đž Archived View for beyondneolithic.life âş articles âş does_time_flow.gmi captured on 2021-11-30 at 20:18:30. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
By Natalie Wolchover
Quanta Magazine
The laws of physics imply that the passage of time is an illusion. To avoid this conclusion, we might have to rethink the reality of infinitely precise numbers.
Strangely, although we feel as if we sweep through time on the knife-edge between the fixed past and the open future, that edge â the present â appears nowhere in the existing laws of physics.
In Albert Einsteinâs theory of relativity, for example, time is woven together with the three dimensions of space, forming a bendy, four-dimensional space-time continuum â a âblock universeâ encompassing the entire past, present and future. Einsteinâs equations portray everything in the block universe as decided from the beginning; the initial conditions of the cosmos determine what comes later, and surprises do not occur â they only seem to. âFor us believing physicists,â Einstein wrote in 1955, weeks before his death, âthe distinction between past, present and future is only a stubbornly persistent illusion.â
The timeless, pre-determined view of reality held by Einstein remains popular today. âThe majority of physicists believe in the block-universe view, because it is predicted by general relativity,â said Marina CortĂŞs, a cosmologist at the University of Lisbon.
However, she said, âif somebody is called on to reflect a bit more deeply about what the block universe means, they start to question and waver on the implications.â
Physicists who think carefully about time point to troubles posed by quantum mechanics, the laws describing the probabilistic behavior of particles. At the quantum scale, irreversible changes occur that distinguish the past from the future: A particle maintains simultaneous quantum states until you measure it, at which point the particle adopts one of the states. Mysteriously, individual measurement outcomes are random and unpredictable, even as particle behavior collectively follows statistical patterns. This apparent inconsistency between the nature of time in quantum mechanics and the way it functions in relativity has created uncertainty and confusion.
Over the past year, the Swiss physicist Nicolas Gisin has published four papers that attempt to dispel the fog surrounding time in physics. As Gisin sees it, the problem all along has been mathematical. Gisin argues that time in general and the time we call the present are easily expressed in a century-old mathematical language called intuitionist mathematics, which rejects the existence of numbers with infinitely many digits. When intuitionist math is used to describe the evolution of physical systems, it makes clear, according to Gisin, that âtime really passes and new information is created.â Moreover, with this formalism, the strict determinism implied by Einsteinâs equations gives way to a quantum-like unpredictability. If numbers are finite and limited in their precision, then nature itself is inherently imprecise, and thus unpredictable.
Physicists are still digesting Gisinâs work â itâs not often that someone tries to reformulate the laws of physics in a new mathematical language â but many of those who have engaged with his arguments think they could potentially bridge the conceptual divide between the determinism of general relativity and the inherent randomness at the quantum scale.
âI found it intriguing,â said Nicole Yunger Halpern, a quantum information scientist at Harvard University, responding to Gisinâs recent article in Nature Physics. âIâm open to giving intuitionist mathematics a shot.â
CortĂŞs called Gisinâs approach âextremely interestingâ and âshocking and provocativeâ in its implications. âItâs really a very interesting formalism that is addressing this problem of finite precision in nature,â she said.
Gisin said itâs important to formulate laws of physics that cast the future as open and the present as very real, because thatâs what we experience. âI am a physicist who has my feet on the ground,â he said. âTime passes; we all know that.â
Information and Time
Gisin, 67, is primarily an experimenter. He runs a lab at the University of Geneva that has performed groundbreaking experiments in quantum communication and quantum cryptography. But he is also the rare crossover physicist who is known for important theoretical insights, especially ones involving quantum chance and nonlocality.
On Sunday mornings, in lieu of church, Gisin makes a habit of sitting quietly in his chair at home with a mug of oolong tea and contemplating deep conceptual puzzles. It was on a Sunday about two and a half years ago that he realized that the deterministic picture of time in Einsteinâs theory and the rest of âclassicalâ physics implicitly assumes the existence of infinite information.
Consider the weather. Because itâs chaotic, or highly sensitive to small differences, we canât predict exactly what the weather will be a week from now. But because itâs a classical system, textbooks tell us that we could, in principle, predict the weather a week on, if only we could measure every cloud, gust of wind and butterflyâs wing precisely enough. Itâs our own fault we canât gauge conditions with enough decimal digits of detail to extrapolate forward and make perfectly accurate forecasts, because the actual physics of weather unfolds like clockwork.
Now expand this idea to the entire universe. In a predetermined world in which time only seems to unfold, exactly what will happen for all time actually had to be set from the start, with the initial state of every single particle encoded with infinitely many digits of precision. Otherwise there would be a time in the far future when the clockwork universe itself would break down.
But information is physical. Modern research shows it requires energy and occupies space. Any volume of space is known to have a finite information capacity (with the densest possible information storage happening inside black holes). The universeâs initial conditions would, Gisin realized, require far too much information crammed into too little space. âA real number with infinite digits canât be physically relevant,â he said. The block universe, which implicitly assumes the existence of infinite information, must fall apart.
He sought a new way of describing time in physics that didnât presume infinitely precise knowledge of the initial conditions.
The modern acceptance that there exists a continuum of real numbers, most with infinitely many digits after the decimal point, carries little trace of the vitriolic debate over the question in the first decades of the 20th century. David Hilbert, the great German mathematician, espoused the now-standard view that real numbers exist and can be manipulated as completed entities. Opposed to this notion were mathematical âintuitionistsâ led by the acclaimed Dutch topologist L.E.J. Brouwer, who saw mathematics as a construct. Brouwer insisted that numbers must be constructible, their digits calculated or chosen or randomly determined one at a time. Numbers are finite, said Brouwer, and theyâre also processes: They can become ever more exact as more digits reveal themselves in what he called a choice sequence, a function for producing values with greater and greater precision.
By grounding mathematics in what can be constructed, intuitionism has far-reaching consequences for the practice of math, and for determining which statements can be deemed true. The most radical departure from standard math is that the law of excluded middle, a vaunted principle since the time of Aristotle, doesnât hold. The law of excluded middle says that either a proposition is true, or its negation is true â a clear set of alternatives that offers a powerful mode of inference. But in Brouwerâs framework, statements about numbers might be neither true nor false at a given time, since the numberâs exact value hasnât yet revealed itself.
Thereâs no difference from standard math when it comes to numbers like 4, or ½, or pi, the ratio of a circleâs circumference to its diameter. Even though pi is irrational, with no finite decimal expansion, thereâs an algorithm for generating its decimal expansion, making pi just as determinate as a number like ½. But consider another number x thatâs in the ballpark of ½.
Say the value of x is 0.4999, where further digits unfurl in a choice sequence. Maybe the sequence of 9s will continue forever, in which case x converges to exactly ½. (This fact, that 0.4999⌠= 0.5, is true in standard math as well, since x differs from ½ by less than any finite difference.)
But if at some future point in the sequence, a digit other than 9 crops up â if, say, the value of x becomes 4.999999999999997⌠â then no matter what happens after that, x is less than ½. But before that happens, when all we know is 0.4999, âwe donât know whether or not a digit other than 9 will ever show up,â explained Carl Posy, a philosopher of mathematics at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem and a leading expert on intuitionist math. âAt the time we consider this x, we cannot say that x is less than ½, nor can we say that x equals ½.â The proposition âx is equal to ½â is not true, and neither is its negation. The law of the excluded middle doesnât hold.
Moreover, the continuum canât be cleanly divided into two parts consisting of all numbers less than ½ and all those greater than or equal to ½. âIf you try to cut the continuum in half, this number x is going to stick to the knife, and it wonât be on the left or on the right,â said Posy. âThe continuum is viscous; itâs sticky.â
Hilbert compared the removal of the law of excluded middle from math to âprohibiting the boxer the use of his fists,â since the principle underlies much mathematical deduction. Although Brouwerâs intuitionist framework compelled and fascinated the likes of Kurt GĂśdel and Hermann Weyl, standard math, with its real numbers, dominates because of ease of use.
Gisin first encountered intuitionist math at a meeting last May attended by Posy. When the two got to talking, Gisin quickly saw a connection between the unspooling decimal digits of numbers in this mathematical framework and the physical notion of time in the universe. Materializing digits seemed to naturally correspond to the sequence of moments defining the present, when the uncertain future becomes concrete reality. The lack of the law of excluded middle is akin to indeterministic propositions about the future.
In work published last December in Physical Review A, Gisin and his collaborator Flavio Del Santo used intuitionist math to formulate an alternative version of classical mechanics, one that makes the same predictions as the standard equations but casts events as indeterministic â creating a picture of a universe where the unexpected happens and time unfolds.
It is a bit like the weather. Recall that we canât precisely forecast the weather because we donât know the initial conditions of every atom on Earth to infinite precision. But in Gisinâs indeterministic version of the story, those exact numbers never existed. Intuitionist math captures this: The digits that specify the weatherâs state ever more precisely, and dictate its evolution ever further into the future, are chosen in real time as that future unfolds in a choice sequence. Renato Renner, a quantum physicist at the Swiss Federal Institute of Technology Zurich, said Gisinâs arguments âpoint in the direction that deterministic predictions are fundamentally impossible in general.â
In other words, the world is indeterministic; the future is open. Time, Gisin said, âis not unfolding like a movie in the cinema. It is really a creative unfolding. The new digits really get created as time passes.â
Fay Dowker, a quantum gravity theorist at Imperial College London, said she is âvery sympatheticâ to Gisinâs arguments, as âhe is on the side of those of us who think that physics doesnât accord with our experience and therefore itâs missing something.â Dowker agrees that mathematical languages shape our understanding of time in physics, and that the standard Hilbertian mathematics that treats real numbers as completed entities âis certainly static. It has this character of being timeless, and that definitely is a limitation to us as physicists if weâre trying to incorporate something thatâs as dynamic as our experience of the passage of time.â
For physicists such as Dowker who are interested in the connections between gravity and quantum mechanics, one of the most important implications of this new view of time is how it begins to bridge what have long been thought of as two mutually incompatible views of the world. âOne of the implications it has for me,â said Renner, âis that classical mechanics is in some ways closer to quantum mechanics than we thought.â
If physicists are going to solve the mystery of time, they have to grapple not just with the space-time continuum of Einstein, but also with the knowledge that the universe is fundamentally quantum, ruled by chance and uncertainty. Quantum theory paints a very different picture of time than Einsteinâs theory. âOur two big theories on physics, quantum theory and general relativity, make different statements,â said Renner. He and several other physicists said this inconsistency underlies the struggle to find a quantum theory of gravity â a description of the quantum origin of space-time â and to understand why the Big Bang happened. âIf I look at where we have paradoxes and what problems we have, in the end they always boil down to this notion of time.â
Time in quantum mechanics is rigid, not bendy and intertwined with the dimensions of space as in relativity. Furthermore, measurements of quantum systems âmake time in quantum mechanics irreversible, whereas otherwise the theory is completely reversible,â said Renner. âSo time plays a role in this thing that we still donât really understand.â
Many physicists interpret quantum physics as telling us that the universe is indeterministic. âFor Chrissakes, you have two uranium atoms: One of them decays after 500 years, and the other one decays after 1,000 years, and yet theyâre completely identical in every way,â said Nima Arkani-Hamed, a physicist at the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton, New Jersey. âIn every meaningful sense, the universe is not deterministic.â
Still, other popular interpretations of quantum mechanics, including the many-worlds interpretation, manage to keep the classical, deterministic notion of time alive. These theories cast quantum events as playing out a predetermined reality. Many-worlds, for instance, says each quantum measurement splits the world into multiple branches that realize every possible outcome, all of which were set in advance.
Gisinâs ideas go the other way. Instead of trying to make quantum mechanics a deterministic theory, he hopes to provide a common, indeterministic language for both classical and quantum physics. But the approach departs from standard quantum mechanics in an important way.
In quantum mechanics, information can be shuffled or scrambled, but never created or destroyed. Yet if the digits of numbers defining the state of the universe grow over time as Gisin proposes, then new information is coming into being. Gisin said he âabsolutelyâ rejects the notion that information is preserved in nature, largely because âthere is clearly new information that is created during a measurement process.â He added, âIâm saying that we need another way of looking at these entire ideas.â
This new way of thinking about information may suggest a resolution to the black hole information paradox, which asks what happens to information swallowed by black holes. General relativity implies that information gets destroyed; quantum theory says itâs preserved. Hence the paradox. If a different formulation of quantum mechanics in terms of intuitionist math allows information to be created by quantum measurements, perhaps it also lets information be destroyed.
Jonathan Oppenheim, a theoretical physicist at University College London, believes information is indeed lost in black holes. He doesnât know if Brouwerâs intuitionism will be the key to showing this, as Gisin contends, but he says thereâs reason to think information creation and destruction might be deeply related to time. âInformation is destroyed as you go forward in time; itâs not destroyed as you move through space,â Oppenheim said. The dimensions that make up Einsteinâs block universe are very different from one another.
Along with supporting the idea of creative (and possibly destructive) time, intuitionist math also offers a novel interpretation of our conscious experience of time. Recall that in this framework, the continuum is sticky, impossible to cut in two. Gisin associates this stickiness with our sense that the present is âthickâ â a substantive moment rather than a zero-width point that cleanly cleaves past from future. In standard physics, based on standard math, time is a continuous parameter that can take any value on the number line. âHowever,â Gisin said, âif the continuum is represented by intuitionistic mathematics, then time canât be cut in two sharply.â Itâs thick, he said, âin the same sense as honey is thick.â
So far, itâs just an analogy. Oppenheim said he had âa good feeling about this notion that the present is thick. Iâm not sure why we have that feeling.â
Gisinâs ideas have prompted a range of responses from other theorists, all with their own thought experiments and intuitions about time to go on.
Several experts agreed that real numbers donât seem to be physically real, and that physicists need a new formalism that doesnât rely on them. Ahmed Almheiri, a theoretical physicist at the Institute for Advanced Study who studies black holes and quantum gravity, said quantum mechanics âprecludes the existence of the continuum.â Quantum math bundles energy and other quantities into packets, which are more like whole numbers rather than a continuum. And infinite numbers get truncated inside black holes. âA black hole may seem to have a continuously infinite number of internal states, but [these get] cut off,â he said, due to quantum gravitational effects. âReal numbers canât exist, because you canât hide them inside black holes. Otherwise theyâd be able to hide an infinite amount of information.â
Sandu Popescu, a physicist at the University of Bristol who corresponds often with Gisin, agreed with the latterâs indeterministic worldview but said he is not convinced that intuitionist math is necessary. Popescu objects to the idea that digits of real numbers count as information.
Arkani-Hamed found Gisinâs use of intuitionist math interesting and potentially relevant to cases such as black holes and the Big Bang where gravity and quantum mechanics come into apparent conflict. âThese questions â of numbers as finite, or fundamentally things that exist, or whether thereâs infinitely many digits, or the digits are made as you go on,â he said, âmight be related to how we should ultimately think about cosmology in situations where we donât know how to apply quantum mechanics.â He too sees the need for a new mathematical language that could âliberateâ physicists from infinite precision and allow them to âtalk about things that are a little bit fuzzy all the time.â
Gisinâs ideas resonate in many corners but still need to be fleshed out. Going forward, he hopes to find a way of reformulating relativity and quantum mechanics in terms of finite, fuzzy intuitionist mathematics, as he did with classical mechanics, potentially bringing the theories closer. He has some ideas about how to approach the quantum side.
One way that infinity rears its head in quantum mechanics is in the âtail problemâ: Try to localize a quantum system, like an electron on the moon, and âif you do that with standard mathematics, you have to admit that an electron on the moon has a super small probability of being also detected on Earth,â Gisin said. The âtailâ of the mathematical function representing the particleâs position âbecomes exponentially small but nonzero.â
But Gisin wonders, âWhat reality should we attribute to a super small number? Most experimentalists would say, âPut it to zero and stop questioning.â But maybe the more theoretically oriented would say, âOK, but there is something there according to the math.â
âBut it depends, now, which math,â he continued. âClassical math, there is something. In intuitionist math, no. There is nothing.â The electron is on the moon, and its chance of turning up on Earth is well and truly zero.
Since Gisin first published his work, the future has grown only more uncertain. Now every day is a kind of Sunday for him, as crisis grips the world. Away from the lab, and unable to see his granddaughters except on a screen, he plans to keep thinking, at home with his mug of tea and garden view.