💾 Archived View for tilde.town › ~vidak › metaphysics › conspectus.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 03:08:44. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Conspectus on Idealist Naturalism

Blair Vidakovich (2022)

The argument for Idealism is derived from the Pittsburgh Hegelian

school's famous epithet that the "space of reasons is _sui

generis_". However these followers of Sellars have usually opted to

become what they describe as "expressivists" with respect to

normativity. That is to say, the meaning of a proposition with

normative content is simply an expression of support for, or a

rejection of its meaning.

Huw Price, although technically of Cambridge and Australian ilk, would

not find resistance from the likes of say, Robert Brandom when it

comes to specifying the metaphysical status of a normative

concept. Both would regard moral facts as objects of a dubious

trustworthiness. Indeed, while both avowed 'Pragmatists', as far as

intellectual allegiances go, they have have, in fact, embraced the

Empiricist horn of the traditions contained within Pragmatism.

It is true that the phrase, the 'space of reasons' finds its origin in

Wilfrid Sellars. It may be that Sellars approved of the general thrust

of the full phrase 'the space of reasons is _sui generis_". But the

most consistent and incisive advocates for taking this slogan

seriously have been philosophers like Joseph Rouse, John Haugeland,

John McDowell, and Rebecca Kukla--among others: such as _ from UNSW.

I similarly agree with the spirit of Richard Gaskin's individualist

Idealist rendering of McDowell's _Mind and World_, even if I disagree

profoundly with his understanding of what constitutes Idealism.

The overall upshot of the supposed _sui generis_ nature of the space

of reasons stems from Sellars's belief that the 'Scientific Image' of

the world introduced to the world by the European philosophers of the

Renaissance _develops out of_ the common sense, lay epistemological

perspective of the world.

Now this observation, or conviction that the (Natural) Scientific

Image of the world is, say, an emergent aspect of an ordinary person's

epistemological and experential grasp on the objective world just

means that the Scientific Image develops out of the space of reasons.

The term 'space of reasons' can be rendered more or less

formalistically, but it can be further explained by making a passing

reference to the Early Wittgenstein of the _Tractatus_. Wittgenstein's

picture of his logical atomism was on in which all the irreducible

logical ements would form a complex--albeit static and mechanical--web

of logical linkages and enlightening inferences. The space of reasons

is a metaphor by way of Sellars which captures the spirit of what

Ludwig Wittgenstein was trying to say, while avoiding all of the

significant unpleasant consequences of, say, among other aspects of

Wittgenstein's philosophy, logical positivism.

The space of reasons is a metaphor which images the reasoning agents

within its area as, say, sharing a certain volume of physical space,

and it were as if the agents navigated the structure of their analysis

of some problems, or constucture of some translation (a la Quine), or

generation of some communication for its reception to another volume

of space--or within the space (a la Habermas).

Indeed people like Terence Cuneo have explicitly employed the simile

of a 'web' of facts (which deliberating and reasonsing agents

navigate).

So my argument is that we should assert that the space of reasons is

_sui generis_. I think this is a reasonable assumption or first

axiom. It also does justice to the idea of the democratisation and

broader acceptance of philosophy. It must absolutely be true that, as

the ordinary everyday mundane experience of reality forms the basis

out which the Natural Sciences emerge with their 'disenchanted' (or,

shall we say, with a little more jargon--deflationist?) picture or

framing of the world outside our minds.

From this is follows that the Scientific Image of the world is a

creation from the elements of the space of reasons. You may, at some

stage object that I have mischaracterised the mundane ordinary

experience of the world. Some might say, for instance, that my

understadning of what Sellars called the 'Human Image' of the world is

wildly optimistic. To this I would respond with the observation that

the tendency to oscillate from Hobbes to Rousseau on the question of

politicially, philosophically--perhaps morally (etc.)--unorganised or

uninitiated peoples is based on a myth about the people who existed

outside of Europe at the time of the Renaissance and

Enlightenment--see Graeber's posthumously published book _The Dawn of

Everything_, which, with expert reasoning and eye-opening new

anthropological evidence, powerfully debunks the idea that _any_ human

civilisation at _any_ time existed in permanent states of social

organisation. Perhaps this is the true force of the _sui generis_

nature of the space of reasons.

The conclusion of the argument I am making is that, by analogy to

Kant's division of the human mind into noumenal and phenomenal

processing dimensions--we may be entitled to say Idealism is permitted

because the structure between the (a) space of reasons; and (b) the

Scientific Image of the world is isomorphic with Kant's distinction

between _Practical_ and _Theoretical Reason_.

The components of the space of reasons, and intrinsically value-laden

'logical space' or logical 'web'. While we may reserve the

specification of the structural content of the space of reasons, we

may indeed draw a close analogy between Kant's _Practical Reason_ and

the space of reasons.

By comparison, Sellars's term the _Scientific Image_ maps neatly onto

Theoretical Reason--,e, the mechanical-phenomena processor, the

Understanding. The Faculty of the Understanding is _also_ the very

centre of the phenomenal aspect of the Kantian philosophy of

mind. This 'region' of the 'web' of Kant's philosophy is an

explanation for how the Renaissance mechanical philosophy of the

cosmos is possible, and objective. The noumenal aspect of the Kantian

philosophy of mind, however stands out in stark--and sometimes

antinomial(!)--opposition to the 'Scientific Image' of the Faculty of

Understanding.

In passing, it is perhaps worth observing that Kant's is a philosophy

which practices 'enlightened ecclecticism'. That is, one can imagine

the _Critique of Pure Reason_ as a highly modular philosophy. Indeed

we have seen--most notably Strawson--sever what they considered to be

unpleasant or untenable aspects of Kant's philosophy frmo what they

deemed could be retained. Most notably missing from Strawson's

reassembly of Kant was the noumenal dimension of the person.

Yet am I not drawing favourable parallels between the space of reasons

and Kant's imagined and fantastic noumenal aspect of the mind? Is what

I am advancing seem like the opposite of Strawson--and for that reason

is what I am trying to argue absolutely unacceptable?

I think this is where the analogy between Kant and the more

Wittgensteinian space of reasons ends. We should elect not to adopt

_Kant's_ supplied substance of the purview of Practical Reason.

Let us return to why the analogy between Sellars and Kant was

productive for our discussion. What I have discussed above amounts to

this--if it is true that the space of reasons is _sui generis_ i.e.,it

exists as the human concept of the mind before all other

conceptions--and I argue that it is--then it is as if Kant's story had

been less modular and structured monistically: Theoretical Reason

emerges forth from Practical Reason.

That is: the ordinay, value-laden experience and activity that

everyday people practice with more-or-less reasonable skill and

success is the foundation for the (Natural) Scientific Image of the

world.

If this is true--and I argue that it is--then we are entitled to stand

Simon Blackburn's scathing criticism of Liberal Naturalism in

_Normativity a la mode_ on its head! You will remember that Simon

Blackburn is more-or-less of one mind with the expressivists Brandom

and Price about the metaphysical status of values, meaning, and

normativity in their philosophies of the mind. To Blackburn it is as

if the doubter of the radical deflationism about the role of morality

in human discourse is 'helping themselves' to extra philosophical

concepts in their explanations of Objectivity, Truth, Justice, etc.

WHen conceived according to the narrative I have suggested, to me it

seems as if the expressivists, emotivists, or quasi-realists, in short

_anti-realists_ about normativity, are bizarre ascetics about the

human mind, human morality, meaning--what have you.

Whereas Blackburn would ridicule my position that humans are first

imbued with meaning, and from there learn how to access the concepts

of Natural Sciace, I would regard much of the moral or axiological

anti-realist narratrive about the metaphysical status of human moral

discourse as extreme Scientism.

If the explanation I am offering in favour of Idealism is at all

acceptable, it will also be partly because it is not unamenable to a

philosophical legacy which the expressivists aim to do service

to--Naturalism.

There are many and various ways to define Naturalism. We should

certainly not accept the legacy of W. V. O. Quine on this

topic--primarily because he would probably very much approve of the

efforts of the contemporary anti-realists. Quine would claim that,

given the natural sciences are what they are, Naturalism just meanins

philosophy must never contradict, and must, with as similar method and

metaphysics as possible, deal in philosophical discourse in ways which

are intimately integrated with the Natural Sciences.

Most Liberal Naturalists have attempted to allow discourse about

normativity to be philosophically analysed by relaxing the strength of

shall we call it, "Quinean Naturalism".

I rather agree with Roy Bhaskar's much mroe confident approach to

providing an alternative to Quinean Naturalism. Bhaskar astutely

observes that, formally, all Naturalism amounts to is that the methods

(and, one could even strengthen this claim by adding the _objects_ as

well) of science and philosophy must be the same. Where Quine knuckles

under is by accepting a further substantive premise: that the methods

of the Natural Sciences are to be taken as they are currently given,

and cannot be questioned by philosophy.

Bhaskar's agnosticism about the informativeness about the current

content/substance of the current Natural Sciences is refreshing on

this point. He then proceeds--in _The Possibility of Naturalism_--to

attempt to deduce a Naturalist scientific realist philosophy that is

consistent with the methods of the sciences _however they are to be

conceived_. Bhaskar's position seems to make more sense to me: a

philosophy is a Naturalist one just by virtue of having the same

methods as the Natural Sciences.

I think we should appropriate the term Naturalism for ourselves simply

becase the concepts of the Scientific Image are to be drawn from

elements of its superset--the space of reasons. In this way, we can

say we have an Idealist brand of Naturalism not unknown to the great

Renaissance Rationalists Spinoza, Leibniz, later to be followed in the

Enlightenment by Goethe and Hegel.

_Because_ the space of reasons provides the foundation for the image

the Natural Sciences have of the world, we should regard the elements

of the Scientific Image as _just being_ elements of the space of

reasons. Because the _content_ of the Scientific Image of the world

_just is_ also the elements from the space of reasons, this Idealist

view of the mind can also help itself to the label 'Naturalist'.

The argument only gets stronger once the actual content of the space

of reasons, and, within it, the Scientific Image, is delimited and

specified. In this way it can be exhaustively demonstrated exactly

what the 'method' of this Idealist Naturalism comprises.

The Assault on Common Sense

There is in some naturalisms a direct route from moral anti-realism,

to an assault on the way ordinary life is to be understood. These

naturalisms are the orthodoxy. Indeed the standard image of naturalism

is one which devalues the understandings of common sense. I want to

defend the actual capacity people display when they reason.

The lack of faith many naturalists display in ordinary, everyday

concerns and wisdoms is a function of a flase model of what the every,

ordinary reasoning agent is.

I want to first give demonstrations of the problem of what the

orthodoxy considers a practical reasonsing person to be. Then, I will

turn to my positions on the matter. Where naturalism and common sense

philosophy intersect, I think the solutions lie. But I can give

priority to 'common sense' where I can, as naturalism has a tendency

to forget Ockham's Razor. But my more thorough explanation for why we

should rank common sense discourse as a first class citizen in our

philosophical projects is that I count meaning--sense-making--as _sui

generis_ in the everyday persons's concept of mind.

We are suffering from a crisis in faith in rationality and compassion

in our society. It is becoming more difficult to wrest back the

ability to communicate the values of critical thinking to whom we lost

it. Ordinary people are desperate for a deeper, more fulfilling

life. Indeed now, more than ever non-philosophers are concerned about

the Good Life, and many have determinate, concrete conceptions of what

that Good Life looks like.

Naturalism arrives on the scene armed ready to discuss and share the

full complement of truth-elucidating weaponry it has. It is hard to

believe, imagining oneself as untrained philosophically, that

naturalists have arrived in the discourse with the intention to play

nice.

Indeed too often naturalism does _not_ think and act in terms of

individualities, multiplicities, or pluralities. Naturalism represents

an Imperialists force in our society, as it very often refuses to

engage in _educational_ discussion, opting to coerce and mock.

Naturalism's creed is that what is, is natural, and whaterver is

non-natural, is not. The concept of naturalism is couterposed to

_super_naturalism. Naturalism might have allied itself with its less

radical "Liberal" Naturalism, but historically, what we have observed

is the dominant orthodox naturalist claim turn and attack its

non-reductionist, non-eliminativist, more 'liberal' critics.

Naturalism might also have attempted to communicate and educate for

others. The tone it set while adducing its 'discoveries' from the hard

natural sciences couild have been conciliatory, and empathetic. BNut,

it has not been so. The ire of philosophical naturalism has not left

any other more 'liberal' or oppositional metaphysics unnoticed.