đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for tilde.town â€ș ~vidak â€ș metaphysics â€ș dialectical-naturalism.gmi captured on 2022-01-08 at 13:47:09. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

My Theory of Dialectical Naturalism

I began my philosophy of dialectical naturalism by being very inspired

by the philosophy of mind that John McDowell developed in his John

Locke Lectures in the 90s, and published in book form in Mind and

World.

McDowell is first a Wittgensteinian quietist, and a Hegelian second. I

am a Hegelian, and in no way a Wittgensteinian. So the message that I

lifted from *Mind and World* is one that is at odds with McDowell's

philosophy.

McDowell only figures concepts that humans understand and possess to

inhabit the Fregean level of 'sense'. I take it to mean that concepts

are situated in the level of 'reference'. So when McDowell takes it to

mean that concepts are, fundamentally, ephemeral human constructions

that do not actually inhabit the objective world, I disagree. I am a

strong conceptual realist. I hold that concepts are objects that exist

in the world whether or not humans existed, and whether or not humans

are aware about them.

I also differ from McDowell in my characterisation of what a concept

is. McDowell accepts some of Kant's story, only some of Hegel's story,

and parts of Aristotle when dealing with concepts. On the whole,

McDowell is a Kantian about concepts—he pictures them to be

mentalistic relationships that help humans make judgements. I do not

agree with this either. I take a concept to be an Aristotelian

Hegelian concept. That is, it is the objective or actual expression of

some essence. It is something's formal-final cause. In this way, I do

not admit of concepts as mentalistic objects. This has an important

effect on the theory of truth that this philosophy espouses. Truth and

reality are not foundationalist. Truths and facts are not atomic,

static blocks that are either 'all' or 'nothing' about their validity

and soundness.

In this way, foundationalism treats 'truth' and 'reality' as

interchangeable labels. I make a distinction between truth and

realness. I admit that everything is real, or, as McDowell says, a

fact is something that is the case, and that the world is a totality

of facts, but, I say some things are more true that others.

What makes something more true than something else? The more perfectly

is expresses its essence. Something with totally expresses its essence

is perfectly true. So, for me, as it does not for McDowell, a concept

is also teleological: hence it is a formal-final cause of an object.

But, apart from these differences, I am very inspired by the story

that McDowell tells in *Mind and World*: The mind is divided into two

sorts of processes when judgements about the world. These sorts of

relationships explain how we are perfectly in touch with the

world. This is a direct realist theory of mind. Elsewhere, people have

labelled this theory of mind as a “conduit theory of experience”. To

my mind, this moniker is accurate. This is not a representationalist

theory of experience—it is an 'identity' theory of experience.

An 'identity' theory of experience does not picture the mind as

mirroring or copying the content about the world when it is

experiencing. This is normally how theories of mind are

expounded. Instead, the content of the world directly figures directly

in the mind.

The first process that the mind possesses in order to be perfectly in

touch with the world is the faculty of sensibility, and the second the

faculty of spontaneity.

Sensibility takes the content of the world that it experiences and

delivers it up to spontaneity. Sensibility is completely uncritical

and passive with respect to the content of the world. It is the

faculty of spontaneity which forms (what Kant would call) judgements

about the world.

So, I admit of the Kantian philosophy of mind: I view the mind as

being divided into Receptivity and Spontaneity.

However, unlike McDowell, I do not leave any ambiguities about whether

or not this explanation is dualistic. I take it that what the

Sellarsian philosophers call the 'space of reasons' to extend all the

way down to the level of sensibility.

This, for me, means that the world is enchanted with meaning and value

in the sense that McDowell derides in *Mind and World*: there is meaning

in the fall of a sparrow as there is in a book.

Let me pause for a moment, and explain why I take this to be true,

before discussing its highly attractive political implications.

McDowell seems to be happy saying that the 'space of concepts' extends

into sensibility, but not the space of reasons. Only the faculty of

spontaneity inhabits the space of reasons.

I think this explanation, which has to be gleaned from a close textual

interpretation and logical reconstruction of McDowell's ideas in Mind

and World, means McDowell's philosophy is ultimately dualist, and if

we are to keep what we like about McDowell's theory of mind—which is

that the world is imbued with meaning.

McDowell is seated somewhere between a Humean and a Kantian on the

question of what it exactly means to have a disenchanted experience of

the world at the level of sense-data, and an enchanted and rational

one at the level of conceptual articulation.

A Humean fully accepts what McDowell calls the 'Myth of the

Given'. This is that human experience of the world is deterministic

and completely disenchanted. Humeans structure the logical categories

of the Sellarsians in this way:

First, the space of nature, which is identical with the realm of

scientific intelligibility. Then, the space of reasons is a

subcategory of scientific intelligibility. So, Humeans are

naturalists.

Kantians are anti-naturalists. They accept that the space of nature is

indeed vacated of any meaning, but that there is more that is real

than just the space of nature. Kantians are dualists about truth. We

might image that they speak of the 'space of the real', of which the

space of reasons and the realm of scientific intelligibility are

cohabitants.

I do not like either of these stories, and I do not like McDowell's

either. McDowell pictures the 'space of concepts' as a superset of the

space of reasons. So, if we understand McDowell correctly, there are

meaningful concepts, and concepts which are devoid of meaning. In this

way, the space of nature is the home to both the realm of natural

scientific intelligibility, and the space of reasons as well.

I take this to still be a dualism. The picture that I prefer is that

the space of reasons is identical with the space of nature.

The political implications of (what I call) this philosophy of

dialectical naturalism is that humans can perceive moral facts in the

same way as they can experience epistemic facts. If it is true that

there are moral facts with the same alethic properties as epistemic

facts, then it follows that there must be a good or a right way for

humans to live.

Ultimately, I am, with this above metaphysics, interested in

constructing a philosophy of objective morality. This account of

morality is a virtue ethical account. The broad aim of my project is

to produce a list of virtues about how the social ecology of humans

should be structured. The list of virtues I will produce apply to

humans both individually and collectively. The social system that my

philosophy outlines is a communist one. I aim to demonstrate that the

organisation of human life around the ‘needs principle’ is the morally

objectively correct way to live.

I argue that organising the totality of human life around ‘from each

according to their ability, to each according to their need’ provides

the best way for humans to flourish.