which betrays that a victory has been won â a
victory? over what? over whom? an enigmatic, question-packed,
questionable victory, but the first victory nonetheless: such bad and
painful things are part of the history of the great liberation. It is at
the same time a sickness that can destroy the man who has it, this first
outbreak of strength and will to self-determination, to evaluating on
oneâs own account, this will to free will: and how much sickness is
expressed in the wild experiments and singularities through which the
liberated prisoner now seeks to demonstrate his mastery over things! He
prowls cruelly around with an unslaked lasciviousness; what he captures
has to expiate the perilous tension of his pride; what excites him he
tears apart. With a wicked laugh he turns round whatever he finds veiled
and through some sense of shame or other spared and pampered: he puts to
the test what these things look like when they are reversed. It is an
act of willfulness, and pleasure in willfulness, if now he perhaps
bestows his favour on that which has hitherto had a bad reputation â if,
full of inquisitiveness and the desire to tempt and experiment, he
creeps around the things most forbidden. Behind all his toiling and
weaving â for he is restlessly and aimlessly on his way as if in a
desert â stands the question mark of a more and more perilous curiosity.
âCan all values not be turned round? and is good perhaps evil? and God
only an invention and finesse of the Devil? Is everything perhaps in the
last resort false? And if we are deceived, are we not for that very
reason also deceivers? must we not be deceivers?â â such thoughts as
these tempt him and lead him on, even further away, even further down.
Solitude encircles and embraces him, ever more threatening, suffocating,
heart-tightening, that terrible goddess and mater saeva cupidinum [wild
mother of the passions] â but who today knows what solitude is?
From this morbid isolation, from the desert of these years of temptation
and experiment, it is still a long road to that tremendous overflowing
certainty and health which may not dispense even with wickedness, as a
means and fish-hook of knowledge, to that mature freedom of spirit which
is equally self-mastery and discipline of the heart and permits access
to many and contradictory modes of thought â to that inner spaciousness
and indulgence of superabundance which excludes the danger that the
spirit may even on its own road perhaps lose itself and become
infatuated and remain seated intoxicated in some corner or other, to
that superfluity of formative, curative, moulding and restorative forces
which is precisely the sign of great health, that superfluity which
grants to the free spirit the dangerous privilege of living
experimentally and of being allowed to offer itself to adventure: the
masterâs privilege of the free spirit! In between there may lie long
years of convalescence, years full of variegated, painfully magical
transformations ruled and led along by a tenacious will to health which
often ventures to clothe and disguise itself as health already achieved.
There is a midway condition which a man of such a destiny will not be
able to recall without emotion: it is characterized by a pale, subtle
happiness of light and sunshine, a feeling of bird-like freedom,
bird-like altitude, bird-like exuberance, and a third thing in which
curiosity is united with a tender contempt. A âfree-spiritâ- this cool
expression does one good in every condition, it is almost warming. One
lives no longer in the fetters of love and hatred, without yes, without
no, near or far as one wishes, preferably slipping away, evading,
fluttering off, gone again, again flying aloft; one is spoiled, as
everyone is who has at some time seen a tremendous number of things
beneath him- and one becomes the opposite of those who concern
themselves with things which have nothing to do with them. Indeed, the
free spirit henceforth has to do only with things â and how many things!
â with which he is no longer concerned ...â
Here, of course, is rhetoric â but it is a rhetoric of a freedom which
one wills, a freedom cast as a will to health, a will to live
experimentally, no longer content to rest on the laurels of someone
elseâs truth. There is something of the desert about this freedom which
is tied to being driven on by oneself to oneâs own knowledge, oneâs own
mastery of self. This is a finding oneself which leads one to question
everything, to pledge to oneself that nothing will count unless it is
won by your own honesty and self-determination. It will undoubtedly lead
to solitude â but one must also prove oneself strong enough for that as
well. And so:
âAt that time it may finally happen that, under the sudden illumination
of a still stressful, still changeable health, the free, ever freer
spirit begins to unveil the riddle of that great liberation which had
until then waited dark, questionable, almost untouchable in his memory.
If he has for long hardly dared to ask himself: âwhy so apart? so alone?
renouncing everything I once reverenced? renouncing reverence itself?
why this hardness, this suspiciousness, this hatred for your own
virtues?â â now he dares to ask it aloud and hears in reply something
like an answer. âYou shall become master over yourself, master also over
your virtues. Formerly they were your masters; but they must be only
your instruments beside other instruments. You shall get control over
your For and Against and learn how to display first one and then the
other in accordance with your higher goal. You shall learn to grasp the
sense of perspective in every value judgement â the displacement,
distortion and merely apparent teleology of horizons and whatever else
pertains to perspectivism; also the quantum of stupidity that resides in
antitheses of values and the whole intellectual loss which every For,
every Against costs us. You shall learn to grasp the necessary injustice
in every For and Against, injustice as inseparable from life, life
itself as conditioned by the sense of perspective and its injustice. You
shall above all see with your own eyes where injustice is always at its
greatest: where life has developed at its smallest, narrowest, neediest,
most incipient and yet cannot avoid taking itself as the goal and
measure of things and for the sake of its own preservation secretly and
meanly and ceaselessly crumbling away and calling into question the
higher, greater, richer â you shall see with your own eyes the problem
of order of rank, and how power and right and spaciousness of
perspective grow into the heights together. You shallâ â enough: from
now on the free spirit knows what âyou shallâ he has obeyed, and he also
knows what he now can, what only now he â may do ...â
This is a will to oneâs independence, to oneâs excellence [virtue, in
Greek historical derivation, is a matter of excellence in being a human
being], and is not just a personal but a cultural task. Thus, in section
225 of Human, All Too Human, Nietzsche says: âHe is called a free spirit
who thinks differently from what, on the basis of his origin,
environment, his class and profession, or on the basis of the dominant
views of the age, would have been expected of him.â The free spirit,
that is, sets themselves apart; they are an exception. Such people set
themselves on a course and go on a journey, as Nietzsche calls it in
section 292, âthe path of wisdomâ which they embark upon âwith a bold
step and full of confidenceâ in which they are to âserve as [their] own
source of experienceâ. In his final aphorism of the original book [638]
Nietzsche calls free spirits âwanderers and philosophersâ and they seek
a transfiguration as of morning that transfigures the night. It is worth
noting here that Human, All Too Human marks an intellectual turning
point for Nietzsche in which he turns away from former beliefs and
things which, as he himself intimates, fettered him, and strikes out on
his own, determined to win the right to his own knowledge of things.
This is the Nietzsche who will be willed into existence for the next 10
years of his life and which leads to Zarathustra, the Overhuman and the
transvaluation of all values. Thus, this book is, as Nietzsche
describes, the beginnings of a self-administered intellectual cure and
the identification of growing spiritual/intellectual health with such a
thing. In this connection, it is worth repeating once more that the
German word âGeistâ means âspiritâ yet also âmindâ and âintellectâ. The
word Nietzsche uses for âfree spiritâ is âfreigeistâ and in German that
can mean âfree thinkerâ just as much as âfree spiritâ. In fact,
Nietzsche often plays on that fact.
That the free spirit is a cultural task Nietzsche starts to betray in
âAssorted Opinions and Maximsâ, added as a second part to Human, All Too
Human. Nietzsche had already in what I have quoted linked âfree spiritsâ
with Europe and Europeans and he does so again in aphorism 87 here where
he sees Europe playing a cultural role in world terms [yet as the
antithesis of nationalism!]. Here âall free spiritsâ are put alongside
âall good Europeansâ, something that happens in several places
throughout his books as well. Then again in aphorism 182 [âsigns of
cultural weatherâ] Nietzsche says: âTo test whether someone is one of us
or not â I mean whether he is a free spirit or not â one should test his
feelings towards Christianity. If he stands towards it in any way other
than critically then we turn our back on him: he is going to bring us
impure air and bad weather.â To be a critic of Christianity, of course,
will become one of Nietzscheâs most consistent tasks and here that is a
marker of the free spirit, a cultural task to which they are detailed.
Nietzsche expands upon this further in a key section [347], for our
purposes, from The Gay Science in which he parses the difference between
the believer who wants to be commanded and the free spirit:
âBelievers and their need to believe. â The extent to which one needs a
faith in order to flourish, how much that is âfirmâ and that one does
not want shaken because one clings to it â that is a measure of the
degree of oneâs strength (or, to speak more clearly, oneâs weakness).
Christianity, it seems to me, is still needed by most people in old
Europe even today; hence it still finds believers. For that is how man
is: an article of faith could be refuted to him a thousand times; as
long as he needed it, he would consider it âtrueâ again and again, in
accordance with that famous âproof of strengthâ of which the Bible
speaks. Metaphysics is still needed by some, but so is that impetuous
demand for certainty that today discharges itself in
scientific-positivistic form among great masses â the demand that one
wants by all means something to be firm (while owing to the fervour of
this demand one treats the demonstration of this certainty more lightly
and negligently): this is still the demand for foothold, support â in
short, the instinct of weakness that, to be sure, does not create sundry
religions, forms of metaphysics, and convictions but does â preserve
them. Indeed, around all these positivistic systems hover the fumes of a
certain pessimistic gloom, something of a weariness, fatalism,
disappointment, fear of new disappointment â or else self-dramatizing
rage, a bad mood, the anarchism of exasperation and whatever other
symptoms or masquerades there are of the feeling of weakness. Even the
vehemence with which our cleverest contemporaries get lost in pitiful
nooks and crevices such as patriotism (I refer to what the French call
chauvinisme and the Germans âGermanâ), or in petty aesthetic creeds such
as French naturalism (which enhances and exposes only the part of nature
that simultaneously disgusts and amazes â today one likes to call it la
verite vraie â ), or in Petersburg-style nihilism (meaning faith in
unbelief to the point of martyrdom), always indicates primarily the need
for faith, a foothold, backbone, support ... Faith is always most
desired and most urgently needed where will is lacking; for will, as the
affect of command, is the decisive mark of sovereignty and strength.
That is, the less someone knows how to command, the more urgently does
he desire someone who commands, who commands severely â a god, prince,
the social order, doctor, father confessor, dogma, or party conscience.
From this one might gather that both world religions, Buddhism and
Christianity, may have owed their origin and especially their sudden
spread to a tremendous sickening of the will. And that is actually what
happened: both religions encountered a demand for a âThou Shaltâ that,
through a sickening of the will, had increased to an absurd level and
bordered on desperation; both religions were teachers of fanaticism in
times of a slackening of the will and thereby offered innumerable people
support, a new possibility of willing, a delight in willing. For
fanaticism is the only âstrength of the willâ that even the weak and
insecure can be brought to attain, as a type of hypnosis of the entire
sensual-intellectual system to the benefit of the excessive nourishment
(hypertrophy) of a single point of view and feeling which is now
dominant â the Christian calls it his faith. Once a human being arrives
at the basic conviction that he must be commanded, he becomes âa
believerâ; conversely, one could conceive of a delight and power of
self-determination, a freedom of the will, in which the spirit takes
leave of all faith and every wish for certainty, practised as it is in
maintaining itself on light ropes and possibilities and dancing even
beside abysses. Such a spirit would be the free spirit par excellence.â
Free spirits, then, are NOT believers anymore than they are those who
want to be commanded. Indeed, free spirits, as of their nature, are
those with an unsurpressable desire to command themselves, to rule
themselves, to create their own âI shallâ. This is an egoistic place of
self-command but also something of cultural significance where to be a
believer, to be commanded, to be âChristianâ, is a phenomenon which
manifests itself in society at large. A society of free spirits would be
a society of the self-determined, the self-actualised, not a society of
willing believers. âFree spiritsâ is used in such a connection, in fact,
earlier in section 343 where Nietzsche, reflecting on âthe death of Godâ
which his madman had announced, lantern in hand, in the marketplace in
section 125, reflects on a future context for this and lends it a
glimmer of utopian light:
âHow to understand our cheerfulness. â The greatest recent event â that
âGod is deadâ; that the belief in the Christian God has become
unbelievable â is already starting to cast its first shadow over Europe.
To those few at least whose eyes â or the suspicion in whose eyes is
strong and subtle enough for this spectacle, some kind of sun seems to
have set; some old deep trust turned into doubt: to them, our world must
appear more autumnal, more mistrustful, stranger, âolderâ. But in the
main one might say: for many peopleâs power of comprehension, the event
is itself far too great, distant, and out of the way even for its
tidings to be thought of as having arrived yet. Even less may one
suppose many to know at all what this event really means â and, now that
this faith has been undermined, how much must collapse because it was
built on this faith, leaned on it, had grown into it â for example, our
entire European morality. This long, dense succession of demolition,
destruction, downfall, upheaval that now stands ahead: who would guess
enough of it today to play the teacher and herald of this monstrous
logic of horror, the prophet of deep darkness and an eclipse of the sun
the like of which has probably never before existed on earth? Even we
born guessers of riddles who are so to speak on a lookout at the top of
the mountain, posted between today and tomorrow and stretched in the
contradiction between today and tomorrow, we firstlings and premature
births of the next century, to whom the shadows that must soon envelop
Europe really should have become apparent by now â why is it that even
we look forward to this darkening without any genuine involvement and
above all without worry and fear for ourselves? Are we perhaps still not
too influenced by the most immediate consequences of this event â and
these immediate consequences, the consequences for ourselves, are the
opposite of what one might expect â not at all sad and gloomy, but much
more like a new and barely describable type of light, happiness, relief,
amusement, encouragement, dawn ... Indeed, at hearing the news that âthe
old god is deadâ, we philosophers and âfree spiritsâ feel illuminated by
a new dawn; our heart overflows with gratitude, amazement, forebodings,
expectation â finally the horizon seems clear again, even if not bright;
finally our ships may set out again, set out to face any danger; every
daring of the lover of knowledge is allowed again; the sea, our sea,
lies open again; maybe there has never been such an âopen seaâ.â
We see here that talk of âfree spiritsâ is more than the personal need
for companion spirits which Nietzsche had when writing Human, All Too
Human. The idea has now become part of an intellectual, moral, political
and cultural critique [encompassing the books Human, All Too Human,
Daybreak and The Gay Science] where free spirits have a role to play in
the future of Europe and the world, a role to do with values and
culture. The title of this book, The Gay Science [âgayâ as in âcheerfulâ
or joyfulâ â which are both good alternatives], is in fact itself a
cultural reference of Nietzscheâs to âthe specific unity of âsinger,
knight, and free spiritâ which was characteristic of early Provençal
culture.â The free spirit is, then, a cultural figure.
It should be no surprise, then, that the ultimate free spirit is
Zarathustra, into whom the free spirit metamorphosises as an act of
self-overcoming. Already, near the beginning of his many speeches in
Thus Spoke Zarathustra, Zarathustra proclaims that âI love him who is of
a free spirit and a free heartâ [recalling the multivalent nature of
âGeistâ!] and this, of course, will lead to the Overhuman which is also
a free spirit. Thus, as Zarathustra pronounces in the section entitled
âOf the Famous Philosophersâ, âBut he who is hated by the people as a
wolf is by the dogs: he is the free spirit, the enemy of fetters, the
non-worshipper, the dweller in forests.â Such people must âbreak their
will to venerateâ in order to establish their own âgenuinenessâ. But
then, once more, Nietzsche links free spirits with the desert when he
says:
âGenuine â that is what I call him who goes into godforsaken deserts and
has broken his venerating heart. In the yellow sand and burned by the
sun, perhaps he blinks thirstily at the islands filled with springs
where living creatures rest beneath shady trees. But his thirst does not
persuade him to become like these comfortable creatures: for where there
are oases there are also idols. Hungered, violent, solitary, godless:
that is how the lion-will wants to be. Free from the happiness of serfs,
redeemed from gods and worship, fearless and fearful, great and
solitary: that is how the will of the genuine man is. The genuine men,
the free spirits, have always dwelt in the desert, as the lords of the
desert; but in the towns dwell the well-fed famous philosophers â the
draught animals.â
It seems clear that the free spirit is without gods â but they are also
without the desire to venerate or show reverence. These things they have
cultivated out of themselves as matters of health and strength. Free
spirits have nothing to worship and they have lost even the desire to
worship. Instead they are âfree spirits and wanderersâ who must ever
overcome themselves and their culture as constant revivifying springs of
new life and new growth. In that, the pre-eminent Nietzschean symbol is
the dance. Elsewhere in Zarathustra Nietzsche says ânone of you has
learned to dance as a man ought to dance â to dance beyond yourselves!â
â and that is what the free spirit must learn to do.
Nietzscheâs next book after Thus Spoke Zarathustra was Beyond Good and
Evil, an appropriate title for the free spirit that denominates where
such a person resides â for how can the free spirit who determines
themselves NOT reside there? The second part of this book is, in fact,
titled âThe Free Spiritâ and so it seems that Nietzsche made this
connection for himself too. Here we find a spirit of speculation and
suspicion entirely appropriate to the free spirit who has chosen to live
experimentally in search of their own knowledge and truth whilst
entirely aware of the question âWhy should the world that is relevant to
us not be a fiction?â Such a free spirit is coming to the point of
questioning the very language and grammar in which all their thought is,
and must be, put and to realising that âit cannot matter in the least
whether precisely you are in the rightâ. This is because such a free
spirit realises that âa more praiseworthy veracity may lie in every
little question mark placed after your favourite words and favourite
theories [and occasionally after yourselves].â The free spirits and, as
Nietzsche also denominates them in this second part of Beyond Good and
Evil, âphilosophers of the futureâ, are skeptics who must test
everything for themselves; they have made themselves so responsible and
cultivated an honesty within themselves for this task. Such
free-spirited philosophers of the future are once more expressly named
as âexperimentersâ and so are those not who are driven by the past
knowledge of others but by that knowledge they acquire in and through
their own lives and experiences. But:
âAre they new friends of âtruthâ, these approaching philosophers?
Probably so, for until now all philosophers have loved their truths. But
it is certain that they will not be dogmatists. It would surely go
against their pride, and also against their good taste, if their truth
had to be a truth for everyone else, too â this has been the secret wish
and ulterior thought in all earlier dogmatic endeavours. âMy judgement
is my judgement: no one else has a right to it so easilyâ, as a
philosopher of the future might say. We have to rid ourselves of the bad
taste of wanting to agree with many others. âGoodâ is no longer good if
our neighbour takes the word into his mouth. So how could there possibly
be âcommon goodsâ! The term contradicts itself: anything that is common
never has much value. In the end things will have to be as they are and
always have been: the great things are left to the great, the abysses to
the profound, tenderness and thrills to the sensitive, and to sum it up
in a few words, everything extraordinary to the extraordinary.â
Here Nietzsche puts a higher value on the personally acquired truth than
on the truth of the majority, the latter a thing, in his mind, of bad
taste. Each must think for themselves in this philosophy of the future.
Only this builds health. It is a personal but also fundamentally
cultural prescription when extrapolated from person to person in
networks of relationships. This is brought out further in the final note
of the free spirit chapter in section 44:
âAfter all that has been said, must I still make a special point of
mentioning that they too will be free, very free spirits, these
philosophers of the future â just as surely as they will not be free
spirits merely, but something more, higher, greater, and fundamentally
different, something that would not go unrecognized or misidentified?
But in saying this, I feel even towards them (as towards ourselves, the
free spirits who are their heralds and forerunners!) the obligation to
dispel for both of us a stupid old prejudice and misunderstanding that
for all too long has enshrouded the concept âfree spiritâ like a fog. In
all the countries of Europe, and in America now as well, there is
something that is misusing this name: a very narrow, trapped, enchained
sort of spirit who wants more or less the opposite of what we do, by
instinct and intention â not to mention that they are bound to be the
shut windows and barred doors to those approaching new philosophers.
These falsely dubbed ïżœïżœfree spiritsâ belong, short and sour, to the
levellers, loquacious scribbling slaves of the democratic taste and its
âmodern ideasâ; they are all of them people without solitude, without
their own solitude, plain well-behaved lads whose courage and honourable
propriety cannot be denied. It is just that they are unfree and
laughably superficial, especially in light of their basic tendency to
see, more or less, the cause of all human misery and failure in the
structures of society up to now, thus happily managing to turn truth
upside down! What they are trying with all their strength to achieve is
a common green pasture of happiness for the herd, with safety, security,
comfort, ease of life for everyone; their two most often recited tunes
and teachings are âEqual rightsâ and âCompassion for all sufferingâ â
and they take suffering itself as something that must be eliminated.
We who are the opposite, who have opened an eye and a conscience to the
question of where and how the plant âhuman beingâ has most vigorously
grown tall, we are of the opinion that this has always happened under
the opposite conditions: that the precariousness of the plantâs
situation had first to increase enormously; that its power of invention
and disguise (its âspiritâ-) had to become subtle and daring through
long periods of pressure and discipline; that its life-will had to be
intensified into an unconditional power-will. We are of the opinion that
harshness, violence, enslavement, danger on the street and in the heart,
seclusion, stoicism, the art of the tempter and every kind of devilry,
that everything evil, frightful, tyrannical, predatory, and snake-like
about humans serves to heighten the species âhuman beingâ as much as
does its opposite. To say only this much, in fact, is not even saying
enough, and whether we speak or are silent at this juncture, we find
ourselves at the other end of all modern ideology and wishful thinking
of the herd: as their antipodes, perhaps? Is it any surprise that we
âfree spiritsâ are not the most communicative of spirits? That we do not
wish to reveal in every case what a spirit can liberate itself from and
what it may then perhaps be driven to? And as far as concerns the
dangerous phrase âbeyond good and evilâ, it guards us at least against
being misidentified: we are something other than âlibre-penseursâ,
âliberi pensatoriâ , âfreethinkersâ, and whatever other names all these
honourable advocates of âmodern ideasâ might choose to call themselves
by. Having been at home, or at least a guest in many countries of the
spirit; having again and again escaped the pleasant, overstuffed nooks
to which our special loves and hatreds, our youth, our origins, the
accidents of people and books, or even the weariness of the journey have
seemed to banish us; full of malice towards the temptations of
dependence that lie hidden in honours or money or position or the
enthusiasms of the senses; grateful in fact for distress and varying
illnesses, because they have always freed us from some rule and its
âprejudiceâ; grateful to god, devil, sheep, and worm in us, curious to
the point of vice, investigators to the point of cruelty, thoughtlessly
fingering what cannot be grasped, with teeth and stomach for what is
most indigestible, ready for any craft that demands sharp wits and sharp
senses, ready for every venture thanks to a surplus of âfree willâ, with
fore-souls and back-souls whose ultimate intentions no one can easily
penetrate, with foregrounds and backgrounds that no foot could traverse
to the end, secluded under the cloaks of light, conquerors despite our
resemblance to heirs and wastrels, organizers and collectors from morn
till night, misers of our wealth and of our overflowing desk-drawers,
economical in learning and forgetting, inventive in schemata, sometimes
proud of category tables, sometimes pedants, sometimes labouring
night-owls even in bright daylight; and yes, if necessary, even
scarecrows â and that is what is necessary today, in so far as we are
the born, sworn jealous friends of solitude, our own , deepest, most
midnight, midday solitude. That is the sort of human we are, we free
spirits! And perhaps you have something of it, too, you who are
approaching? You new philosophers? -â
To be sure this is a long âaphorismâ that is plugged into Nietzscheâs
wider cultural critique yet the sense of it, for the free spirit, is
that the free spirit is not, as Nietzsche called all those of his day in
whom he found a sense for âdemocracyâ or âequalityâ, a âlevellerâ.
Nietzsche, to keep things simple, found this idea of levelling or an
abstracted imbued equality or democracy fundamentally unhealthy at a
cultural level; it literally, in his mind, did not promote strength or
health and so, regardless of moral judgments [which he wouldnât have
agreed with either], was regarded as a materially bad thing which could
only lead [and was leading] to societal decay. Thus, whether you think
democracy or equality are good things or not, Nietzsche argues that they
are bad for the social organism as matters of inevitable material fact
when using a biological metaphor of life, health and growth. What is
not, however, is the free spirit who is independent of mind and who has
hardened themselves to survive in the desert, a person of free will not
afraid of the solitude which comes from oneâs own truth and oneâs own
hard won knowledge verified by personal experience. For such a person
suffering is not to be valued simply as âbadâ and eradicated at all
costs and in every case. For such a one suffering, too, has its uses if
it befalls us; it can even be necessary. The free spirit, such as
Nietzsche regards himself to be, thinks in terms of health and
cleanliness, that which promotes life, before they acquiesce before the
slightest test or hardship as if the point of life was to avoid them
all. For the free spirit, that which promotes oneâs own strength is good
and that which encourages weakness is detrimental. The free spirit
thinks in terms of breeding and favours that which strengthens rather
than that which weakens. [I think here of Diogenes rolling in hot sand
in summer to steel himself to the heat or clinging to cold statues in
winter to steel himself against the cold.] It is in this sense that Emma
Goldman can praise Nietzsche as one who wants to make aristocrats of us
all rather than âa race of weaklingsâ. To put words in Emma Goldmanâs
mouth, in fact, she really wants a community of free spirits as
Nietzsche did too.
The characterisation of the free spirit is further commented upon by
Nietzsche in the 24^(th) section of the third essay of On The Genealogy
of Morality. Here, once more, Nietzsche wants to emphasise that free
spirits are not any kind of believers:
âWe âknowersâ are positively mistrustful of any kind of believers; our
mistrust has gradually trained us to conclude the opposite to what was
formerly concluded: namely, to presuppose, wherever the strength of a
belief becomes prominent, a certain weakness, even improbability of
proof. Even we do not deny that faith âbrings salvationâ: precisely for
that reason we deny that faith proves anything, â a strong faith which
brings salvation is grounds for suspicion of the object of its faith, it
does not establish truth, it establishes a certain probability â of
deception. What now is the position in this case? â These ânoâ-sayers
and outsiders of today, those who are absolute in one thing, their
demand for intellectual rigour [Sauberkeit â which literally means
âcleanlinessâ], these hard, strict, abstinent, heroic minds who make up
the glory of our time, all these pale atheists, Antichrists,
immoralists, nihilists, these sceptics, ephectics, hectics of the mind
[that is, of the Geist] (they are one and all the latter in a certain
sense), these last idealists of knowledge in whom, alone, intellectual
conscience dwells and is embodied these days, â they believe they are
all as liberated as possible from the ascetic ideal, these âfree, very
free spiritsâ: and yet, I will tell them what they themselves cannot see
â because they are standing too close to themselves â this ideal is
quite simply their ideal as well, they themselves represent it nowadays,
and perhaps no one else, they themselves are its most intellectualized
product, its most advanced front-line troops and scouts, its most
insidious, delicate and elusive form of seduction: â if I am at all able
to solve riddles, I wish to claim to do so with this pronouncement! ...
These are very far from being free spirits: because they still believe
in truth ... â
The free spirit is a person of intellectual rigour who requires the
courage, honesty and authenticity for what they know â and, just as
importantly, for what they donât know. Note that Nietzsche links this to
a need for an intellectual cleanliness which may demand saying âNoâ to
societyâs highest truths and most revered ideas. The free spirit must be
the âimmoralistâ and ânihilistâ who pays that no attention if their own
intellectual rigour denies it. They must be fully independent
intellectual entities. What is at stake here, as Nietzsche explains in
section 203 of Beyond Good and Evil â referenced in On The Genealogy of
Morality â is nothing less than âthe total degeneration of manâ. It is,
once again, this question of what makes for strength and health, the
âlevellingâ and âequalityâ of âSocialistsâ or the creed of free spirits:
âWe who are of another faith â, we, to whom the democratic movement
counts not just as a form of decay of political organization but as the
form of decay, namely diminution, of man, as a way of levelling him down
and lowering his value: where must we reach out with our hopes? â To new
philosophers, there is no alternative; to spirits strong enough and
primordially forceful enough to give an incentive for contrary
valuations and for âeternal valuesâ to be valued another way round,
turned another way round; to those sent on ahead, to men of the future
who, in the present, tie up the knot of compulsion which forces the will
of millennia on to new paths. To teach man that the future of mankind is
his will, dependent on a human will, and to prepare him for great deeds
of daring and comprehensive attempts at discipline and breeding, in
order to put an end to that terrible domination of folly and accident
hitherto known as âhistoryâ â the folly of the âgreatest numberâ is just
its final form â: for this, some time or other, a new type of
philosopher and commander will be necessary, in comparison to whose
image everything we have seen on earth by way of hidden, terrible and
benevolent spirits will seem pale and dwarfed. It is the image of such
leaders which floats before our eyes: â dare I say it out loud, you free
spirits? The circumstances which one must partly create and partly take
advantage of to bring this about; the probable ways and experiments by
means of which a soul would grow to such height and power in order to
feel the compulsion to these tasks; a transvaluation of values under the
new pressure and hammer of which a conscience is steeled, a heart turned
to iron, so that it can bear the weight of such a responsibility; on the
other hand, the necessity of such leaders, the appalling danger that
they might not materialize or that they might turn out badly or
degenerate â these are our real worries and anxieties, you know, donât
you, you free spirits? These are the heavy distant thoughts and
thunderstorms that pass over the firmament of our life. There are few
pains as deep as that of having seen, recognized and sympathized with an
extraordinary man who has strayed from his path and degenerated: whoever
has the rare eye for the absolute danger of âmanâ himself degenerating,
whoever, like us, has recognized the incredible contingency which has
played its game with regard to the future of men â a game in which no
hand participated, not even âGodâs fingerâ! â whoever guesses at the
calamity which lies concealed in the stupid naĂŻvety and blind trust of
âmodern ideasâ, still more in the whole Christian-European morality: he
suffers from an anxiety which cannot be compared with any other, â he
sees with one glance what, under a favourable accumulation and increase
in forces and tasks could still be bred from man, he knows, with all the
knowledge of his conscience, how man is still untapped for the greatest
possibilities and how often the species, man, has already stood
confronted with mysterious decisions and new paths: â he knows even
better from his own painful memory what pathetic things have so far
habitually shattered, snapped, sunk and made wretched an embryonic being
of the highest potential. The total degeneration of man right down to
what appears today, to socialist idiots and numbskulls, as their âman of
the futureâ â as their ideal! â this degeneration and diminution of man
to the perfect herd animal (or, as they say, to the man in a âfree
societyâ), this bestialization of man into a dwarf animal of equal
rights and claims is possible, there is no doubt! Whoever has once
thought these possibilities through to the end knows one form of nausea
more than other people do â and perhaps also a new task!....â
With this text Nietzsche introduces the idea of values and the need for
them to be transvalued if humankind would be a healthy species.
Nietzsche refutes the idea that âequal rightsâ leads to a healthy
humanity â perhaps not least because this very idea is entirely contrary
to the free spirits he has heretofore imagined at length. Nietzsche
stands for that person who, by act of will, is constantly questioning
everything â not least themselves! â in order to overcome themselves. He
believes that the strongest humanity is that which is made up of the
strongest, most healthy, human beings. This âhealthâ is not, of course,
meant in a naively medical sense; it is a metaphor and only a metaphor.
Nietzsche is about asking what makes human beings vital and alive, what
promotes their growth. His answer is a full intellectual, moral and
cultural independence which can only lead to political independence as
well. For Nietzsche, free spirits create their own values and change old
values into new ones so that they totally recreate themselves on their
own terms [so also Zarathustra]. The sense of this is brought out, in
fact, in section 13 of The Anti-Christ:
âLet us not underestimate the fact that we ourselves, we free spirits,
already constitute a ârevaluation of all valuesâ, a living declaration
of war on and victory over all old concepts of âtrueâ and âuntrueâ. The
most valuable insights are the last to be discovered; but methods are
the most valuable insights. All the methods, all the presuppositions of
our present scientific spirit have been regarded with the greatest
contempt for thousands of years, they barred certain people from the
company of âdecentâ men, â these people were considered âenemies of
Godâ, despisers of the truth, or âpossessedâ . As scientific characters,
they were Chandala [untouchables]. We have had the whole pathos of
humanity against us â its idea of what truth should be, of what serving
the truth should entail: so far, every âthou shaltâ has been directed
against us ... Our objectives, our practices, our silent, cautious,
distrustful nature â all of this seemed totally unworthy and despicable.
â In the end, and in all fairness, people should ask themselves whether
it was not really an aesthetic taste that kept humanity in the dark for
so long: people demanded a picturesque effect from the truth, they
demanded that the knower make a striking impression on their senses. Our
modesty is what offended their taste for the longest time ... And didnât
they know it, these strutting turkey-cocks of God â â
Of course, in The Anti-Christ the target is the Christian with their
belief. But Nietzsche is not thereby afraid to say that âJesus could be
called a âfree spiritâ, using the phrase somewhat looselyâ [section 32]
â and that because, in his analysis of the Galilean:
âThe concept, the experience of âlifeâ as only he knew it, repelled
every type of word, formula, law, faith, or dogma. He spoke only about
what was inside him most deeply: âlifeâ or âtruthâ or âlightâ are his
words for the innermost, â he saw everything else, the whole of reality,
the whole of nature, language itself, as having value only as a sign, a
parable.â
We will remember from earlier that the free spirit was not, and could
not, ever be a dogmatist. Nietzsche thinks that Jesus was no dogmatist
either. In giving his own truth, he demonstrated a kind of free
spiritedness which even Nietzsche â the Antichrist! â could recognise.
The Anti-Christ itself is a good, and short, book to read in regard to
free spirits â yet not because it is all about them but because it is
about their opposites, the Christians and believers. It is here, in
fact, that Nietzsche makes one of his most pertinent comments on
intellectual integrity and the necessary intellectual qualities which
can lead to a true intellectual independence. This is in section 54:
âMake no mistake about it: great spirits are sceptics. Zarathustra is a
sceptic. The vigour, the freedom that comes from the strength and
super-strength of spirit proves itself through scepticism. Where basic
issues about value or lack of value are concerned, people with
convictions do not come into consideration. Convictions are prisons.
These people do not see far enough, they do not see beneath themselves:
but if you are going to talk about value and lack of value, you need to
see five hundred convictions beneath you, behind you ... A spirit who
wills greatness and also wills the means to it is necessarily a sceptic.
The freedom from every sort of conviction, being able to see freely, is
part of strength ... His whole intellect is devoted to the great
passion, the foundation and the power of its being, more enlightened,
more despotic than he is himself; it gives him assurance; it gives him
the courage even for unholy means; it allows him convictions under
certain circumstances. Conviction as a means: there are many things that
can be achieved only by means of a conviction. Great passion uses
convictions and uses them up, it does not subordinate itself to them, â
it knows its own sovereignty. â Conversely: the need for faith, for some
unconditional yes or no⊠is a need of the weak. Men of faith, the
âfaithfulâ of every type, are necessarily dependent people, â the sort
of people who cannot posit themselves as a goal, who are utterly
incapable of positing goals from out of themselves. The âman of faithâ
does not belong to himself, he can only be a means, he needs to be used
up, he needs someone to use him up. He instinctively holds a morality of
self-abnegation in the greatest honour; everything urges him to adopt
it, his shrewdness, experience, vanity. Every type of faith is an
expression of self-abnegation, of self-alienation ... Just think how the
vast majority of people need some regulative guideline as an external
principle of bondage or mooring, how compulsion, slavery in a higher
sense, is the only and ultimate condition for the thriving of the
weak-willed person, particularly the female: this is how conviction,
âfaithâ, should be understood as well. It gives the man of convictions a
backbone. Not to see many things, not to be free on a single point, to
be partisan through and through, to have a strict and necessary optic in
all values â these are the only conditions under which this type of a
person can even arise. But this makes him the opposite, the antagonist
of the truthful person, â of truth ... A faithful person is not free to
have any sort of conscience for the question âtrueâ or âuntrueâ: honesty
on this point would be his immediate downfall. People with convictions
have pathologically conditioned optics, which makes them into fanatics â
Savonarola, Luther, Rousseau, Robespierre, Saint-Simon, â the antithesis
of strong spirits who have become free. But the grand poses struck by
these sick spirits, these conceptual epileptics, can affect the great
masses, â fanatics are picturesque, humanity would rather see gestures
than listen to reasons ...â
This intellectual independence of the free spirit is then a matter of
the strength of my own reasons â but where âreasonsâ are necessary
things for the free spirit, things one must fashion for oneself.
Freedom, in this sense, Nietzsche does not think is automatic or given.
It is, and can only be, an achievement of the self. One must make
oneself a goal and use everything up in that endeavour â one
consequently cannot afford the luxury of âconvictionsâ for these must
always be subservient to the creation and overcoming of oneâs past
truths. âConvictions are more dangerous enemies of truth than liesâ â as
Nietzsche had said right back in that book âfor free spiritsâ at section
483. It is right to say then, as Nietzsche does in Ecce Homo where he
reviews Human, All Too Human, that âThe term âfree spiritâ does not want
to be understood in any other way [than as] a spirit that has become
free, that has taken hold of itself again.â This is a matter of progress
â towards oneself â progress towards oneâs moral, intellectual, cultural
and political independence. This, in fact, is what I think attracted
Emma Goldman to Nietzsche so much and held her interest â whilst others
dissented â and made it the basis of her own anarchy.
If we take this interpretation of Nietzscheâs âfree spiritâ as read then
the mirror image of this figure is the Italian anarchist, Renzo
Novatore. Let us consider, for example, his text âThe Revolt of The
Uniqueâ â a text also significantly demonstrative of his influence by
Max Stirnerâs The Unique and Its Property. Novatore was a man who
started his rebellion for self-actualization early, rebelling against
both being schooled, which he left after only a term, and doing as his
parents wanted. It is said of him that he would wander off into the
woods near his home and educate himself with books acquired by what he
had sold, having pilfered produce from his parentsâ farm to sell for
money. In adult life he served some prison time for apparently setting
fire to a church and he deserted from the Italian Army during World War
One, being saved from being hunted down when an amnesty was declared. He
met his demise, at the age of 32, in a shoot out with police whilst
pursuing a life of illegalism â which Iâm sure he didnât mind at all as
it was death, as his life, on his own terms. âDeath is the final loverâ
as he said in an article titled âLetâs Exalt Lifeâ published in the
magazine Iconoclasta in 1920.
But it is to âThe Revolt of The Uniqueâ that I turn first of all which
is written publicly towards fellow Italian anarchist, Carlo Molaschi.
Molaschi had for several years been an individualist anarchist like
Novatore himself but some time around 1921, when âThe Revolt of The
Uniqueâ was written, Molaschi modulated his views to social anarchist
ones, having already been working with other social anarchists such as
Errico Malatesta and Camillo Bernieri, among others. The text of âThe
Revolt of The Uniqueâ is clearly written in response to this â although
Novatore still has the grace to address Molaschi as a âcomradeâ. The
text, however, is a strong polemical defence of Novatoreâs individualist
anarchism and a critique of social conceptions of the same as,
essentially, giving away everything in anarchism that is truly effective
and worthwhile. It is in this that we begin to see Novatoreâs
credentials as a Nietzschean free spirit who wants to take âanarchismâ
seriously.
Straight off the bat here Novatore sets the tone by saying:
âI donât want to dictate moral maxims to my âneighbour,â or teach anyone
anything⊠I leave this task to the missionaries of all faiths, the
priests of all churches, the demagogues of all parties, the apostles of
all ideas. I only want to howl my extreme rebellion against everything
that oppresses me; I only want to push far away from me everything that
the religious, socialist, or libertarian priesthood wants to impose on
my individuality without me having freely accepted and wanted it.â
Here Novatore has already associated âsocialistâ with a âpriesthoodâ, a
hierarchical metaphor of control. As he continues, he talks about his
âuniquenessâ and the âdogmatic⊠societarianismâ he feels âpoisonsâ it.
An important point is reached when he says that âI have a personal truth
of my own that isnât and canât be universal âtruthââ, something that is
surely both a Nietzschean and a Stirnerite point. He references âthe
unique ideal that is my individualityâ in this respect and says that âI
donât deny to anyone the beauty of their ideas, the strength of their
dream, and the truth of their thoughtâ [and, of course, he expects the
same in return]. His conclusion is then:
âLet each human being therefore workâif he thinks this wayâat the
discovery of his own I, at the realization of his own dream, at the
complete integration and full development of his own individuality.
Every human being who has discovered and won himself walks on his own
path and follows his free course. But let no one come to me to impose
his belief, his will, his faith on me. By denying god, fatherland,
authority, and law, I have achieved anarchism. By refusing to sacrifice
myself on the altar of the people and of humanity, I have achieved
individualism. Now I am freeâŠâ
This is a social as well as an individual prescription just as
Nietzscheâs project of free spirits had social as well as personal
connotations. It canât not have when such a thing is being put forward
as a general idea in regard to what you think it is best for people to
be [even if you then leave it up to their own judgment]. So Novatore is,
at a minimum, implying that human beings who discover themselves [i.e.
become free spirits] should walk on their own path and follow their own
free course and that this would be a better society than the one we have
now if they did. Novatore in this essay imagines himself in a âwar
against the brute force of society, of the people, of humanityâ who
âdare to act against the uniqueâ and have a âthousand monstrous armsâ.
He authorizes himself to defend himself against this mass coercion of
the collectivity âwithout scruplesâ exactly because he âfollows himselfâ
and does it to the nth degree, to the very end and without equivocation.
He is, in the popular phrase, truly âa law unto himselfâ. This, it
should be completely understood, is what Novatore believes anarchism is
â the complete denial of any authority but that of himself and the
complete inauthenticity of any attempt to coerce him, either by force or
by imagined benevolence. Novatore proclaims a creed of self-sufficiency
[and so is very Cynic in this respect] and he is not interested in an
anarchism of organised benevolence because the principle of personal
agency and autonomy is the condition that must be absolutely satisfied
for him in order to even recognise something as anarchism. Novatoreâs
view is that the only real interests in life are personal ones not
abstract or ideal ones â for actual human beings, individuals, are the
things that actually, materially exist. Things like âhumanityâ do not.
Novatoreâs view is that anarchy is not anarchy unless it addresses such
real human interests, the interests of real, living people. The human
being must be what counts â in its specificity â rather than âhumanityâ.
Novatore describes himself, from a sarcastically drawn social
perspective, as âdiseased with Stirnerâs âfierce egoismââ and âinfected
by arrogant Zarathustrian Overhumaniaâ to make the point that, to those
who see a mass but not the individual, such people are regarded as
nothing and effectively erased as a result.
Novatore now enters into an interesting phase of his essay where he
takes on the social anarchist position, which Molaschi seems to have
preached, prompting Novatoreâs response, which is presented as âmutual
aid, solidarity and love are necessities of lifeâ. Here, of course, it
would seem to be argued by Molaschi [or is at least presented by
Novatore] that the creeds of Stirner and Nietzsche lead away from these
things [that is, are implicitly regarded as socially detrimental].
Novatore wants to set the criticisms of Stirner and Nietzsche in this
assumption to one side, however [he doesnât agree with them but he is
animated himself by his own points]. Instead, he wants to criticise the
idea that Molaschi seems to think things should be FOR EVERYONE as he
thinks they should be [so as Auban accused Trupp in The Anarchists].
That is to say, he wants to enforce definitions and classifications â
and so conditions â onto others â an anti-individualist move which also
contradicts the idea of free spirits. As to âmutual aid, brotherhood and
loveâ, Novatore admits they are a necessity [which might be surprising]
but he doesnât admit they either are, or could be, a reality â at least
not in universal terms or as an achievable goal of society. Reality,
thinks Novatore, is âhatred, enmity, warâ. The contrast here seems to be
that Novatore views âsocialâ thinkers as proffering a future paradise or
imagining future utopias where enmity has ceased and all human beings
live in peace with all other human beings. Novatore fundamentally
rejects this picture and denies it will ever be possible whilst
playfully contrasting things Molaschi, in his new social guise, says now
with things he used to say when he was as individualist as Novatore is.
Novatore responds to the future paradise scenario with the comment âthe
dream of workers is not my dream. The longings of the people are not my
longings, the pains of the mass are not my pains!âŠâ As such, he
constantly forces the social anarchist like Molaschi to face up to the
truth that the only real interests in life are personal ones â something
Molaschi himself accepted in his own very recent past.
This is to contrast what Novatore paints as the âproselytisingâ,
future-oriented, idealist anarchism of social organisation with the
personal, individual, egoistic, unique anarchism of himself and other
individualists like him. Novatore here wants to point out the coercion
that is introduced into anarchism at that point at which anyone starts
saying what anarchists âshouldâ be doing for he regards this as a
transgression of what is almost the singular eternal principle of free
spirit: that there is anyone elseâs âshouldâ but my own for the
anarchist; that, therefore, EVERYTHING is voluntary for such a person
and that no coercion, whether violent or benevolent, is legitimate. Here
Novatore criticises an evolutionary argument Molaschi seems to have made
of himself that what one esteems in oneâs youth is not necessarily the
same as what one esteems in later years, having gained more experience.
Novatore grants this point but continues by adding that just because
this is reasonable it does not mean it must be the same for everyone. It
is neither an âobligationâ to evolve in such a way nor a âdutyâ.
Novatore pronounces himself against any anarchist âshouldâ and against
any anarchist who utters this âshouldâ too easily. Implicitly, he forces
anarchists, once again, back onto the absolute notion that freedom of
interest only exists for the individual which is where the actual, real,
living, material interests in life lie. His point is that no one has any
real requirement to be like anything except themselves. There is no
algorithm, plan, much less dogma, which determines what an anarchist
must be like, what an anarchist must want, or how they should behave.
Novatore mentions more than once the former verity of Molaschi himself
that âanarchists are born and not madeâ in this respect.
Novatore summarises this point in the noteworthy sentence that
âanarchism has ended up making itself official and becoming a party.â
The correct response to this is âOuch!â for that, surely, is what
anarchism can never, should never, become. In this respect, Novatore
references âthe conferences, the unions, the workerismâ and âthe
organizationsâ that have recently arisen in anarchist circles. He
christens this âpaternal democratic domesticityâ and these are not good
words from Novatoreâs mouth. They echo, in fact, Nietzscheâs
condemnations of socialism as secularised Christianity, the love that
kills rather than the hate that kills â and the love that kills is all
the worse for that because it claims to love as it kills you. Novatore,
however, stands for âanti-society individualismâ and, elsewhere, he
pledges to fight [actually fight, with weapons] against any society
which is formulated against him. [Novatore sees any society as against
him for it is the tendency, perhaps even the point, of society to
constrain the individual. But a free spirit only wants to be free!]
It is probably troubling for at least some readers then what
âanti-societyâ might actually mean on the lips of Renzo Novatore. He is
not unaware of this readerâs concern and I will do him the courtesy of
quoting his answer to this question in full:
âFirst of all, we need to come to a bit of an agreement about what
âanti-societyâ means.
I am not a misanthrope and so much the less a misogynist⊠I need friends
and lovers, clothes and bread. I am not an anchorite or a saint in the
desert. But thereâs no need to be such a thing in order to be
anti-society. Being anti-society meansâfor meânot collaborating in the
preservation of the present society nor lending oneâs efforts to any new
social construction. I said it once before: Every society you build will
have its fringes, and on the fringes of every society, heroic and
restless vagabonds will wander, with their wild and virgin thoughts,
only able to live by preparing ever new and terrible outbreaks of
rebellion! I shall be among them! And if materialistic âneedsâ force me
to go toward society, the ânecessityâ to be free sets me against it and
gives birth in me to a third âneed.â That of doing violence to it.
Without scruples! This is my âanti-societyâ perspective. And if we
happened to speak of so-called âprogressâ I could even affirmâwithout
fear of going wrongâthat the triumph and the glory of the human path are
due only to the spirit that informs this anti-society principle of
individualism.â
The final point here is an important point for, once again, it argues
that what makes life worth living in our reality, which is
individualised reality, is its very individualism, the ability to think
for oneself, act on individual impulse, follow individual desire. This,
in fact, is what makes social interaction meaningful or valuable â that
it is not coerced, forced or fixed, that we choose it for ourselves,
voluntarily. Novatoreâs point, hidden under scary terms like
âindividualismâ and âanti-societyâ, is that its only really the fact of
our independence which gives our lives any meaning. If we canât choose
things for ourselves then that meaning becomes dulled and what is
valuable is lost. This, for example, is why prison is a punishment: it
takes away autonomy, agency and our free association, the things which
make things meaningful and valuable for us, the things, according to
Novatore, to which anarchism is calling us back. So Novatore argues that
such an anarchism is actually the key to life, that which he will
literally fight for [as it turns out, to the death]. This, then, is a
fundamentally social as well as individual prescription, an actuality of
free and autonomous human beings living as they please.
All of this, it transpires, revolves around how you understand that
little seven letter word FREEDOM. I want to quote what Novatore says
about this, in the context of a reply to the newly social anarchist
Molaschi, as follows:
âThe word âFreedomâ taken in itself is a negation: nothingâdeath!
Freedom is a propulsion towards powerâit is the strength of conquest and
the capacity for possession. (I have had the capacity to free myself
from that tiresome old lover of mine; because I had the capacity and the
power, I have taken the liberty of gathering this new flower). Living
means doing good and bad to others. No one can live without hurting
anyone⊠Living means: dominating and being dominated! With the
realization of the unpleasant authoritarian communism of the socialists,
the rulers would be a slimy handful of demagogues, vulgar, cunning
insects; plebeian slaves in their turn of a dogma. In realizing
libertarian communism, the great majority would be the ruling Goddess.
But libertarian communism (which is the dream of those who hate conflict
and battleâwhich is youth and lifeâand for which they are nonetheless a
quick, strange paradoxical contradiction, to make war in the name of
equality and peace) would have to take extreme measures against those
who want to come out, advance, rise up to a more ample affirmation of
individual life. Libertarian communism would then be forced to repress
in order to preserve itself. But its materialistic preservation would be
the categorical negation of the very spirit that informs and exalts it!
And here we are finally at anarchyâI admit that one can speak of this as
a social realization of human life together. âAnarchyâ would thus be
nothing more nor less than the triumph of the higher âtype.â Radically
vanishedâbecause even the lowliest of all human beings would have had to
go beyond itâthe as-stupid-as-it-is-vulgar right to private property and
everything that is âmaterial good.â The spiritual dominator remainsâthe
one who is noble by nature. He will stand above the others and dominate
them. (No one, I believe, would have the false pretension of levelling
ethical, aesthetic, artistic, intellectual, and spiritual values, like
physical and sexual values). Because the noble one, even in Anarchyâor
rather, in anarchy more than in any other form of human life
togetherâwill enjoy pleasure that others would not be able to enjoy,
even if he, for love of them, wanted to renounce them. Anarchy is
therefore the natural Autocracy of the noble.â
The final conclusion here was also defended by Emma Goldman â although
Goldman didnât go around with a Browning pistol like Novatore
threatening to shoot anyone who denied her her liberty to live life
according to her noble desires. She was, however, coming from the same
Nietzschean place as Novatore in such a thought [which, incidentally,
some noticed and criticised her for as she remarks in reference to
âminorities versus majoritiesâ in Anarchism and Other Essays]. That
point, which I maintain Goldman shared with Novatore here, is that
anarchismâs vision of life is based in an absolute, radical freedom
which, ultimately, it is only possible to express at the individual
level. It is the anarchism of free spirits for free spirits are the only
ones who make themselves, and so their freedom and functional
independence, their goal and purpose because it is felt as a personal
need. It is only this, so they both say, which then guarantees freedom
beyond the individual level. Personal freedom makes free people and only
free people, not organisational imperative, can make a free politics
[understood, in this sense, as a web of personal relations]. So when
Goldman writes, âI want freedom, the right to self-expression,
everybodyâs right to beautiful, radiant thingsâ it is my argument that
she is actually saying, in her own words, of course, what Novatore here
says in his. Their anarchism together is an anarchism of free spirits,
of free autonomous anarchism for everyone. This, in fact, is why I think
Goldmanâs attitude appears to have been âgive people this freedom and
the rest will take care of itselfâ â which appears to be Novatoreâs
attitude as well. Here we should not be put off by scary words like
âautocracyâ and ânobilityâ but pierce beneath the language to engage
with the kind of people such thinking hopes us to be. It is
fundamentally to do with what we think freedom is and what it
practically means. And, of course, it is contrasted with a âlibertarian
communismâ which must ultimately be a coercion to its own hegemony as
Novatore never tires of sarcastically digging out.
Novatore, then, hopes for the highest in human life. He hopes for it
certainly for himself â but he does not thereby deny it to you as a
result. That I wish to be a free spirit does not deny you the right or
ability to be one too [or not]. I can satisfy my desires and feast on
life while you do the same thing as well. Each life, says Novatore [as
does Goldman], is individual, and anarchism is the pursuance of what is
best in life for it, something which can only be via individual paths
rather than levelling coercions or âuniversalâ truths. So when Novatore
says that life is âautocracyâ he means it in what most closely resembles
a Stirnerite sense, that each is unique and has their own âpropertyâ
which it is their task to prosper. So Novatoreâs polemical address to
Carlo Molaschi is ultimately an argument that freedom can only really be
individually free and that we must leave âsocietyâ to itself, to the
free interactions of free people. There is, thinks Novatore, no
gerrymandering this for, as of necessity, such interference would be
precisely gerrymandering and so would injure real, personal, material
interests in a systematic way. Novatore, as he says himself, understands
life to be a matter of such injury; it is, we may say, only natural. Yet
he conceives that there is then no utopian solution for it, no
imaginable, or actual, future peace treaty between all human beings. The
social anarchist ideal of future harmony is permanently cancelled for it
is an impossible vision, a collective self-delusion. There is, instead,
only the prospect of free spirits living freely and a community freedom
possibly emerging organically in the midst of that by its actuality as
individual acts with, and upon, individuals. And then, says Novatore,
âwe will love each other with a different love!â
This is a basic picture of the views of Renzo Novatore and his attitude
to anarchism but it can be filled in further from the surviving literary
fragments of his short and vigorously lived life. These, for example,
are some of his definitions:
âGOD: The creation of a sick fantasy. Inhabitant of senile and impotent
brains. Companion and comforter of rancid spirits born to slavery. A
pill for constipated minds. Marxism for the faint of heart.
HUMANITY: An abstract word with a negative connotation, long on power,
short on truth. An obscene mask painted on the mean face of a shrewd
vulgarian for the purpose of dominating the multitude of sentimentalist
idiots and imbeciles.
COUNTRY: Penal servitude for the semi-intelligent, a cowshed of
imbecility. A Circe who transforms her adoring fans into dogs and pigs.
A prostitute for the master, a pimp of the foreigner. Child-eater,
parent-slanderer and scoffer at heroes.
FAMILY: The denial of love, life and liberty.
SOCIALISM: Discipline, discipline; obedience, obedience; slavery and
ignorance, pregnant with authority. A bourgeois body grotesquely
fattened by a vulgar christian creature. A medley of fetishism,
sectarianism and cowardice.
ORGANIZATIONS, LEGISLATIVE BODIES AND UNIONS: Churches for the
powerless. Pawnshops for the stingy and weak. Many join to live
parasitically off the backs of their card-carrying simpleton colleagues.
Some join to become spies. Others, the most sincere, join to end up in
jail from where they can observe the mean-spiritedness of all the rest.
SOLIDARITY: The macabre altar used by capable comedians of all sorts to
display their priestly talent for reciting masses. The beneficiaries pay
nothing less than 100% humiliation.
FRIENDSHIP: Fortunate are those who have drunk from its chalice without
having their souls offended or poisoned. If one such person exists, I
urge them to send me their photograph. Iâm sure to look upon the face of
an idiot.
LOVE: Deception of the flesh and damage to the spirit. Disease of the
soul, atrophy of the brain, weakening of the heart, corruption of the
senses, poetic lies from which one gets ferociously inebriated two or
three times a day in order to consume this precious but stupid life more
quickly. And yet I would prefer to die of love. Itâs the only swindler,
after Judas, that can kill with a kiss.
MAN: A filthy paste of servitude, tyranny, fetishism, fear, vanity -and
ignorance. The greatest offence one can commit against an ass is to call
it a man.
WOMAN: The most brutal of enslaved beasts. The greatest victim shuffling
on earth. And, after man, the most responsible for her problems. Iâd be
curious to know what goes through her mind when I kiss her.â
Meanwhile, in his âAnarchist Individualism in the Social Revolutionâ,
Novatore provides further views with which to supplement those presented
in response to Carlo Molaschi. For example, he begins this essay:
âAnarchist individualism as we understand it â and I say we because a
substantial handful of friends think this like me â is hostile to every
school and every party, every churchly and dogmatic moral, as well as
every more or less academic imbecility. Every form of discipline, rule
and pedantry is repulsive to the sincere nobility of our vagabond and
rebellious restlessness! Individualism is, for us, creative force,
immortal youth, exalting beauty, redemptive and fruitful war. It is the
marvellous apotheosis of the flesh and the tragic epic of the spirit.
Our logic is that of not having any. Our ideal is the categorical
negation of all other ideals for the greatest and supreme triumph of the
actual, real, instinctive, reckless and merry life! For us perfection is
not a dream, an ideal, a riddle, a mystery, a sphinx, but a vigorous and
powerful, luminous and throbbing reality. All human beings are perfect
in themselves. All they lack is the heroic courage of their perfection.
Since the time that human beings first believed that life was a duty, a
calling, a mission, it has meant shame for their power of being, and in
following phantoms, they have denied themselves and distanced themselves
from the real. When Christ said to human beings: âbe yourselves,
perfection is in you!â he launched a superb phrase that is the supreme
synthesis of life.â
The view here is that human beings have all they need in themselves and
that when things like âdutyâ or âcallingâ or âmissionâ â in other words,
imposed obligations â intrude then life is weighted down with
unnecessary and arbitrary chains. But this does not mean, contrary to
those who too easily wish to regard individualist anarchism as
âselfishness raised to a principleâ, that no interest in social
revolution is maintained. In this essay, in fact, Novatore says the
following:
âThe Social Revolution is the sudden awakening of Prometheus after a
fall into a faint of sorrow caused by the foul vulture that rips his
heart to shreds. It is an attempt at self-liberation. But the chains
with which the sinister god Jove [i.e. Zeus] had him chained on the
Caucasus by the repugnant servant Vulcan cannot be broken except by the
Titanic rebel Hero, son of Jove himself. We rebel children of this
putrid humanity that has chained human beings in the dogmatic mud of
social superstitions will never miss bringing our tremendous axe blow
down on the rusty links of this hateful chain. Yes, we anarchist
individualists are for Social Revolution, but in our way, itâs
understood!â
Novatore here wants to distinguish a âsocialâ social revolution from the
interests an individualist free spirit might have in such a revolution.
Changing the present state of affairs into something else, something
other, is an ambition Novatore shares with the social anarchist [both
want to break their chains] but, thereafter, the ambitions immediately
begin to diverge. Individualist anarchists, according to Novatore,
engage in social revolution for their own reasons and not for social
anarchist reasons. They refuse, in fact, to engage in the âsocialâ
aspect of revolution except on their own voluntary terms, something on
which they insist. Consequently, âAll past revolutionsâ, says Novatore,
âwere in the end, bourgeois and conservative.â So therefore:
âThe revolt of the individual against society is not given by that of
the masses against governments. Even when the masses submit to
governments, living in the sacred and shameful peace of their
resignation, the anarchist individual lives against society because he
is in a never-ending and irreconcilable war with it, but when, at a
historical turning point, he comes together with the masses in revolt,
he raises his black flag with them and throws his dynamite with them.
The anarchist individualist is in the Social Revolution, not as a
demagogue, but as a inciting element, not as an apostle, but as a
living, effective, destructive forceâŠ
the ultimate task of we anarchist individualists will be that of blowing
up the final ark with bomb explosions and the final dictator with
Browning shots. The new society established, we will return to its
margins to live our lives dangerously as noble criminals and audacious
sinners! Because the anarchist individualist still means eternal
renewal, in the field of art, thought and action. Anarchist
individualism still means eternal revolt against eternal sorrow, the
eternal search for new springs of life, joy and beauty. And we will
still be such in Anarchy.â
This, then, is a constitutional revolt, one that comes from within and
which is non-negotiable as it is the motivation, the impetus, of the
anarchist individualistâs life. The Nietzschean free-spiritedness of
intellectual, moral and cultural independence here requires a necessary
political independence as well and is functionally foundational. It
should be no surprise, then, that Novatore can share the following views
in âBetween the Two Anarchiesâ:
â Iâanarchist and individualistâdonât want to and cannot embrace the
cause of atheist communism, because I donât believe in the supreme
elevation of the masses and therefore I refuse the realization of
Anarchy understood as a social form of human life together. Anarchy is
in free spirits, in the instinct of great rebels, and in great and
superior minds. Anarchy is the innermost animating mystery of
misunderstood uniquenesses, strong because alone, noble because they
have the courage of solitude and of love, aristocratic because scornful
of commonness, heroic because against all⊠Anarchy is nectar for the
psychic I and not sociological alcohol for the collectivity. The
anarchist is the one who refuses every cause for the joy of his life
radiating from inner spiritual intensity.â
This is to say that Novatore refuses to recognise anarchism as a social
form of human organisation, a theory to be applied to society. He takes
seriously the notion, implied for him in the word âanarchyâ, that such a
thing is not possible. This does not, of course, mean he is against
human interaction or activity with other human beings anymore than
people who do not believe in God thereby think that nature does not go
about its business anyway without a divine overseer. Novatore, after
all, had a wife and child, as well as friends and colleagues, and he has
already stated previously that he is no misanthrope. What he does
believe, however, is that âanarchy is in [Nietzschean] free spiritsâ and
so any social reality must then derive from this reality for him. The
inference here, as with Nietzsche, is that there is the smell of decay
around âcollectivityâ and all thinking which collectivises and so levels
and equalises on that basis, treating the individual as fodder for the
collective deity. Novatore is also in no doubt about how such views make
him look to others who are kept drunk on âsociological alcohol.â He uses
âvagabondâ and âcommon criminalâ of himself often enough to show this
self-awareness. He just doesnât care how such others see him because he
has, in his own conscious uniqueness, passed beyond [concern for] their
good and evil. He has engaged with the independence of the free spirit.
Novatoreâs free-spirited nature issues, in fact, in negation and in a
nihilism towards all social organisation and thinking which becomes
imposition, expectation and obligation. He explains this himself in âI
Am Also A Nihilistâ:
âI am an individualist because I am an anarchist; and I am an anarchist
because I am a nihilist. But I also understand nihilism in my own way⊠I
donât care whether it is Nordic or Oriental, nor whether or not it has a
historical, political, practical tradition, or a theoretical,
philosophical, spiritual, intellectual one. I call myself a nihilist
because I know that nihilism means negation. Negation of every society,
of every cult, of every rule and of every religion. But I donât yearn
for Nirvana, any more than I long for Schopenhauerâs desperate and
powerless pessimism, which is a worse thing than the violent
renunciation of life itself. Mine is an enthusiastic and Dionysian
pessimism, like a flame that sets my vital exuberance ablaze, that mocks
at any theoretical, scientific or moral prison. And if I call myself an
individualist anarchist, an iconoclast and a nihilist, it is precisely
because I believe that in these adjectives there is the highest and most
complete expression of my willful and reckless individuality that, like
an overflowing river, wants to expand, impetuously sweeping away dikes
and hedges, until it crashes into a granite boulder, shattering and
breaking up in its turn. I do not renounce life. I exalt and sing it.â
The key there is that Novatoreâs attitude to life âmocks at any
theoretical, scientific or moral prison.â This is how he sees such
things â as social prisons, as locking up the free spirit in a
sociological prison. Consequently, life is a battle for Novatore, a war
against people and institutions which want to fetter his being. As he
puts this himself in the same essay:
âLife â for me â is neither good nor bad, neither a theory nor an idea.
Life is a reality, and the reality of life is war. For one who is a born
warrior, life is a fountain of joy, for others it is only a fountain of
humiliation and sorrow. I no longer demand carefree joy from life. It
couldnât give it to me, and I would no longer know what to do with it
now that my adolescence is past⊠Instead I demand that it give me the
perverse joy of battle that gives me the sorrowful spasms of defeat and
the voluptuous thrills of victory. Defeated in the mud or victorious in
the sun, I sing life and I love it! There is no rest for my rebel spirit
except in war, just as there is no greater happiness for my vagabond,
negating mind than the uninhibited affirmation of my capacity to life
and to rejoice. My every defeat serves me only as symphonic prelude to a
new victory.â
The focus here, once more, is on what is real and, for Novatore, it is
the individual which is the felt reality of life, the moving force, the
sense and sensibility. Collectivities only exist in thought where they
are useful for making arguments and elucidating ideas but it is people,
real people in their concrete materiality with the needs and desires
that they contingently happen to have, that are of importance to him.
This puts the focus on what Novatore later in the same essay calls âthe
reality of my inner worldâ and Novatore rejects the abstraction
âsocietyâ because his inner world is real whereas society is not.
âSocietyâ is only a name for a holistic construction of human
relationships which could be otherwise imagined. Thus, he finishes this
essay by saying:
âI reject society for the triumph of the I. I reject the stability of
every rule, every custom, every morality, for the affirmation of every
willful instinct, all free emotionality, every passion and every
fantasy. I mock at every duty and every right so I can sing free will. I
scorn the future to suffer and enjoy my good and my bad in the present.
I despise humanity because it is not my humanity. I hate tyrants and I
detest slaves. I donât want and I donât grant solidarity, because I am
convinced that it is a new chain, and because I believe with Ibsen that
the one who is most alone is the strongest one. This is my Nihilism.
Life, for me, is nothing but a heroic poem of joy and perversity written
with the bleeding hands of sorrow and pain or a tragic dream of art and
beauty!â
Perhaps, then, Novatoreâs own construction of the free spirit is that
which he refers to as the âintellectual vagabondâ in an essay of the
same name. Here, paraphrasing both Max Stirner and Friedrich Nietzsche,
the egoist Novatore creates a fiction populated by Stirnerite ideas,
Zarathustran figures, characters from Ibsenâs dramas and even those from
the writing of Oscar Wilde. [All of these figures, incidentally, also
interested Emma Goldman.] But then Novatore is caught short in his
fiction-making and realises that, amongst such figures, he is in âbad
companyâ. His response, as you might expect, is unequivocal:
âOh, luminaries, you save me from the wrath of decent people⊠And save
me yet again from those who donât take the time to destroy, each day in
battle, a bit of this society that oppresses and crushes us, but rather
waste their time trying to teach, to impose systems of struggle and
thought on those who have tried to learn to struggle and think for
themselves. And when their time is not used up in accomplishing all
this, it is employed in figuring out how big the lunatic asylums, in
which the new rebels against the future society will get locked up, will
have to be. For my part, I find myself in good company with these
madmen, and along with one of them, perhaps the best, I cry: âscorn
them, scorn the good and the just, since they have always been the
beginning of the end.â Oh, how well I have lived in the company of these
madmen! How great I find their âmadness of destructionâ! I assure that I
love destructive madness more, far, far more than conserving wisdom.
Yes, yes, leave me with my madmen since I promise you that if the next
European revolution denies us the joy of falling wrapped in the delirium
of DESTRUCTION, in better times, I will come back to speak of Them, and
if there is anything to reproach â perhaps the smallness of their
madness? â I will do it and without reserve.â
If all this is by now striking you as, at least, eccentric, consider
that Novatore imagines the societal alternative, the organised filtering
of human organisation and activity based on uniformity of values and
thinking, as much, much worse. Novatore destroys because he thinks what
he is destroying deserves destruction. This is social commentary on his
part. It is the choice of his own discovered valuations for things over
the idea that he should accept the ones society, or any purely social
construction, teaches him, a will to independence over a will to being
organised. [That this is expected of a man who, as a child, evaded the
authority of both schools and his parents is, of course, a big ask!] Yet
Novatore is also wise enough to realise that his individuality is not
all there is to the world. âSocietyâ in fact, is the constant yang to
his yin. So, as he notes in âOf Individualism and Rebellionâ:
âThere are those who maintain that the human being is by nature a social
being. Others maintain that the human being is by nature anti-social.
Well, I admit that I have never been able to clearly understand what
they meant by their âby natureâ, but I have understood that both sides
are wrong, since the human being is social and anti-social at the same
time. Need, want, affection, love and sympathy are the elements that
push him toward sociability and union. The craving for independence and
the desire for freedom push her toward solitude and individualism. But,
while individualism operates and is realized against society, society
defends itself from its attacks. The war between âsocietarianismâ and
âindividualismâ is thus a fertile war of vitality and energy. But, while
the individual is necessary to society, this in its turn is necessary to
him. Individualism couldnât possibly exist if there was no society
against which it could affirm itself and live, expand itself and
rejoice.â
Perhaps then, in the end, Novatore simply reserves the right to be a
free spirit or intellectual vagabond in a world that will always have a
tendency to want to coerce and organise, to coagulate and coalesce.
Neither he nor Nietzsche, in fact, ever suggested that such free spirits
would be common. In fact, they exist and operate precisely as what is
not common, what is the exception. But both do seem to suggest they will
always exist and assert themselves nevertheless â as an expression of
their lived necessity. We might sum all this up, then, in something from
Novatoreâs âCry of Rebellionâ where he says:
âAll forms of society have systems to do one thing: Equalize! And all
forms of society consider themselves the perfect one. And it is this
dogma of perfection that obstructs the restless rebel who refuses to bow
to its new god⊠And Iâm so revolutionary that I barely recognize myself.
And do you know why I am a barely recognizable revolutionary? Because I
am guided only by the tremendous and unstoppable impulse of MY desire to
expand the force of my own will. I am not guided by phantoms, I do my
own walking: it is not the illusion of a perfect society or the
universal redemption of humanity, but the absolute need to affirm my
potential in spite of all other forces.â
This, at least in Novatoreâs mind, is a world of free spirits asserting
their own existence. It is not a view concerned with society or
macro-political ideas but a view concerned with the negation of society,
a view concerned with the negation of all societies as entities which
are viewed as a standing attack on the free-spirited self. Novatore was
always interested to live and die on his own terms â and he was
fortunate that this was something he achieved. Thus, he would have
argued that none of us can wish for a better outcome to our existence
than that and, taking that on board, this is an approach that we should
take seriously as an anarchist approach to life, an anarchism of free
spirits.
What then is âan anarchism of free spiritsâ in my own words? Lots of
ideas suggest themselves and, since this is a text in which I am trying
to explain things, it is a duty I impose upon myself to try and present
them sensibly. Perhaps the deepest and most consequential of these
ideas, since I must start somewhere, is that âan anarchism of free
spirits is the only way to the achieval of something termed
âanarchismâ.â That sounds circular and perhaps contradictory but in my
mind its not. First of all, Iâm not at all convinced that anarchists are
about, or should be about, the achieval of âanarchismâ or âworld peaceâ
or ârevolutionâ or ridiculous macro-political pie-in-the-sky things like
that. An anarchism of free spirits regards the proper focus of
anarchistic attention as being yourself and willing yourself to be that
free spirit which Nietzsche and Novatore and, for that matter, Goldman
have already spoken to. At most, such a person is concerned to their
relationships with others, with whom they combine in various ways, in
order to satisfy each others needs. But âoverthrowing the governmentâ or
âestablishing an anarchist territoryâ or âorganising the peopleâ? A free
spirit is not concerned with that as a goal. Free spirits invalidate all
leaders rather than creating new ones.
The second point here is that â as Novatore demonstrated â the free
spirit takes words like âanarchismâ and âanarchyâ VERY SERIOUSLY and, as
a consequence, accepts no half measures. If âanarchyâ is âno leadersâ or
âno authorityâ then that must be followed through to the end and not
fudged in âthe anarchist revolutionary councilâ or âthe benevolent
federation of anarchistsâ. âAnarchyâ, for the free spirit, means no
leaders or authorities or coercive bodies at all but autonomy, agency,
free association, voluntary connections which people can break off, for
any reason or none, at any time they like. If it be argued against this
point that this would make any community or project of more than a few
hours impossible since no one could ever be relied on, then I reply to
that that, if it be so, then you must live with it. But I would also add
that cultivating trusting relationships and finding people you can rely
on should never be a matter of coercion or obligation either and ask
whether introducing such things, even apparently benevolently, is really
what you want. For the free spirit any community or project which
requires cooperation must absolutely be based in free association and
cultivating voluntary relationships in order to make something that
comes from within rather than something which is coerced from without.
The free spirit is one who is not shy of sharing themselves with others
in their own, or in a shared, interest but it must always be freely
given by them themselves in order to maintain its free-spirited
character. This is a matter of taking anarchism seriously as an
uncoerced path through life and of taking anarchy seriously as a state
of existence in which coercions are things that life will always seek to
avoid and to rebel against as a duty willingly self-imposed by the free.
The third point is then to say, perhaps as Auban in The Anarchists said
at his best, that metanarratival idealisms which ultimately seek only to
propagate themselves â such as anarchist communism was accused of â are
finally authoritarianism and coercion in another disguise. This is, at
least, certainly a charge individualist anarchists made in the past and
we saw in our discussion of Novatore that he essentially made the same
charge against Carlo Molaschi in real life that Auban made against Trupp
in fiction. The question to answer here is where does the centre of
gravity lie when we talk about freedom? Is it with the collectivity or
is it with the individual? The free spirit says that it is only
individuals, with their real lives and felt needs and actual concerns,
that actually exist and that the collectivity is ultimately an
abstraction that is wielded for various purposes. This, however, is not
to say that people may not have common needs or common foes or that
relationships between people are also not real. It is to say that if
people want to fight foes together or supply needs together then this is
for them to agree upon in and from their own individuality through the
construction of relationships each on their own terms. What my interest
is, whoever âmeâ is there, should always be a matter for me. I should
always be responsible for it and want to be responsible for it. It
should be regarded as something which cannot be given away or subsumed
or superceded by any imagined âhigher levelâ collective body or
abstraction. A free spirit simply would fight to the death against this
as a struggle for their own independent existence â a matter, to them,
of their life and death. How they live, and who they live it with, are
matters for them and them alone and this is seen as taking âanarchismâ
seriously as an idea to begin with, as an idea that means something
specific that cannot be fudged.
Another aspect to this, already hinted at earlier on in the previous
discussion, is that anarchism must never be seen as gerrymandering the
world. The more I have studied anarchism, past and present, the more it
has often seemed to me that, for many, this is exactly what anarchism
is. We see this attitude, for example, wherever we think of anarchism as
a revolution which sweeps away capitalism or a government or as a future
state of affairs where people are organised in a more horizontal way.
The wish here is the same: to fix the world in a way some assumedly
benevolent person or persons imagines is best. IS THAT REALLY ANARCHISM?
IS THAT WHAT âNO AUTHORITYâ HAS AMOUNTED TO? IS âANARCHYâ THEN A STATE
OF AFFAIRS IN WHICH SOME IDEOLOGY HAS DECIDED HOW PEOPLE WILL LIVE?
Excuse me, but I seem to have studied anarchism for years and come to
the conclusion that this is exactly what anarchism was intended to make
impossible! What is anarchism? What is anarchy? Is it disseminating a
new ideology which reorientates how people relate to one another and
creates communities and societies? Is it, in this sense, âgerrymandering
the worldâ? For an anarchism of free spirits it could not be for each
would wish their own independence and to create their relationships with
one another as they saw fit â not according to that benevolent ideology
which someone else thought was best for them. Again: do we take
âanarchyâ seriously? Do we take âanarchismâ seriously? What does it mean
to do this when you really get down to the filth and the gutter? It
means no leaders; it means no authorities; it means I take
responsibility for myself, I educate myself, I create myself, I
actualise myself â for my life is my business and I must live it as I
please. Whether you like it or not. It is Max Stirnerâs recognition that
âThe idols exist through me; I need only refrain from creating them
anew, then they exist no longer: âhigher powersâ exist only through my
exalting them and abasing myself.â As such, a further quotation of Max
Stirnerâs from The Unique and Its Property puts this thought in broader
terms:
âRevolution and insurrection should not be looked upon as synonymous.
The former consists in a radical change of conditions, of the prevailing
condition or status, the state or society, and is therefore a political
or social act; the latter indeed has a transformation of conditions as
its inevitable result, but doesnât start from it, but from the
discontent of human beings with themselves; it is not an armed uprising,
but a rising up of individuals, a getting up, without regard to the
arrangements that spring from it. The revolution is aimed at new
arrangements, while the insurrection leads us to no longer let ourselves
be arranged, but rather to arrange ourselves, and sets no radiant hopes
on âinstitutions.â...
The revolution commands one to make arrangements; the insurrection
demands that one stand or raise himself up... The insurrectionist
strives to become constitutionless.â
We have to take seriously, then, what Nietzsche meant by a free spirit.
He meant someone creating, and asserting, their intellectual, moral,
cultural and political independence or their Stirnerite
âconstitutionlessnessâ, their refusal to be institutionalised. But in my
using the word âindependenceâ here let us not make facile allusions to
someone living alone in self-absorbed isolation. This is not what is
meant. It is much more to do with a person who owns themselves, who does
not defer, who insists that their thoughts, their life, their behaviour,
is a matter for them. They do not defer to custom or act according to
tradition as unthinking meatpuppets being worked by the dead hand of the
past that has animated them from birth through the maladministrations of
parents, teachers and public morality. In simple terms, they think for
themselves and, in doing so, they rebel against uniformity, duty,
obligation, staying in your lane, knowing your place and doing as you
are told. They are people who refuse to be drilled and who insist on
making their own meanings and creating their own values and value
systems. Such things they regard as the honesty and virtue of the free
spirit. They are those who, even if everyone else goes along with
things, will not be coerced. They insist on the voluntaristic nature of
human conduct and on an anarchism based in voluntarism. They ask that,
if anarchism and anarchy mean anything, they mean human agency, real
autonomy and a total and absolute freedom of association â and they
imagine that, these things being granted, the rest is not really our
concern and will take care of itself for people do not need to be
organised, they are quite capable of organising themselves if they feel
the need to.
The free spirit conceives that anarchism is not, as has often been the
case in the past, a matter purely of externals. The Mujeres Libres, for
example, knew that was not the case during the Spanish Revolution of the
mid-1930s because they found that misogynistic attitudes were apparently
undisturbed by the anarchistsâ practice of their anarchism. The free
spirit regards anarchism as a matter of what is within, as a matter of
character, personality, personal values, a fastidiously cleansed mind in
which every last vestige of inherited thinking has been purged of old
values. The free spirit is a Zarathustran who creates their own law
tables and disciplines themselves to think afresh and for themselves.
This, they imagine, is no easy win for thoughts, ideas and values are
insidious and hard to see until they are exposed. The idea here is
similar to a saying of Jesus from Lukeâs gospel which Renzo Novatore may
have himself referenced earlier:
âOnce Jesus was asked by the Pharisees when the kingdom of God was
coming and he answered, âThe kingdom of God is not coming with things
that can be observed; nor will they say âLook here it is!â or âThere it
is!â For, in fact, the kingdom of God is among you.ââ
What is translated here from Greek as âamong youâ can also quite
legitimately be rendered âwithin youâ â and many modern bibles have a
textual note from the translators to this effect. The importance of this
translation is that Jesus then conceives of his âkingdom of Godâ as a
spiritual thing, a matter of internals like values, beliefs, ideas,
things which animate and motivate someoneâs life, their character. There
are many other ancient texts which have Jesus making similar claims â
although this is not really the time to go into it. [My chapter on Jesus
in Being Human has more on this.] My point is that this applies to an
anarchism of free spirits too for this is an internal thing and it is a
belief which posits that no one could âchange the worldâ â as anarchists
have historically been imagined to want to do â UNLESS THEY WERE
INTERNALLY OF A CONSTITUTION TO BE ABLE TO DO SO. My interpretation of
Jesus is of a person who wanted to create a community with new values
that lived their historical Judaism in a particular way. My
interpretation of anarchism is that it is primarily a view on the
constitution of the human being which, entirely on the basis of that,
opens out into the possibility for social change. In fact, as I have
studied anarchism more and more, I have found it increasingly impossible
to imagine how there could ever be any sort of widespread anarchist
consciousness in public without conscious anarchist people. And that all
starts within, with being what you are. If this means I make of
anarchism a spirituality or a consciousness [and to some extent it does]
then SO BE IT.
This leads me back to a point I have made several times before, however,
this being that ANARCHISM ISNâT, FIRST OF ALL, POLITICAL AND ECONOMIC.
There was a time, I will concede, when it mostly was. This is what the
Kropotkins and the Bakunins and even the Malatestas cared about. But it
wasnât all that Emma Goldman cared about. It wasnât all that Voltairine
de Cleyre cared about. So such exclusive concerns didnât even survive
until the 20^(th) century undisturbed. Historical anarchism, when you
actually study its detail, very quickly splintered, if not shattered,
into individual interpretations. Some joined organisations, yes, but
many others didnât and determined anarchism would be for them what it
meant to them â perhaps shooting the king or robbing banks or stealing
from posh houses and sharing the booty with the poor. I entirely agree
people have a right to do that. I entirely agree, in fact, that some
ignorant anarcho-capitalist who wants you to get into crypto and who has
no knowledge whatsoever of the anarchism of the past, or its various
values, has the right to his ill-informed opinions. Do I think he is
right? No. Do I want to educate him? If I can. But, in the end, he can,
and probably will, think what he likes. Anarchists have to recognise
that this will ALWAYS be the case and that anarchism is not forcing all
people to one view, the right view. There is actually already a name for
that anyway: its called fascism. Its fascism, as Alan Moore points out
in his description of it, which views society as the bundle of uniform
twigs. Anarchism, on the other hand, is the philosophy of free spirits
who grow wild. Or, at least, it should be.
This is why an anarchism of free spirits sees anarchism as as much an
intellectual and moral phenomenon as it does a political and economic
one. Should people be released from authoritarian government?
Absolutely. Will this be impossible unless we simultaneously release
these same people from economic servitude? Of course. But the free
spirit insists that you must also simultaneously, or as near to
simultaneously as you can, release people from moral servitude and
intellectual servitude as well â these being internal masters which make
your consciousness its slave. You must, in fact, create free thinking
people who are not bound to a uniform view if you then want them to go
on to insist on their political and economic freedom. Otherwise you
might be in a situation where you free the slaves â but then, having no
idea how to operate for themselves, they simply wander back to their old
masters. The historic anarchist emphasis on education among anarchists
is exactly what this is all about, in fact, for anarchists have always
insisted that you canât just free people and they have further added
that they must be educated to such a point that they desire, and act
towards, their own freedom. [Malatestaâs âWe anarchists do not want to
emancipate the people; we want the people to emancipate themselvesâ will
never not be relevant here.] The free spirit is one who knows all about
this for they have reached that self-educational point and desire their
own freedom; in fact, they insist on it. This is what classical
anarchists imagined in general and the free spirit is all in favour of
that. But this then means that we must stop harping on, in a singular
way, about an external politico-economic anarchism as if this was all
that anarchism was about and realise that how people think and who
people are is just as vital as, if not more vital than, this. Without
free spirits, who are we expecting to free anyone from political and
economic chains? If anarchists expect people to FREE THEMSELVES then how
can they do that unless they are free spirits?
The point here is that anarchism exists at all because, historically,
there have been anarchists. The material individual reality is the
important thing here which is to say, as Novatore did, that what really
counts here is real people and their lives â not ideas, not goals, not
beliefs: people. Let me regale you now with a couple of metaphorical
pictures before I rise to my ultimate point:
First, imagine a highly coiffured garden tended by a person who clearly
wants everything just so. Plants, bushes and shrubs are all perfectly
placed according to a pre-determined plan, everything is subject to
precise horticulture so it produces a perfectly symmetrical display, the
lawn is cut with scissors so that the grass is an exact and uniform
length. The result is a garden full of straight lines and pristine
appearance where there is not so much as a stray leaf. Now imagine
another garden grown wild. Nothing is the same in this garden, there are
no straight lines and every living thing there grows uncoerced. Some
plants are big, reaching out towards the sun, whilst others wither and
die. Here, the dice fall as they may and no one is tending to everything
so that it is just so. Each organism does the best that it can in its
circumstances, using whatever alliances it can make.
A second allegory. Imagine the world as a vast open prison. It shouldnât
be too hard for in many places today you canât even raise your voice,
slip off your clothes or act differently to how all the other people are
acting before some policeman â an official one with a badge or one of
the unofficial ones who have fallen in line with societyâs morals and
dictates â steps in to coerce your behaviour. In this open prison where,
as Sartre said, âHell is other peopleâ, you have to watch yourself every
step because someone is always ready to snitch on you to someone
official whilst, in many public places cameras of many different kinds
stand ready to catch you doing something someone else has decided you
shouldnât do. You were born into this prison and that you had leaders
above you and laws to follow upon that birth was already decided and
taken out of your hands. Now, all you must do is obey. Yet,
nevertheless, here and there in this open prison there are people who
insist they are liberated. They refuse their voluntary servitude. They
donât buckle under or get with the program. They donât accept that their
lives were taken away from them, are subject to control by others, and
that they are prisoners with a measure of freedom by the grace of
others. They declare their emancipation and that they will live free â
up to and including if the police and prison guards come for them. They
insist on creating their own context.
The free spirit here is, of course, a plant in the wild garden and the
âprisonerâ who declares their liberation â for the free spirit is, to
use a further metaphor, the cat who refuses to be herded. Only such
people can ever create âanarchismâ because only the genuine and
authentic interaction of free people can ever create an anarchism which
is conceived of as the uncoerced freedom of wilderness. The image of
this anarchism is then precisely the wild garden and not the coiffured
one â although there are several people who call themselves
âorganisationalâ or âsocialâ anarchists who think the coiffured garden
is an image of an anarchist future. I contradict them. I oppose them. I
say they are deceiving themselves by confusing a kind of order with
freedom. I say that the only anarchism worth the name is a wild
anarchism of lives lived and alliances forged in the midst of life on an
ad hoc basis [just like a mycorrhizal network, in fact]. Anarchism is
emancipation from external order which, in one way or another, is always
going to be based on coercion or control. Whether this is hostile [as in
the prison] or benevolent [as in the garden] does not really matter for
that it is coercion or control at all is the important thing. So I am
saying that we see a life as like a plant which just wants to grow as
strong and as tall as it can in order to exist in good health rather
than seeing it as the whole garden that â due to some controlling urge
to order â needs to be planned and prodded into an entirely unnatural
symmetry. [I have, as an aside, always hated those big planned out
gardens. Show me something growing wild, it is much better.] Anarchists
are not gardeners, they are they plants. Anarchists are certainly not
jailers, they are not even prisoners. They insist on living free and
independently.
So I deny, in the end, that anarchism is order or a will to
organisation. This does not mean that anarchists cannot cooperate or
organise themselves. But âthemselvesâ is the important word there and
not âorganiseâ. Of course the achievement of certain goals, desirable
goals no doubt, takes cooperation â but cooperation should always come
from below as an act of will and never from above by pressure or
manipulation or requirement. The free-spirited anarchist impulse is to
grow wild, that which, in organisational terms, would be regarded as in
a decentralised, unplanned way, because an anarchism of free spirits, of
those who think for themselves and go their own way, will ALWAYS BE THE
BEST DEFENCE AGAINST CENTRALISED CONTROL. ALL anarchists seek to defeat
such centralised control so this is really a question of the best way to
achieve that. I submit that it is not by creating anarchist structures
and organisations and institutions which, in the end, are only new
conduits to coerce and gerrymander outcomes. The free spirit trades
letting things fall as they may for the ability to, in the words of Alan
Moore from V for Vendetta, live a life of âDo As You Pleaseâ. Their life
is a contingent one with no guarantees and not a wholly imaginary
utopian future peace and harmony. It is the free spiritâs intuition that
you cannot, can never, create such a thing on purpose and that, in
wanting to, you only trade one kind of illegitimate coercion for
another, one labelled âbenevolentâ. But benevolent according to who? No,
says the free spirit. Leave people really and genuinely free and let the
rest take care of itself. Or, in Daoist terms, do nothing and nothing
will be left undone. âAnarchismâ, much less âanarchyâ, is not something
anarchists should set out to create; it is something that should form
organically, all by itself, because of the actions and interactions of
free spirits and free people. It is this entirely biological, natural
metaphor that should be our guiding, and dancing, star.
With love,
ANARQXISTA GOLDMAN X