💾 Archived View for tanelorn.city › ~vidak › old-blog › ilyenkov-leontev-linguistics.gemini captured on 2020-11-07 at 01:35:08. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

⬅️ Previous capture (2020-09-24)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

---

generator: pandoc

title: 'Evald V. Ilyenkov and A. N. Leontev on Language Acquisition'

viewport: 'width=device-width, initial-scale=1.0, user-scalable=yes'

---

2019-11-21T16:03:00+08:00

0.0 Introduction

================

This paper will describe, and then compare and contrast, two very

different 'second-language' acquisition activities. The underlying

philosophical viewpoints that underpin each of the activities will also

be drawn out and discussed. The advantages and short-comings of each of

the approaches underlying the two activities considered in the paper

will be elucidated. The two activities and respective

language-acquisition approaches discussed in this paper are (a) a

memorisation activity, and its corresponding behaviourist underpinning;

and (b) a social peer-interview report exercise and its corresponding

social constructivist underpinning. It will be argued that while

memorisation activities such as the one discussed in the paper are

almost universally incorporated as some component of 'second-language'

acquisition, its philosophical underpinning is fundamentally flawed.

Wrote-learning and memorisation are a function of the wide-spread social

norm that classrooms are the best place to learn languages. Memorisation

caters to the rationalisation of education as an 'outcomes based'

practice, which reifies human existence. Against the behaviourist

philosophical underpinning of memorisation activities and its attendant

consequences for education, it will be argued that a social

constructivist position should be taken towards language acquisition,

such as that embodied in the chosen activity presented.

1.0.0 -- Main Section

=====================

1.1.0 -- Description of Activities

----------------------------------

1.1.1 -- Activity One

The first activity considered in this paper is a very simple one, but it

is more or less ubiquitous within language acquisition programs. It is

actually two different activities, but since the theoretical assumptions

underpinning those two activities are so similar, they will be

considered together as one unit, to give a broader and fuller

understanding of those theoretical assumptions.

The first part of activity one is the memorisation of common English

phrases such as 'good morning!', 'how are you?', and 'congratulations!'

The L1 associated with this part of the activity is French, although one

could just as easily transfer the activity into any other L1. The

substantial content of the activity consists in having the English

phrases (L2) to be learned placed alongside their equivalent French

counterparts (L1). The execution of the activity could be oral, aural,

or written. It would involve memorising the form and content of the

English (L2) phrases with regard to the original French (L1) form and

content.

The second part of the activity is the memorisation of English

homophones. Homophones are words that sound the same, but have different

meanings, and sometimes different spellings. Homophones are particularly

difficult to learn because they seem at first quite arbitrary. This

appearance of arbitrariness usually leads to activities such as this

one, which are based on memorisation and wrote-learning. The purpose of

this activity is to memorise the English (L2) words that are equivalent

to the learner's L1. Again, the execution of this activity could be

oral, aural, written, or some combination of the three.

1.1.2 -- Activity Two

The second activity considered by this paper is called 'conversation

grid'. A grid of questions is drawn up, and learners must converse and

interact with one-another using their L2 in order to record answers to

the questions on the grid. The activity is first modelled by the teacher

and another student, or by two students, and then learners go off by

themselves and learn via their peers. A key facet of this activity is

that it stresses minimal teacher authority. Learners are encouraged to

try dialogue for themselves and 'muddle through'. The activity can be as

easy or as difficult as the level of command of English of the learners

requires. Beginner learners would discuss and record information about

other's hobbies, likes and dislikes, or occupations. More advanced

learners could discuss more abstract topics, and could be required to

write more fuller and complex written answers to the prescribed

questions. The purpose of activity two is to involve learners in social

interaction, as opposed to the first activity. Activity two emphasises

the communication of meaning, as opposed to the mastery of technical

linguistic forms.

1.2.0 -- Theoretical Underpinnings of Activities

------------------------------------------------

The two activities that were chosen to be considered in this paper are

based on very different views about personhood, the mind, and learning.

The two different views manifested in the above two activities will now

be considered.

1.2.1 -- Activity One

---------------------

The theoretical assumptions about the mind and the person that underpin

the first activity can be collectively labelled 'behaviourism'.

Behaviourism, as its name suggests, asserts that the truth about

someone's learning is located in their behaviour, and not in their

consciousness. It is argued that behaviourism is a persuasive way of

viewing learning because of the claim that 'behavioural change can be

perceived objectively and can therefore be measured' (Louw, 1993: 220).

Behaviourism proceeds from the view that

what we have learned cannot be directly perceived; but the resulting
change in behaviour or performance can be. On the basis of our
performance, it can be deduced what and how much we have learned
(Louw, 1993: 220).

Behaviourism proceeds from the vulgar materialist and empiricist view of

the mind that asserts that because consciousness does not disclose

itself as physical or material substance, it shouldn't be considered as

actually real. The resulting theoretical framework that results from

this philosophical assumption resolves all human behaviour into

'stimuli' and 'responses'. The process by which a stimulus results in a

response is called a 'reflex'. Behaviourism treats learning as

'conditioning'. Conditioning is the behaviourist concept for the process

whereby a person's the physical environment is altered in such a way

that they develop new reflexes in order to deal with new stimuli.

1.2.2 -- Activity Two

---------------------

The learning theory called 'social constructivism' underpins the second

activity. If behaviourism can be said to be the 'most primitive' form of

descriptive and explanatory paradigm for learning, social constructivism

could be said to be 'two notches above it'.

The branch of social constructivism that will be accounted for here will

be what has been termed 'activity theory'. Activity theory developed out

of Lev Vygotsky's research on educational psychology. It is premised on

dialectical materialism, a metaphysics that was developed in an attempt

to resolve the 'antimonies \[contradictions\] of bourgeois thought'

(Ilyenkov, 1977). Behaviourism is one side of the main contradiction

within bourgeois thought. It asserts that truth is purely objective and

measurable. The other side of the contradiction is idealism, which

asserts that truth is more or less purely seated in the mind. (Whether

or not cognitivism falls into this latter category is a matter of

debate. Some argue cognitivism is merely an eclectic form of

behaviourism.)

Dialectical materialism, in order to resolve this contradiction (what

describes explains human being and thought? The environment or human

mental states?), asserts that 'it is not \[a person's\] consciousness

that determines their existence, but on the contrary, their social

existence that determines their consciousness' (Lukacs, 1971: 18).

Activity theory expands on this metaphysics by asserting that language

is but one component of a body of objective, but immaterial, socially

constructed thought-forms that mediate subjective human interaction with

the objective environment (Leontev, 1977).

1.3.0 -- Discussion

-------------------

The purpose of this section, the discussion section, is to compare and

contrast the two lessons described above. The purpose of this is to

explain how they are influenced by the above two different theories of

language learning. From this explanation an argument will be built that

asserts that social constructivism points to a deeper and fuller

understanding of second-language acquisition. Very briefly, the

behaviourist recipe for 'learning' an L2 (N.B. this method represents

'classical conditioning', as opposed to 'operant conditioning') is as

follows:

- Identify the learner's L1. The learner's L1 is, for the purposes of

the L2 acquisition, an 'unconditioned stimulus' (UCS) which produces

'unconditioned responses' (UCR). The UCR in this case is the

learner's comprehension of linguistic meaning.

- Pair the UCS with a neutral stimulus, the L2 sought to be 'learned'.

This is memorisation and wrote learning.

- Remove the learner's L1 from the learning environment. Apply to the

learner the neutral stimulus, the L2, the 'conditioned stimulus'

(CS), and this will elicit comprehension in the learner of the L2, a

'conditioned response' (CR) (Louw, 1993: 224).

Abstractly:

- UCS -\> UCR

- UCS + CS -\> UCR

- CS -\> CR

There are two observations that we can make about the first activity and

its behaviourist theoretical underpinning, and they are all a function

of its adherence to a strict notion of positivism. First, the

acquisition of the L2 is treated as discrete 'appropriation'. In other

words, the L2 acquisition is conceptualised as a kind of mathematical

function: L2 goes in, comprehension comes out. Acquisition happens on

one plane of existence. Behaviourists might argue that memorisation

leads to a process behaviourists label 'generalisation', which means

that wrote-learned words should come to be associated with broader

contexts of communication, but as Louw & Edwards (Louw, 1993: 231)

mention, it is not clear whether generalisation is as regular and

predictable as behaviourists claim.

Second, the substance of the L2 to be learned is treated in a formalist

manner. It is treated as form without content. In other words, the L2 is

treated in almost perfect abstraction, within any regard being paid to

the kinds of contexts in which one would use the language. A possible

example of this is the complete lack of ability of the memorisation

activity to help the learner understand the pragmatics that may be

involved in communicating meaning using the words.

The fundamental basis of both of these observed problems with the

memorisation activity is that its positivistic, behaviourist

underpinning posits a view of the human mind and its learning that is

passive and 'contemplative'. It is certainly possible for a behaviourist

to maintain that language is a dynamic and evolving human construction,

but the learning process that they advocate asserts that language is a

monolithic, static body of data that is ready and able to be abstracted

and appropriated formalistically.

In this connection we can recall part of Marx's Theses on Feuerbach: The

chief defect of all materialism up to now ... is that the object,

reality, what we apprehend through our senses, is understood only in the

form of the subject or contemplation; but not as sensuous human

activity, as practice, ... (Ilyenkov, 1977: 224) (Ilyenkov's emphasis).

What this meant was that

\[people were\] considered the passive side of the subject-object
relation, as the determined member of this inter-relation.
Furthermore, man was abstracted here from the combination of social
relations and transformed into an isolated individual. The
\[human\]-environment relations were therefore interpreted as
individual to all the rest, to everything that lay outside the
individual brain and existed independently of it (Ilyenkov, 1977:
225).

But, crucially,

outside the individual, and independently of his will and
consciousness, there existed not only nature but also the social
historical environment, the world of things created by \[humanity's\]
labour, and the system of relations between \[person\] and \[person\],
developed in the labour process. In other words, not only did nature
by itself ('in itself' \[to use Kantian terminology\]) lie outside the
individual, but also humanised nature, altered by labour (Ilyenkov,
1977: 225).

The social constructivist underpinning behind the second activity seeks

to capture and help learners engage with the social historical

environment embodied within language, within the L2. Although the

activity is limited to the classroom environment, which is artificial

and abstract, it can be hoped that the practical execution of the ideas

underpinning the activity will lead to the development of skills by the

learners that will enable them to go out into the real world and use

language the way it really works: as a cultural tool, an artefact that

mediates personal access to objective reality.

The advantage of the second activity over the first is that it relies on

the active participation and involvement of the learner. By conversing

with peers and the teacher, the learner taps into language's function as

a human cultural artefact. Language is a practical, social activity that

requires more than just individualised, abstract memorisation. It

requires grounding in concrete reality in order to be truly meaningful.

In a sense it is 'situated' in different cultural activities that

require active participation, not passive memorisation (Brown, 1989).

3.0.0 -- Conclusion

===================

In this paper, two different activities with very different approaches

to language acquisition were compared and contrasted. The first

activity, based in positivistic behaviourist theoretical assumptions

about learning and the mind, treated language as an abstract,

individualised experience. This position on language acquisition was

argued to be philosophically wanting, lacking in substantiation in

concrete evidence, and normatively unappealing. It was argued that the

second activity rectified the shortcomings of the first. It viewed

language as a body of human cultural signs and understandings that

mediated subjective interaction with objective reality. Language in this

sense was argued to be dynamic, and the underpinnings of the second

activity's approach was argued to be more powerful in both a descriptive

and explanatory sense.

2154.

4.0.0 -- References

===================

- Brown, J. S., Collins, A., & Duguid, P. (1989). Situated cognition

and the culture of learning. Educational Researcher, 18, 32-42.

- Ilyenkov, E. V. (1977). Dialectical logic: essays on its history and

theory. (H. C. Creighton, Trans.) Moscow: Progress Publishers.

Retrieved from

http://www.marxists.org/archive/ilyenkov/works/essays/index.htm

- Leontev, A. N. (1977). Activity and Consciousness. In Philosophy in

the USSR: Problems of Dialectical Materialism (pp. 180-202). Moscow:

Progress Publishers. Retrieved April 5, 2014, from

http://www.marxists.org/archive/leontev/works/1977/leon1977.htm

- Louw, D., & Edwards, D. (Eds.). (1993). Psychology: an introduction

for students in southern Africa. Johannesburg: Lexicon.

- Lukacs, G. (1971). What is Orthodox Marxism? In G. Lukacs, History

and Class Consciousness (pp. 1-26). Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT

Press.