💾 Archived View for tanelorn.city › ~vidak › old-blog › nuclear-deterrence.gemini captured on 2020-09-24 at 01:39:46. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

---

generator: pandoc

title: 'What the Empirical Evidence Says About Nuclear ''Deterrence'''

viewport: 'width=device-width, initial-scale=1.0, user-scalable=yes'

---

2020-03-07T07:59:40Z

Rational deterrence theory developed alongside the advent of nuclear

weapons. The intersection of the two events yielded the concept of

'nuclear deterrence', an idea that has become popular. It asserts that a

real or perceived threat of catastrophic nuclear attack from one state

to another allows that first state to deter the second from certain

causes of action, namely military confrontations. An extended version of

this idea holds that the world is now somehow more peaceful as a result

of interlocking looming threats of nuclear attack.

Nuclear deterrence is largely a deductive theory, and has been

criticised for, among other things, being ahistorical and lacking in

empirical validity. Deterrence proponents have responded by saying that

empirical deterrence scholarship such as comparative case studies have

failed to persuasively challenge the assumptions behind the theory

(Achen & Snidal 1989). This paper will argue that the empirical work

that has been done on deterrence theory, criticising its assumptions and

conclusions, is largely correct. In particular it will be argued that

the conceptual and methodological limitations of the empirical

criticisms of nuclear deterrence theory are not too great to be

overcome---that is, that it is perfectly valid to build social

scientific theories and concepts from empirical observation.

I - Description of The Idea of Nuclear Deterrence

=================================================

Nuclear deterrence will be described before discussing the validity of

the various empirical criticisms that have been levelled against it. The

reason why it must be described is because its use has entered common

parlance, and as such has suffered from great variation and diffusion in

meaning. A fairly rigorous approximation of nuclear deterrence will be

set out in order to provide some terms of reference, so that the

deterrence criticisms coming later will fit into some form of coherent

dialogue.

Nuclear deterrence proceeds from rational choice analyses. When nuclear

deterrence is invoked, the following assumptions are usually implicit:

1. Rational actor assumption. Actors have exogenously given preferences

and choice options, and they seek to optimise preferences in light

of other actors' preferences and options.

2. Principle explanatory assumption. Variation in outcomes is to be

explained by differences in actors' opportunities. (Appeals to

exogenous changes in preferences, or to norms, roles, or culture,

are temporarily or analytically suspended.)

3. Principle substantive assumption. The state acts as if it were a

unitary rational actor. (Changes in personnel, in decision-making

patterns, or in bureaucratic politics are not the explanatory focus

(Achen & Snidal 1989, p. 150).

It follows that a relationship of deterrence is established when a

threat of retaliatory nuclear attack from one state alters the

preference optimisation calculus of another that is attempting to alter

the balance of power in a system. The relationship of deterrence is

meant to be established in the following manner. Let us say that there

are two states in a system and a state of affairs between them such that

there is a stable power 'status quo' in the system before any kind of

relationship of deterrence comes into being. One state is a defender of

the status quo, and the other is an initiator of change of power

relations. Pursuant to the assumptions above, both states exist in

competition and seek to better their position in the system. Both states

perform a calculation of the best decisions to make at any particular

time, and let us say that, given the initiator is savvy to the

preferences and options of the defender (this is important, preferences

being close to 'desires' and options being close to real courses of

action related to capabilities), it has the preference to attack the

defender and alter the status quo. Whether or not it acts on that

preference is based on a calculation that involves weighing up the costs

and benefits of making that act. One of the costs involved in attacking

the defending state is the future threat of it making a retaliatory

attack, as 'punishment'. If the cost of a retaliatory attack from a

defending state is too great, an initiator will be deterred from

challenging the status quo. Hence a relationship of deterrence is

obtained.

A - Credibility

---------------

The problem-solving capacity of deterrence theory concerns the process

by which a defending state actively and purposively influences the

cost/benefit calculation of an initiator's decision to attack and change

the status quo. The focus which most have placed on the ability of

deterrence theory to solve security problems comes from the fact that a

significant portion of the initiator's cost/benefit calculation revolves

around an indeterminacy, something that the initiator cannot work out

with certainty. Relaxing the assumption above that the initiator is

fully aware of preferences and options of the defender, the analyst

encounters the problem that initiator cannot know for sure whether the

defender will have the ability and commitment to fight back after an

attack (Achen & Snidal 1989, p. 151).

The concept that is used to measure the probability by which an

initiator estimates the cost of a defender's ability and commitment to

have a war or some other kind of conflict over the alteration of the

status quo is called deterrence credibility. Working backwards in the

initiator's decision-making process, suppose that a defender's threat to

retaliate is credible. This means that the initiator believes that the

defender has the option to retaliate (not just the desire, but the

capacity exists: the defender has the military means to retaliate after

an attack and is politically free to do so), and that the defender would

find retaliation in its interest if the prize is threatened. Then, if

the threatened retaliatory punishment from the defender exceeds the

gains of the initiator from attacking, the initiator will believe the

attack will make it worse off than by practicing restraint, and will be

deterrable, or deterred from attacking.

B - Reassurance

---------------

By dint of history there is a corresponding nuclear deterrence concept

which is related to nuclear deterrence credibility but is somewhat

different. The concept is called nuclear deterrence stability, and it

comes from extending the idea of credibility by replacing the system of

one initiator and one defender with one which features two actors that

are simultaneous initiators and defenders. Because both actors exist in

the same competitive environment as the credibility model, where both

actors are seeking to satisfy their preferences as much as possible, and

both powers have nuclear weapons, there exists the risk that one actor

may pre-empt the other's nuclear deterrence threats, and totally wipe it

out, yielding a zero-sum win for the pre-empting actor. Stability is, in

this context, a very narrow indicator. It is meant to measure the

'second strike' (or 'strike second') nuclear capacity of either actor in

this system. If both actors have a second strike capacity, they still

have the capacity to form the option of a credible deterrence threat

after they have been attacked with a nuclear arsenal. The trouble with

this---and this introduces some impurities into the rational choice

description of nuclear deterrence---is that there is always the

incentive for both actors strive to build nuclear weapons systems that

deprive their competitor of a second strike capacity, eradicating the

effect of nuclear deterrence entirely. Here the indeterminacy problem of

deterrence credibility becomes transmuted into nuclear reassurance.

Instead of there being some uncertainty to be explained as to the desire

and capacity of a state to attack for the purpose of deterrence, the

problem-solving function of the rational choice schema is set towards

working out whether either actor believes that its competitor won't

attack. The active and purposive component of reassurance is that,

instead of issuing threats, each side seeks to reassure the other that

it won't commit to plans that will see the other side wiped out,

destroying the effectiveness of its deterrence. Reassurance is more or

less the same as deterrence credibility because a state protects its own

deterrence credibility by promising not to harm its competitor's

credibility.

Deterrence and reassurance here turn on the credibility of a retaliatory

attack by a defender which alters the cost/benefit calculation of the

initiator. It is important to note that credibility turns

correspondingly on the perception either generated passively or created

actively (and there is some controversy here to be sure) inside the

initiator about (a) the nature of the defender, and (b) the defender's

interests and intentions. It should be noted that the empirical

literature has much to say about this. For the sake of the current

discussion however, it is important to point out how nuclear deterrence

theory gets around the perception issues inherent in its operation. The

way it gets around the issue of how a defender changes the behaviour of

an initiator is that it tightly controls how either actor thinks. First,

as per the first assumption above, it makes state preferences (the

things they desire) exogenous to the rational choice games through which

it puts them. This means that the things that states want are assumed

beforehand, and held constant so that games can be constructed in a

sensible manner. Second, it makes sure that the behaviour that states

exhibit is related to the choice of those assumed preferences, and not

anything else. Forces such as mistakes, the role of communication and

language, or complex cognitive processes are not the explanatory focus

of the theory.

The reason why it is important to point out the way in which nuclear

deterrence theory gets around the problems of state communication and

interaction is that many of the empirical studies on nuclear deterrence

have raised questions about the validity of these rational choice

assumptions. The big problem with the empirical criticisms of nuclear

deterrence theory, however, is that they proceed from a very different

conceptual and methodological paradigm than that of rational choice

analyses. The fundamental difference between nuclear deterrence theory

and the empirical work that has been done on it is the order in which

theory and evidence is used. This has a real effect on the empirical

approach's ability to verify the descriptive and prescriptive claims

that nuclear deterrence theory makes. Whereas nuclear deterrence theory

is deductive, which abstracts from reality for the purpose of building a

theory which is meant to be conceptually coherent and simple in its

explanatory import, empirical attempts to engage with deterrence are

inductive: observations come first, and typologies and generalisations

come second. Methodologically speaking, nuclear deterrence advocates are

probably less concerned with individual case explanations than analysts

who are attempting to empirically verify the theory. This is significant

because the only way that an empirical study of the validity of nuclear

deterrence can proceed is by conducting case studies. For instance Achen

& Snidal's complaint that empirical case studies don't really address

the concerns behind the method of deductive theories:

\[f\]or theoretical purposes, the difficulty with explaining
individual cases is that there are so many details in every case that
no single theory can reproduce them all, and some evidence can be
found for too wide an array of variables and propositions (Achen &
Snidal 1989, p. 157).

While this is probably an overstatement of the limits of conducting case

studies, there are indeed difficulties with making generalisations with

an empirical inquiry when looking at such a deductive and conceptually

'pure' theory such as nuclear deterrence. As Jervis (1989, p. 195)

notes, when conducting empirical studies,

\[i\]diosyncrasies are many and powerful; similar outcomes can be
reached by many different paths and apparently similar initial
conditions do not always yield the same results. Partly for this
reason and partly because of the limitations of existing research,
what we have no is more a list than a tight theory.

So there is a real divide between the conceptual and methodological

fundamentals of deductive and inductive theories. The typologies between

empirical case studies of nuclear deterrence theory can be incredibly

fluid and varied, and may not rigorously address every facet of the

single deductive theory to which they might be aimed. But the

disadvantages outlined above should come with a qualification. What we

know from the evidence on nuclear deterrence

is not without structure and coherence. Many of the generalisations
produced by the case studies are linked; the inferred processes can
generate additional propositions; and the arguments apply to a wide
range of problems in addition to deterrence and deterrence failures
(Jervis 1989, p. 196).

It is important to discuss all this because treating the empirical

criticisms of nuclear deterrence theory as if they apply directly to

nuclear deterrence's own analytical focus only tells half the story. As

will be shown below, the evidence on nuclear deterrence takes issue with

the way states interact and communicate to be sure, but it doesn't do so

in a way that starts from the same first principles as rational

deterrence theory. The evidence proceeds in a way that holds a lot of

other things constant, and not just the assumptions behind nuclear

deterrence. For instance, the evidence might investigate the possibility

of preference endogeneity with respect to deterrence, but in a way that

sees states as the product of bureaucratic and not unitary

decision-making processes. Despite the piecemeal and highly qualified

progress of empirical work of nuclear deterrence, it should be seen as

valid. The validity comes from its ability to make coherent and

persuasive generalisations that have strong and convincing prescriptive

and descriptive power.

II - Empirical Findings

=======================

Jervis (1979) provides a concrete summary of what the case study

literature finds about the 'reality' of nuclear deterrence. The findings

fall under several headings (or 'themes') and these are: (a) the reality

of state risk-taking behaviour; (b) the role of rewards and concessions

in deterrence; (c) mistakes, and the things that can go wrong; (d) the

limitations of state information-processing and cognition; and (e) the

nature of state interests and commitments---that is, the costs that

states impose on themselves for the purpose of bringing about nuclear

deterrence.

A - Risk-taking

---------------

The first of these themes, risk-taking, is relatively straightforward,

and it relates to the 'brinkmanship' aspect of nuclear deterrence.

Nuclear deterrence theory points towards the use of 'credible threats of

force'---a willingness and capacity to deploy threats of force in order

to deter--- that are meant to alter the cost/benefit analysis of an

initiator's thinking when that initiator wants to change the status quo

power relations. What the empirical evidence says about this process is

that states and state elites of a 'defending' state are often far more

prudent and risk-averse than nuclear deterrence theory would have one

believe. States are very often wary of foreclosing the policy options

that they have available to them, reducing possible courses of action

down to one single choice. The cognitive and information-processing

aspect of this preference-selection phenomenon will obviously discussed

later, but it is significant to note that the rational calculation

aspect of nuclear deterrence suggests that defending state elites should

have no trouble issuing grave threats and managing an incredibly risky

relationship with an initiator, when in reality this does not seem to be

the case at all. What the evidence suggests is that defending and

initiating state elites bargain with each other: defending state elites

prefer to 'trade an increment in their chance of prevailing for an

increment in the chances of maintaining peace' (Jervis 1979, p. 303).

Furthermore, there appear to be different risk-management behaviours for

different kinds of defenders and initiators. If the above were taken to

be a general rule, it would seem that states care less about long-run

strategic considerations than one would expect. This is not the case.

When it comes to great power (say USA versus USSR) deterrence

interactions, long-run considerations feature much more prominently in

state decision-making. This means that either side is much more likely

to retreat and give concessions instead of issuing new threats. This

evidence contradicts nuclear deterrence theory in two ways: first, not

all defenders and initiators are the same, and in certain cases,

defenders will more than not opt to retreat, trusting initiators to not

exploit their concessions.

B - Rewards

-----------

The second theme looks at the role of rewards, instead of threats and

disincentives, in a relationship of nuclear deterrence. The evidence on

this category refers to the way the defender's communication with the

initiator is meant to change that initiator's cost/benefit calculation

when it wants to attack. What nuclear deterrence theory says about the

deterrence relationship is that an initiator's decision calculus is

geared in such a way that only threats of violence from a status quo

defender will influence its operation, and cause it to back down. What

the evidence says on this matter is that threats of disincentives do not

necessarily, or even in most cases, alter an initiator's decision

calculus in a manner that establishes a relationship of deterrence. It

may be that a state has no other option---or thinks it has no other

option---but to be bellicose, and threats of nuclear violence might only

steel its resolve. In instances where things are no so dire, threats of

nuclear violence risk 'humiliating' an initiator state; on this point

the evidence suggests that frequently it is hard for a state to admit

total defeat. Threats of nuclear force may in these circumstances cause

initiator feelings of resentment, and may make deterrence far more

difficult in the future if not couples with some kind of reward or

concession---that is if total deterrence is possible at all.

C - Mistakes and Things That Can Go Wrong

-----------------------------------------

This third theme is a very substantive one, and deals directly with the

'perception issue' inherent in nuclear deterrence's rational choice

paradigm. Mistakes, and things that can go wrong when attempting to

purposively create a relationship of deterrence fall under another four

headings. Deterrence may fail where it is supposed to succeed because

the defender: (i) may fail to understand the other's values; (ii) may

misunderstand the way the initiator sees the world; (iii) may have

incorrect beliefs about the initiator's strength and options; and (iv)

may face extreme difficulty in correctly determining the initiator's

basic intentions.

Each of these four mistakes in judgment on the part of the defender

speaks to the second assumption behind rational deterrence theory. This

assumption causes states behaviour to be explained through their

'opportunities' only---that is, the opportunity that they have to act on

their exogenously given preferences---and not anything else. Not only

does this radically simplify the kinds of behaviours states can have,

but it also says something about the way states are meant to detect and

interpret the behaviours of their counterparts (or 'competitors'). If

the behaviour of states is meant to be tightly linked to their

preferences, per a rational choice paradigm, a defending state should be

able to safely estimate the preferences of an initiator by looking at

its behaviour. However all four of these different types of mistakes and

errors in judgment found in the empirical evidence suggest the opposite.

They suggest that in practice, states have a very difficult time

divining the desires and capabilities of their counterparts.

The explanation in the empirical literature for these difficulties

usually falls within a different analytical paradigm. For instance,

Jervis (1982) stresses the role of the concept of perceptions in

explaining the difficulties states seem to have in correctly working out

information about other states. Perceptions represent a significant

increase in complexity over exogenous preferences and behaviour in terms

of opportunity, because it adds an extra layer of cognitive grey matter

over state interaction. Perceptions depend on the attitudes and values

of the state that is doing the perceiving, and so when interacting with

other states, the perceiving state is heavily conditioned by its own

conscious and unconscious psychological elements. This says something

about the way states perform their supposed rational calculation under

rational choice analyses---this will be discussed next.

D - Information processing and Cognition

----------------------------------------

The fourth theme is not directly related to the three assumptions

outlined above, but nonetheless relates to them closely. Nuclear

deterrence theory asserts that states should be able to perform a

careful and precise rational appraisal of the costs and benefits of

choices when considering bringing about, or reacting to relationships of

deterrence. Typically, there should be very few limits in making

mistakes or errors of judgment when calculating the kinds of choices

involved in executing or reacting to a relationship of deterrence. Note

that this is different from the heading above. The theme above describes

the errors states makes about their counterparts, this theme covers the

expectations that states have about the probabilities of certain things

occurring in general.

The Jervis outlines three errors in rationality that states exhibit in

practice (Jervis 1979, pp. 310-311). The first of these is that states

usually focus on the payoffs involved in the decision-making process,

rather than what should be their true focus of calculation: changes in

event probabilities. The second is very straight forward, and that is

that there is evidence to indicate that even if states have a firm grasp

of the probabilities involved in attempting to engineer a relationship

of deterrence, they don't calculate as precisely as they should. The

third impairment of rationality is that states, even when they have good

estimates of event probabilities, fail to make proper explicit value

trade-offs.

Each of these three errors in cognition are again related to the first

assumption behind rational deterrence theory, that of preference

exogeneity. The theory assumes that states rank and order preferences in

a systematic and unbiased manner. What the evidences suggests about

state rationality is that states don't seem to draw up and scrutinise

policy preferences in such a clear and ordered manner. Some preferences

are more valued than others for cognitive, yet---if one was talking in a

strict sense---irrational reasons, whereas others may not suffer from

being under- or over-valued, but may not be compared and analysed

properly.

E - State Interests and Commitments

-----------------------------------

The fifth and final theme that Jervis describes as emerging from the

body of empirical literature about nuclear deterrence is that of the

nature of state interests and commitments when attempting to establish a

relationship of deterrence. Very briefly, this theme looks at the way

states formulate their perceptions of the costs and benefits that are

involved in establishing a relationship of nuclear deterrence, be they

defender or initiator. The empirical literature suggests that there

exist two factors that influence state rationality when they deal with

nuclear deterrence relationships, and these are either (i) a state's

interest in something; or (ii) a state's commitment with respect to

something. What is important about these two factors is that they are

measures of costs and benefits that states self-impose upon themselves.

This is of course against the grain when it comes to the precepts of

rational deterrence theory, which, again, returning to the matter of

preference exogeneity, says that states consider all options equally and

without bias.

III - Conclusion

================

This paper has made a very brief effort at outlining the operation of

rational deterrence theory, one of the many bases that exist for

substantiating nuclear deterrence theories, and in turn relating

rational deterrence theory to the criticisms that have been made of it

in empirical literature. The paper's attention has chiefly been

concerned with Robert Jervis's summary of the empirical work that has

been done on rational deterrence theory.

3 923.

Bibliography

Achen, CH & Snidal, D 1989, 'Rational Deterrence Theory and Comparative

Case Studies', World Politics, vol 41, no. 2, pp. 143-169.

Jervis, R 1979, 'Deterrence Theory Revisited', World Politics, vol 31,

no. 2, pp. 289-324.

Jervis, R 1982, 'Deterrence and Perception', International Security, vol

7, no. 3, pp. 3-30.

Jervis, R 1989, 'Rational Deterrence: Theory and Evidence', World

Politics, vol 41, no. 2, pp. 183-207.

MccGwire, M 1986, 'Deterrence: the problem--not the solution',

International Affairs, pp. 55-70.

MccGwire, M 1994, 'Is There a Future for Nuclear Weapons?',

International Affairs, vol 70, no. 2, pp. 211-228.

MccGwire, M 2006, 'Appendix 2: Nuclear deterrence', International

Affairs, vol 82, no. 4, pp. 771-784.

Ritchie, N 2009, 'Deterrence dogma? Challenging the relevance of British

nuclear weapons', International Affairs, vol 85, no. 1, pp. 81-98.